|
Showing 1 - 7 of
7 matches in All Departments
The book shows that civil disobedience is generally more defensible
than private conscientious objection. Part I explores the morality
of conviction and conscience. Each of these concepts informs a
distinct argument for civil disobedience. The conviction argument
begins with the communicative principle of conscientiousness (CPC).
According to the CPC, having a conscientious moral conviction means
not just acting consistently with our beliefs and judging ourselves
and others by a common moral standard. It also means not seeking to
evade the consequences of our beliefs and being willing to
communicate them to others. The conviction argument shows that, as
a constrained, communicative practice, civil disobedience has a
better claim than private objection does to the protections that
liberal societies give to conscientious dissent. This view reverses
the standard liberal picture which sees private 'conscientious'
objection as a modest act of personal belief and civil disobedience
as a strategic, undemocratic act whose costs are only sometimes
worth bearing. The conscience argument is narrower and shows that
genuinely morally responsive civil disobedience honours the best of
our moral responsibilities and is protected by a duty-based moral
right of conscience. Part II translates the conviction argument and
conscience argument into two legal defences. The first is a
demands-of-conviction defence. The second is a necessity defence.
Both of these defences apply more readily to civil disobedience
than to private disobedience. Part II also examines lawful
punishment, showing that, even when punishment is justifiable,
civil disobedients have a moral right not to be punished. Oxford
Legal Philosophy publishes the best new work in
philosophically-oriented legal theory. It commissions and solicits
monographs in all branches of the subject, including works on
philosophical issues in all areas of public and private law, and in
the national, transnational, and international realms; studies of
the nature of law, legal institutions, and legal reasoning;
treatments of problems in political morality as they bear on law;
and explorations in the nature and development of legal philosophy
itself. The series represents diverse traditions of thought but
always with an emphasis on rigour and originality. It sets the
standard in contemporary jurisprudence.
This book offers a much-needed investigation of moral and political
issues concerning disability, and explores how the experiences of
people with disabilities can lead to reconsideration of prominent
positions on normative issues. Thirteen new essays examine such
topics as the concept of disability, the conditions of justice, the
nature of autonomy, healthcare distribution, and reproductive
choices. The contributors are Norman Daniels, Ellen Daniels Zide,
Leslie P. Francis, Christie Hartley, Richard Hull, Guy Kahane, F.
M. Kamm, Rosalind McDougall, Jeff McMahan, Douglas MacLean,
Susannah Rose, Anita Silvers, Julian Savulescu, Lorella Terzi,
David Wasserman, and Jonathan Wolff.
Oxford Legal Philosophy publishes the best new work in
philosophically-oriented legal theory. It commissions and solicits
monographs in all branches of the subject, including works on
philosophical issues in all areas of public and private law, and in
the national, transnational, and international realms; studies of
the nature of law, legal institutions, and legal reasoning;
treatments of problems in political morality as they bear on law;
and explorations in the nature and development of legal philosophy
itself. The series represents diverse traditions of thought but
always with an emphasis on rigour and originality. It sets the
standard in contemporary jurisprudence. This book shows that civil
disobedience is generally more defensible than private
conscientious objection. Part I explores the morality of conviction
and conscience. Each of these concepts informs a distinct argument
for civil disobedience. The conviction argument begins with the
communicative principle of conscientiousness (CPC). According to
the CPC, having a conscientious moral conviction means not just
acting consistently with our beliefs and judging ourselves and
others by a common moral standard. It also means not seeking to
evade the consequences of our beliefs and being willing to
communicate them to others. The conviction argument shows that, as
a constrained, communicative practice, civil disobedience has a
better claim than private objection does to the protections that
liberal societies give to conscientious dissent. This view reverses
the standard liberal picture which sees private 'conscientious'
objection as a modest act of personal belief and civil disobedience
as a strategic, undemocratic act whose costs are only sometimes
worth bearing. The conscience argument is narrower and shows that
genuinely morally responsive civil disobedience honours the best of
our moral responsibilities and is protected by a duty-based moral
right of conscience. Part II translates the conviction argument and
conscience argument into two legal defences. The first is a
demands-of-conviction defence. The second is a necessity defence.
Both of these defences apply more readily to civil disobedience
than to private disobedience. Part II also examines lawful
punishment, showing that, even when punishment is justifiable,
civil disobedients have a moral right not to be punished.
