|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Metaphysics & ontology
What is the relation between time and change? Does time depend on
the mind? Is the present always the same or is it always different?
Aristotle tackles these questions in the Physics, and Time for
Aristotle is the first book in English devoted to this discussion.
Aristotle claims that time is not a kind of change, but that it is
something dependent on change; he defines it as a kind of 'number
of change'. Ursula Coope argues that what this means is that time
is a kind of order (not, as is commonly supposed, a kind of
measure). It is universal order within which all changes are
related to each other. This interpretation enables Coope to explain
two puzzling claims that Aristotle makes: that the now is like a
moving thing, and that time depends for its existence on the mind.
Brilliantly lucid in its explanation of this challenging section of
the Physics, Time for Aristotle shows his discussion to be of
enduring philosophical interest.
This volume investigates what is beyond the Principle of
Non-Contradiction. It features 14 papers on the foundations of
reasoning, including logical systems and philosophical
considerations. Coverage brings together a cluster of issues
centered upon the variety of meanings of consistency,
contradiction, and related notions. Most of the papers, but not
all, are developed around the subtle distinctions between
consistency and non-contradiction, as well as among contradiction,
inconsistency, and triviality, and concern one of the above
mentioned threads of the broadly understood non-contradiction
principle and the related principle of explosion. Some others take
a perspective that is not too far away from such themes, but with
the freedom to tread new paths. Readers should understand the title
of this book in a broad way,because it is not so obvious to deal
with notions like contradictions, consistency, inconsistency, and
triviality. The papers collected here present groundbreaking ideas
related to consistency and inconsistency.
Antirealist views about morality claim that moral facts or truths
do not exist. Does this imply that other types of normative facts,
such as epistemic facts, do not exist? The Normative Web develops a
positive answer to this question. Terence Cuneo argues that moral
and epistemic facts are sufficiently similar so that, if moral
facts do not exist, then epistemic facts do not exist. But
epistemic facts do exist: to deny their existence would commit us
to an extreme version of epistemological scepticism. Therefore,
Cuneo concludes, moral facts do exist. And if moral facts exist,
then moral realism is true.
It is sometimes said that moral realists rarely offer arguments
for their position, settling instead for mere defenses of a view
they find intuitively plausible. By contrast, The Normative Web
provides not merely a defense of robust realism in ethics, but a
positive argument for this position. In so doing, it engages with a
range of antirealist positions in epistemology such as error
theories, expressivist views, and reductionist views of epistemic
reasons. These positions, Cuneo claims, come at a prohibitively
high theoretical cost. Given this cost, it follows that realism
about both epistemic and moral facts is a position that we should
find highly attractive.
Kant's Elliptical Path explores the main stages and key concepts in
the development of Kant's Critical philosophy, from the early 1760s
to the 1790s. Karl Ameriks provides a detailed and concise account
of the main ways in which the later Critical works provide a
plausible defence of the conception of humanity's fundamental end
that Kant turned to after reading Rousseau in the 1760s. Separate
essays are devoted to each of the three Critiques, as well as to
earlier notes and lectures and several of Kant's later writings on
history and religion. A final section devotes three chapters to
post-Kantian developments in German Romanticism, accounts of
tragedy up through Nietzsche, and contemporary philosophy. The
theme of an elliptical path is shown to be relevant to these
writers as well as to many aspects of Kant's own life and
work.
The topics of the book include fundamental issues in epistemology
and metaphysics, with a new defense of the Amerik's 'moderate'
interpretation of transcendental idealism. Other essays evaluate
Kant's concept of will and reliance on a 'fact of reason' in his
practical philosophy, as well as his critique of traditional
theodicies, and the historical character of his defense of religion
and the concepts of creation and hope within 'the boundaries of
mere reason'. Kant's Elliptical Path will be of value to historians
of modern philosophy and Kant scholars, while its treatment of
several literary figures and issues in aesthetics, politics,
history, and theology make it relevant to readers outside of
philosophy.
