|
Showing 1 - 9 of
9 matches in All Departments
Along with many small improvements, this revised edition contains
van Yzeren's new proof of Pascal's theorem (1.7) and, in Chapter 2,
an improved treatment of order and sense. The Sylvester-Gallai
theorem, instead of being introduced as a curiosity, is now used as
an essential step in the theory of harmonic separation (3.34). This
makes the logi cal development self-contained: the footnotes
involving the References (pp. 214-216) are for comparison with
earlier treatments, and to give credit where it is due, not to fill
gaps in the argument. H.S.M.C. November 1992 v Preface to the
Second Edition Why should one study the real plane? To this
question, put by those who advocate the complex plane, or geometry
over a general field, I would reply that the real plane is an easy
first step. Most of the prop erties are closely analogous, and the
real field has the advantage of intuitive accessibility. Moreover,
real geometry is exactly what is needed for the projective approach
to non* Euclidean geometry. Instead of introducing the affine and
Euclidean metrics as in Chapters 8 and 9, we could just as well
take the locus of 'points at infinity' to be a conic, or replace
the absolute involution by an absolute polarity.
Along with many small improvements, this revised edition contains
van Yzeren's new proof of Pascal's theorem (1.7) and, in Chapter 2,
an improved treatment of order and sense. The Sylvester-Gallai
theorem, instead of being introduced as a curiosity, is now used as
an essential step in the theory of harmonic separation (3.34). This
makes the logi cal development self-contained: the footnotes
involving the References (pp. 214-216) are for comparison with
earlier treatments, and to give credit where it is due, not to fill
gaps in the argument. H.S.M.C. November 1992 v Preface to the
Second Edition Why should one study the real plane? To this
question, put by those who advocate the complex plane, or geometry
over a general field, I would reply that the real plane is an easy
first step. Most of the prop erties are closely analogous, and the
real field has the advantage of intuitive accessibility. Moreover,
real geometry is exactly what is needed for the projective approach
to non-Euclidean geometry. Instead of introducing the affine and
Euclidean metrics as in Chapters 8 and 9, we could just as well
take the locus of 'points at infinity' to be a conic, or replace
the absolute involution by an absolute polarity.
Along with many small improvements, this revised edition contains
van Yzeren's new proof of Pascal's theorem ( 1.7) and, in Chapter
2, an improved treatment of order and sense. The Sylvester-Gallai
theorem, instead of being introduced as a curiosity, is now used as
an essential step in the theory of harmonic separation ( 3.34).
This makes the logi cal development self-contained: the footnotes
involving the References (pp. 214-216) are for comparison with
earlier treatments, and to give credit where it is due, not to fill
gaps in the argument. H.S.M.C. November 1992 v Preface to the
Second Edition Why should one study the real plane? To this
question, put by those who advocate the complex plane, or geometry
over a general field, I would reply that the real plane is an easy
first step. Most of the prop erties are closely analogous, and the
real field has the advantage of intuitive accessibility. Moreover,
real geometry is exactly what is needed for the projective approach
to non. Euclidean geometry. Instead of introducing the affine and
Euclidean metrics as in Chapters 8 and 9, we could just as well
take the locus of 'points at infinity' to be a conic, or replace
the absolute involution by an absolute polarity."
In Euclidean geometry, constructions are made with ruler and compass. Projective geometry is simpler: its constructions require only a ruler. In projective geometry one never measures anything, instead, one relates one set of points to another by a projectivity. The first two chapters of this book introduce the important concepts of the subject and provide the logical foundations. The third and fourth chapters introduce the famous theorems of Desargues and Pappus. Chapters 5 and 6 make use of projectivities on a line and plane, repectively. The next three chapters develop a self-contained account of von Staudt's approach to the theory of conics. The modern approach used in that development is exploited in Chapter 10, which deals with the simplest finite geometry that is rich enough to illustrate all the theorems nontrivially. The concluding chapters show the connections among projective, Euclidean, and analytic geometry.
The Fifty-Nine Icosahedra was originally published in 1938 as No. 6
of "University of Toronto Studies (Mathematical Series)." Of the
four authors, only Coxeter and myself are still alive, and we two
are the authors of the whole text of the book, in which any signs
of immaturity may perhaps be regarded leniently on noting that both
of us were still in our twenties when it was written. N either of
the others was a professional mathematician. Flather died about
1950, and Petrie, tragically, in a road accident in 1972. Petrie's
part in the book consisted in the extremely difficult drawings
which consti tute the left half of each of the plates (the much
simpler ones on the right being mine). A brief biographical note on
Petrie will be found on p. 32 of Coxeter's Regular Polytopes (3rd.
ed., Dover, New York, 1973); and it may be added that he was still
a schoolboy when he discovered the regular skew polygons that are
named after him, and are the occasion for the note on him in
Coxeter's book. (Coxeter also was a schoolboy when some of the
results for which he will be most remembered were obtained; he and
Petrie were schoolboy friends and used to work together on
polyhedron and polytope theory. ) Flather's part in the book
consisted in making a very beautiful set of miniature models of all
the fifty-nine figures. These are still in existence, and in
excellent preservation."
This classic work is now available in an unabridged paperback edition. The Second Edition retains all the characterisitcs that made the first edition so popular: brilliant exposition, the flexibility permitted by relatively self-contained chapters, and broad coverage ranging from topics in the Euclidean plane, to affine geometry, projective geometry, differential geometry, and topology. The Second Edition incorporates improvements in the text and in some proofs, takes note of the solution of the 4-color map problem, and provides answers to most of the exercises.
The name non-Euclidean was used by Gauss to describe a system of
geometry which differs from Euclid's in its properties of
parallelism. Such a system was developed independently by Bolyai in
Hungary and Lobatschewsky in Russia, about 120 years ago. Another
system, differing more radically from Euclid's, was suggested later
by Riemann in Germany and Cayley in England. The subject was
unified in 1871 by Klein, who gave the names of parabolic,
hyperbolic, and elliptic to the respective systems of
Euclid-Bolyai-Lobatschewsky, and Riemann-Cayley. Since then, a vast
literature has accumulated. The Fifth edition adds a new chapter,
which includes a description of the two families of 'mid-lines'
between two given lines, an elementary derivation of the basic
formulae of spherical trigonometry and hyperbolic trigonometry, a
computation of the Gaussian curvature of the elliptic and
hyperbolic planes, and a proof of Schlafli's remarkable formula for
the differential of the volume of a tetrahedron.
Foremost book available on polytopes, incorporating ancient Greek and most modern work done on them. Beginning with polygons and polyhedrons, the book moves on to multi-dimensional polytopes in a way that anyone with a basic knowledge of geometry and trigonometry can easily understand. Definitions of symbols. Eight tables plus many diagrams and examples.1963 ed.
|
You may like...
Loot
Nadine Gordimer
Paperback
(2)
R383
R310
Discovery Miles 3 100
|