We are deeply social creatures. Our core social needs-for
meaningful social inclusion-are more important than our civil and
political needs and our economic welfare needs, and we won't secure
those other things if our core social needs go unmet. Our core
social needs ground a human right against social deprivation as
well as a human right to have the resources to sustain other
people. Kimberley Brownlee defends this fundamental but largely
neglected human right; having defined social deprivation as a
persistent lack of minimally adequate access to decent human
contact, she then discusses situations such as solitary confinement
and incidental isolation. Fleshing out what it means to belong,
Brownlee considers why loneliness and weak social connections are
not just moral tragedies, but often injustices, and argues that we
endure social contribution injustice when we are denied the means
to sustain others. Our core social needs can clash with our
interests in interactive and associative freedom, and when they do,
social needs take priority. We have a duty to ensure that everyone
has the opportunity to satisfy their social needs. As Brownlee
asserts, we violate this duty if we classify some people as
inescapably socially threatening, either through using reductive,
essentialist language that reduces people to certain acts or
traits-'criminal', 'rapist', 'paedophile', 'foreigner'-or in the
ways we physically segregate such people and fail to help people to
reintegrate after segregation.
This book offers a much-needed investigation of moral and political
issues concerning disability, and explores how the experiences of
people with disabilities can lead to reconsideration of prominent
positions on normative issues. Thirteen new essays examine such
topics as the concept of disability, the conditions of justice, the
nature of autonomy, healthcare distribution, and reproductive
choices. The contributors are Norman Daniels, Ellen Daniels Zide,
Leslie P. Francis, Christie Hartley, Richard Hull, Guy Kahane, F.
M. Kamm, Rosalind McDougall, Jeff McMahan, Douglas MacLean,
Susannah Rose, Anita Silvers, Julian Savulescu, Lorella Terzi,
David Wasserman, and Jonathan Wolff.
We are deeply social creatures. Our core social needs - for
meaningful social inclusion - are more important than our civil and
political needs and our economic welfare needs, and we won't secure
those other things if our core social needs go unmet. Our core
social needs ground a human right against social deprivation as
well as a human right to have the resources to sustain other
people. Kimberley Brownlee defends this fundamental but largely
neglected human right; having defined social deprivation as a
persistent lack of minimally adequate access to decent human
contact, she then discusses situations such as solitary confinement
and incidental isolation. Fleshing out what it means tothers. Our
core social needs can clash with oo belong, Brownlee considers why
loneliness and weak social connections are not just moral
tragedies, but often injustices, and argues that we endure social
contribution injustice when we are denied the means to sustain ur
interests in interactive and associative freedom, and when they do,
social needs take priority. We have a duty to ensure that everyone
has the opportunity to satisfy their social needs. As Brownlee
asserts, we violate this duty if we classify some people as
inescapably socially threatening, either through using reductive,
essentialist language that reduces people to certain acts or traits
- 'criminal', 'rapist', 'paedophile', 'foreigner' - or in the ways
we physically segregate such people and fail to help people to
reintegrate after segregation.
Human rights capture what people need to live minimally decent
lives. Recognised dimensions of this minimum include physical
security, due process, political participation, and freedom of
movement, speech, and belief, as well as - more controversially for
some - subsistence, shelter, health, education, culture, and
community. Far less attention has been paid to the interpersonal,
social dimensions of a minimally decent life, including our basic
needs for decent human contact and acknowledgement, for interaction
and adequate social inclusion, and for relationship, intimacy, and
shared ways of living, as well as our competing interests in
solitude and associative freedom. This pioneering collection of
original essays aims to remedy the neglect of social needs and
rights in human rights theory and practice by exploring the social
dimensions of the human-rights minimum. The essays subject
enumerated social human rights and proposed social human rights to
philosophical scrutiny, and probe the conceptual, normative, and
practical implications of taking social human rights seriously. The
contributors to this volume demonstrate powerfully how important
this undertaking is, despite the thorny theoretical and practical
challenges that social rights present. Being Social is the first
in-depth and polyphonic philosophical treatment of social rights
qua human rights in the English language. It explains how social
rights are rights to participate and not only to being in society,
but also, even more importantly, it uncovers the social and
interactional dimension of all human rights. A must-read for
international human rights lawyers concerned about the critique of
human rights' individualism.' - Professor Samantha Besson,
International Law of Institutions Chair, College de France, Paris
& Professor of Public International Law and European Law,
University of Fribourg, Switzerland 'Every human being has deep
needs for sociality: for contact, connection, intimacy, inclusion,
recognition, and community. In this pioneering volume, leading
experts explore how social human rights can help fulfil these needs
in our homes, workplaces, cities, nations, and virtual worlds.
Since a human life is a life with others, human rights must include
social rights too.' - Leif Wenar, Olive H. Palmer Professor in
Humanities, Stanford University
|
You may like...
Loot
Nadine Gordimer
Paperback
(2)
R391
R362
Discovery Miles 3 620
|