Aesthetic Transcendentalism is a philosophy endorsing the
qualitative and creative aspects of nature. Theoretically it argues
for a metaphysical dimension of nature that is aesthetically real,
pluralistic, and prolific. It directs our attention to the rich
complexity of immediate experience, the possibility of discovering
new aesthetic features about the world, and the transformative
potential of art as an organic expression. This book presents the
philosophy in its relationship to its historical roots in the
philosophic and artistic traditions of nineteenth-century North
America. In this multidisciplinary study, Nicholas L. Guardiano
brings together a philosophic and literary figure in Ralph Waldo
Emerson, the scientifically minded philosopher Charles S. Peirce,
and the plastic arts in the form of American landscape painting.
Guardiano evaluates this constellation of philosophers and artists
in global perspective as it relates to other historical theories of
metaphysics and aesthetics, while simultaneously performing a
cultural analysis that identifies an essential feature of the
American mind. Aesthetic Transcendentalism thus possesses abiding
significance for our vital interactions with nature, daily
experiences, and contemplations of great works of art. Aesthetic
Transcendentalism in Emerson, Peirce, and Nineteenth-Century
American Landscape Painting will be of interest to scholars of
American philosophy and American art history, especially
specialists of Charles S. Peirce, Ralph Waldo Emerson, and the
Hudson River School painters. It will also appeal to philosophers
working on systematic metaphysical theories of nature.
This book presents a set theoretical approach to sociological
research. It revisits existing sociological approaches and
discusses their limitations, before suggesting an alternative.
While the existing canonical approaches of Positivism,
Conflictualism, and Pragmatism are based on biology, history, and
physics, respectively, the set theoretical approach is based on
mathematics. Utilising its philosophical exploration delineated by
Alain Badiou, the book further translates his work into the field
of social science. The result of this translation is termed
Multiplitism, which evades the limiting contradictions of existing
approaches. Drawing on the mathematical notion of 'set' and
relating it to recent sociological turns such as the relational and
the ontological, the book proposes a scale-relativity through which
the researcher (as subject) and the researched (as object) are
integrated. The book will be of interest to social scientists,
particularly social theorists and advanced level students.
"Time: A Philosophical Introduction" presents the philosophy of
time as the central debate between being and the becoming.This core
theme brings together the key topics, debates and thinkers, making
ideas such as Zeno's paradoxes, the experience of change and
temporal flow and the direction and shape of time and time travel,
clear and understandable. Alongside a glossary and detailed
timeline to further enhance study and understanding, each chapter
features: - Extensive lists of further reading in both primary and
secondary sources- A chronological listing of key figures, brief
biographical data and references- True/false questions, matching,
multiple choice, and short answer questionsTime is a central
philosophical subject, impacting on all many different aspects of
philosophy. More technical discussions of issues from mathematics,
logic and physics are separated into Technical Interludes, allowing
readers to choose their level of difficultly. As a result this
comprehensive introduction is essential reading for upper-level
undergraduates studying the philosophy of time, metaphysics or the
philosophy of science.
Your Greater Self or The Inner Consciousness, written by William
Walker Atkinson in 1908, is yet another title in his repertoire
pertaining to greater or higher thought. In this case, the book
centers on the idea that there are higher levels of consciousness
and meaning that we can become in tune with through meditation and
concentration. Atkinson starts by describing the different centers
of the mind-such as the basement and the storehouse-and uses
imagery to help his readers understand how to reach their inner
consciousness and use it to its full potential.American writer
WILLIAM WALKER ATKINSON (1862-1932) was editor of the popular
magazine New Thought from 1901 to 1905 and editor of the journal
Advanced Thought from 1916 to 1919. He authored dozens of New
Thought books under numerous pseudonyms, including the name "Yogi,"
some of which are likely still unknown today.
As Vyasa, scribe of the epic Mahabarata, said,
The title of this work may seem to beg an important question, since
it rests on the assumption that Diderot has a 'concept of physical
energy'. Indeed the aim of the study is, in part, to assemble
evidence in support of the acte de foi implicit in its title. I am
using 'physical energy' in a loose sense, as a convenient term to
denote 'what matter can do' as distinct from 'what matter is made
of'. Hence it may be taken as broadly synonymous with 'power' or
'force', encompassing both active and potential forms, and thus
corresponding to a combination of the fourth and fifth senses
identified by the Oxford English Dictionary: 4. Power actively and
efficiently displayed or exerted. 5. Power not necessarily
manifested in action; ability or capacity to produce an effect.
