|
Showing 1 - 5 of
5 matches in All Departments
There is a mystery at the heart of Plato's Parmenides. In the first
part, Parmenides criticizes what is widely regarded as Plato's
mature theory of Forms, and in the second, he promises to explain
how the Forms can be saved from these criticisms. Ever since the
dialogue was written, scholars have struggled to determine how the
two parts of the work fit together. Did Plato mean us to abandon,
keep, or modify the theory of Forms, on the strength of Parmenides'
criticisms? Samuel Rickless offers something that has never been
done before: a careful reconstruction of every argument in the
dialogue. He concludes that Plato's main aim was to argue that the
theory of Forms should be modified by allowing that forms can have
contrary properties. To grasp this is to solve the mystery of the
Parmenides and understand its crucial role in Plato's philosophical
development.
Samuel C. Rickless presents a novel interpretation of the thought
of George Berkeley. In A Treatise Concerning the Principles of
Human Knowledge (1710) and Three Dialogues Between Hylas and
Philonous (1713), Berkeley argues for the astonishing view that
physical objects (such as tables and chairs) are nothing but
collections of ideas (idealism); that there is no such thing as
material substance (immaterialism); that abstract ideas are
impossible (anti-abstractionism); and that an idea can be like
nothing but an idea (the likeness principle). It is a matter of
great controversy what Berkeley's argument for idealism is and
whether it succeeds. Most scholars believe that the argument is
based on immaterialism, anti-abstractionism, or the likeness
principle. In Berkeley's Argument for Idealism, Rickless argues
that Berkeley distinguishes between two kinds of abstraction,
'singling' abstraction and 'generalizing' abstraction; that his
argument for idealism depends on the impossibility of singling
abstraction but not on the impossibility of generalizing
abstraction; and that the argument depends neither on immaterialism
nor the likeness principle. According to Rickless, the heart of the
argument for idealism rests on the distinction between mediate and
immediate perception, and in particular on the thesis that
everything that is perceived by means of the senses is immediately
perceived. After analyzing the argument, Rickless concludes that it
is valid and may well be sound. This is Berkeley's most enduring
philosophical legacy.
There is a mystery at the heart of Plato's Parmenides. In the first
part, Parmenides criticizes what is widely regarded as Plato's
mature theory of Forms, and in the second, he promises to explain
how the Forms can be saved from these criticisms. Ever since the
dialogue was written, scholars have struggled to determine how the
two parts of the work fit together. Did Plato mean us to abandon,
keep or modify the theory of Forms, on the strength of Parmenides'
criticisms? Samuel Rickless offers something that has never been
done before: a careful reconstruction of every argument in the
dialogue. He concludes that Plato's main aim was to argue that the
theory of Forms should be modified by allowing that forms can have
contrary properties. To grasp this is to solve the mystery of the
Parmenides and understand its crucial role in Plato's philosophical
development.
Just War theory - as it was developed by the Catholic theologians
of medieval Europe and the jurists of the Renaissance - is a
framework for the moral and legal evaluation of armed conflicts. To
this day, Just War theory informs the judgments of ethicists,
government officials, international lawyers, religious scholars,
news coverage, and perhaps most importantly, the public as a whole.
The influence of Just War theory is as vast as it is subtle - we
have been socialized into evaluating wars largely according to the
principles of this medieval theory, which, according to the eminent
philosopher David Rodin, is "one of the few basic fixtures of
medieval philosophy to remain substantially unchallenged in the
modern world". Some of the most basic assumptions of Just War
Theory have been dismantled in a barrage of criticism and analysis
in the first dozen years of the 21st century. "The Ethics of War"
continues and pushes past this trend. This anthology is an
authoritative treatment of the ethics and law of war by both the
eminent scholars who first challenged the orthodoxy of Just War
theory, as well as by new thinkers. The twelve original essays span
both foundational and topical issues in the ethics of war,
including an investigation of: whether there is a "greater-good"
obligation that parallels the canonical lesser-evil justification
in war; the conditions under which citizens can wage war against
their own government; whether there is a limit to the number of
combatants on the unjust side who can be permissibly killed;
whether the justice of the cause for which combatants fight affects
the moral permissibility of fighting; whether duress ever justifies
killing in war; the role that collective liability plays in the
ethics of war; whether targeted killing is morally and legally
permissible; the morality of legal prohibitions on the use of
indiscriminate weapons; the justification for the legal distinction
between directly and indirectly harming civilians; whether human
rights of unjust combatants are more prohibitive than have been
thought; the moral repair of combatants suffering from PTSD; and
the moral categories and criteria needed to understand the proper
justification for ending war.
The Oxford Handbook of Berkeley is a compendious examination of a
vast array of topics in the philosophy of George Berkeley
(1685-1753), Anglican Bishop of Cloyne, the famous idealist and
most illustrious Irish philosopher. Berkeley is best known for his
denial of the existence of material substance and his insistence
that the only things that exist in the universe are minds
(including God) and their ideas; however, Berkeley was a polymath
who contributed to a variety of different disciplines, not well
distinguished from philosophy in the eighteenth century, including
the theory and psychology of vision, the nature and functioning of
language, the debate over infinitesimals in mathematics, political
philosophy, economics, chemistry (including his favoured panacea,
tar-water), and theology. This volume includes contributions from
thirty-four expert commentators on Berkeley's philosophy, some of
whom provide a state-of-the-art account of his philosophical
achievements, and some of whom place his philosophy in historical
context by comparing and contrasting it with the views of his
contemporaries (including Mandeville, Collier, and Edwards), as
well as with philosophers who preceded him (such as Descartes,
Locke, Malebranche, and Leibniz) and others who succeeded him (such
as Hume, Reid, Kant, and Shepherd).
|
You may like...
Loot
Nadine Gordimer
Paperback
(2)
R398
R369
Discovery Miles 3 690
|