Modern subatomic physics, of course, recognises no such distinction
between 'being' and 'doing'; at a fundamental level,
matter-as-substance and matter-as-energy are interchangeable (and,
as I shall argue towards the end of the study, Diderot himself
comes close to a similar position). Nevertheless, the division is
both justifiable and useful within the context of
eighteenth-century philosophies of nature. For, as many scholars
have pointed out, the trend towards nature as an integrated, active
phenomenon, in place of the cartesian view of passive etendue only
incidentally endowed with motion, was crucial to the development of
scientific thought in the mid-eighteenth century. Debate and
development on such issues as Newtonian attraction, inertia,
electricity and magnetism, chemical reactions, not only contributed
directly to the advancement of physics and chemistry, but also
(like cartesian mechanism) impinged upon the perennial biological
questions, themselves being investigated from a new and exciting
angle. As a philosopher rather than a practising scientist, Diderot
was ideally placed to draw freely and creatively on all these
areas, and his speculations on what we might call 'the nature of
nature' are highly characteristic of the new approach. He comes
increasingly to discuss and define natural phenomena (organic and
inorganic alike) from the point of view of nature's powers - in the
spirit of Renaissance naturalism, but from the perspective of
up-to-date scientific findings. It is in this sense that I refer to
a 'concept of physical energy'. Given the organic quality of
Diderot's thought, it is not surprising to find the idea of energy
recurring in other areas of his works. If man is composed of matter
- active matter - than all human activity, be it moral, political,
aesthetic, becomes capable of interpretation in terms of energy. I
share Chouillet's conviction that this is a crucial aspect of
Diderot's overall philosophy, which deserves to be more widely
recognised and more fully understood.
James Connelly and Giuseppina D'Oro present a revised edition of R.
G. Collingwood's classic work of 1933, supplementing the original
text with important related writings from Collingwood's manuscripts
which appear here for the first time. The editors also contribute a
substantial new introduction, and the volume will be welcomed by
all historians of twentieth-century philosophy.
This is an important new monograph on Plato's metaphysics, focusing
on the theory of the forms, which is the central philosophical
concept in Plato's theory.Few philosophical doctrines have been as
influential and as widely discussed as Plato's theory of Forms; yet
few have been as misunderstood. Most philosophers, following the
recommendation of Aristotle, regard the Forms as abstract entities.
However, this view is difficult to square with other aspects of
Plato's thought, in particular his theory of knowledge.Francis A.
Grabowski aims to dissociate the theory of Forms from its
Aristotelian reception, by interpreting it within the larger
framework of Plato's philosophy. Grabowski notes that the theory
emerged largely from epistemological concerns. He shows that the
ancients conceived of knowledge almost exclusively as a
perception-like acquaintance with things. He goes on to examine
Plato's epistemology and shows that Plato also regards knowledge as
the mind being directly acquainted with its object. Grabowski
argues that, by modelling knowledge on perception, Plato could not
have conceived of the Forms as Aristotle and others have claimed.
He concludes that an interpretation of the Forms as concrete rather
than abstract entities provides a more plausible and coherent view
of Plato's overall philosophical project.
How are causal judgements such as 'The ice on the road caused the
traffic accident' connected with counterfactual judgements such as
'If there had not been any ice on the road, the traffic accident
would not have happened'? This volume throws new light on this
question by uniting, for the first time, psychological and
philosophical approaches to causation and counterfactuals.
Traditionally, philosophers have primarily been interested in
connections between causal and counterfactual claims on the level
of meaning or truth-conditions. More recently, however, they have
also increasingly turned their attention to psychological
connections between causal and counterfactual understanding or
reasoning. At the same time, there has been a surge in interest in
empirical work on causal and counterfactual cognition amongst
developmental, cognitive, and social psychologists--much of it
inspired by work in philosophy. In this volume, twelve original
contributions from leading philosophers and psychologists explore
in detail what bearing empirical findings might have on
philosophical concerns about counterfactuals and causation, and
how, in turn, work in philosophy might help clarify the issues at
stake in empirical work on the cognitive underpinnings of, and
relationships between, causal and counterfactual thought.
The Intimate Resistance is a keen, deeply beautiful reflection on
the human condition. The author explains how we ourselves can warm,
protect and guide those around us. "The intimate resistance is the
name for an experience belonging to a state of proximity; a state
cannot be visited in one day, but rather habitually. Today, to
remain in this state is by no means simple. Proximity cannot be
measured in metres or centimetres. Its opposite is not distance,
but rather the ubiquitous monotony of a world dominated by
technology. What is clear is that day to day and home life are
essential ways of experiencing proximity."
Humanness supposes innate and profound reflexivity. This volume
approaches the concept of reflexivity on two different yet related
analytical planes. Whether implicitly or explicitly, both planes of
thought bear critically on reflexivity in relation to the nature of
selfhood and the very idea of the autonomous individual, ethics,
and humanness, science as such and social science, ontological
dualism and fundamental ambiguity. On the one plane, a collection
of original and innovative ethnographically based essays is
offered, each of which is devoted to ways in which reflexivity
plays a fundamental role in human social life and the study of it;
on the other-anthropo-philosophical and developed in the volume's
Preface, Introduction, and Postscript-it is argued that reflexivity
distinguishes-definitively, albeit relatively-the being and
becoming of the human.
Many of the earliest books, particularly those dating back to the
1900s and before, are now extremely scarce and increasingly
expensive. Pomona Press are republishing these classic works in
affordable, high quality, modern editions, using the original text
and artwork.
This book discusses the influence of creative work on human life,
and the role it has played in shaping human civilization since
antiquity. To do so, it analyzes the history of thought on creative
work from three civilizations: Greek, Indian, and Chinese, as well
as contemporary neurological studies on consciousness. According to
the classical Greeks, humans are instinctively predisposed to use
creative work to gain truth, wisdom and happiness; the Indians
consider that Dharma (duty, morality, etc.) can be achieved only
through work (karma); and for the Chinese, creative work is needed
to attain the supreme wisdom (Dao). Modern studies on consciousness
show that our brain creates a personal self-model (ego tunnel) when
we learn things creatively, and developing such skills provides
lifelong protection for the brain. In the 21st century, human
involvement in creative work is declining as we use mechanized
systems to gain more and more profit, but the wealth falls into the
hands of the few superrich: the Plutonomy. As creative work is
taken over by AI systems, human work is reduced to operating those
machines, and this in turn leads to an exponential growth in the
number of part-time workers (Precariat). The declining value of
human life today is a consequence of this change in society.
Further, reducing creative work means we have no way to distribute
wealth, nor do we have any means to address problems like the lack
of enthusiasm in the young; the health crisis due to lack of
physical activity; or the environmental crisis due to the high
demand for energy to run mechanized systems. This book explores
these issues.
Many of the earliest books, particularly those dating back to the
1900s and before, are now extremely scarce and increasingly
expensive. We are republishing these classic works in affordable,
high quality, modern editions, using the original text and artwork.
This book is about our ordinary concept of matter in the form of
enduring continuants and the processes in which they are involved
in the macroscopic realm. It emphasises what science rather than
philosophical intuition tells us about the world, and chemistry
rather than the physics that is more usually encountered in
philosophical discussions. The central chapters dealing with the
nature of matter pursue key steps in the historical development of
scientific conceptions of chemical substance. Like many
contemporary discussions of material objects, it relies heavily on
mereology. The classical principles are applied to the mereological
structure of regions of space, intervals of time, processes and
quantities of matter. Quantities of matter, which don't gain or
lose parts over time, are distinguished from individuals, which are
typically constituted of different quantities of matter at
different times. The proper treatment of the temporal aspect of the
features of material objects is a central issue in this book, which
is addressed by investigating the conditions governing the
application of predicates relating time and other entities. Of
particular interest here are relations between quantities of matter
and times expressing substance kind, phase and mixture. Modal
aspects of these features are taken up in the final chapter.
The issues of the nature and existence of God, time and infinity,
respectively, and how they relate to each other, are some of the
most complicated problems of metaphysics.This volume presents
contributions of thirteen internationally renowned scholars who
deal with various aspects of these complex issues. The
contributions were presented and discussed during the international
conference: God, Time, Infinity held in Warsaw, September 22-24,
2015.
|
You may like...
Truth and Realism
Patrick Greenough, Michael P Lynch
Hardcover
R3,863
Discovery Miles 38 630
|