|
Showing 1 - 16 of
16 matches in All Departments
First handbook on liberal naturalism Superb line up of
international contributors, many of whom are leading names in the
field Covers hot topics such as history of philosophical
naturalism, key figures from Aristotle to Quine and contemporary
issues such as ethical, metaphysical and epistemological naturalism
A collection of Hilary Putnam's stimulating, incisive responses to
such varied and eminent thinkers as Richard Rorty, Jurgen Habermas,
Noam Chomsky, Martha Nussbaum, W. V. Quine, Wilfrid Sellars, John
McDowell, and Cornel West. Hilary Putnam (1926-2016) was
renowned-some would say infamous-for changing his philosophical
positions over the course of his long and much-admired career. This
collection of essays, the first of its kind, showcases how his
ideas evolved as he wrestled with the work of his contemporaries.
Divided into five thematic sections, Philosophy as Dialogue begins
with questions of language and formal logic, tracing Putnam's
reactions to the arguments of Wilfrid Sellars, Noam Chomsky,
Charles Travis, and Tyler Burge. Next, it brings together Putnam's
responses to realists and antirealists, philosophers of science and
of perception, followed by forays into pragmatism and skepticism.
While Putnam devoted most of his efforts to logic, mathematics, and
the philosophy of mind, he also took up issues in moral philosophy,
politics, and religion. Here we read him in conversation with
giants of these fields, including Martha Nussbaum, Jurgen Habermas,
Elizabeth Anscombe, Cora Diamond, Richard Rorty, and Franz
Rosenzweig. Finally, Philosophy as Dialogue presents Putnam's
deeply personal and largely unknown writing on philosophical method
that reveals the influence of W. V. Quine, Michael Dummett, and
Stanley Cavell on his work. Once more, Mario De Caro and David
Macarthur have presented and introduced a choice selection of
Hilary Putnam's writings that will change the way he is understood.
Most of all, these thirty-six replies and responses to his
contemporaries showcase the extraordinary-perhaps even
unparalleled-breadth of his work, and his capacity to engage deeply
with seemingly every mode of philosophy.
Hilary Putnam's unceasing self-criticism has led to the frequent
changes of mind he is famous for, but his thinking is also marked
by considerable continuity. A simultaneous interest in science and
ethics-unusual in the current climate of contention-has long
characterized his thought. In Philosophy in an Age of Science,
Putnam collects his papers for publication-his first volume in
almost two decades. Mario De Caro and David Macarthur's
introduction identifies central themes to help the reader negotiate
between Putnam past and Putnam present: his critique of logical
positivism; his enduring aspiration to be realist about rational
normativity; his anti-essentialism about a range of central
philosophical notions; his reconciliation of the scientific
worldview and the humanistic tradition; and his movement from
reductive scientific naturalism to liberal naturalism. Putnam
returns here to some of his first enthusiasms in philosophy, such
as logic, mathematics, and quantum mechanics. The reader is given a
glimpse, too, of ideas currently in development on the subject of
perception. Putnam's work, contributing to a broad range of
philosophical inquiry, has been said to represent a "history of
recent philosophy in outline." Here it also delineates a possible
future.
Normativity concerns what we ought to think or do and the
evaluations we make. For example, we say that we ought to think
consistently, we ought to keep our promises, or that Mozart is a
better composer than Salieri. Yet what philosophical moral can we
draw from the apparent absence of normativity in the scientific
image of the world? For scientific naturalists, the moral is that
the normative must be reduced to the nonnormative, while for
nonnaturalists, the moral is that there must be a transcendent
realm of norms. Naturalism and Normativity engages with both sides
of this debate. Essays explore philosophical options for
understanding normativity in the space between scientific
naturalism and Platonic supernaturalism. They articulate a liberal
conception of philosophy that is neither reducible to the sciences
nor completely independent of them--yet one that maintains the
right to call itself naturalism. Contributors think in new ways
about the relations among the scientific worldview, our experience
of norms and values, and our movements in the space of reason.
Detailed discussions include the relationship between philosophy
and science, physicalism and ontological pluralism, the realm of
the ordinary, objectivity and subjectivity, truth and
justification, and the liberal naturalisms of Donald Davidson, John
Dewey, John McDowell, and Ludwig Wittgenstein.
Throughout his diverse and highly influential career, Hilary Putnam
was famous for changing his mind. As a pragmatist he treated
philosophical "positions" as experiments in deliberate living. His
aim was not to fix on one position but to attempt to do justice to
the depth and complexity of reality. In this new collection, he and
Ruth Anna Putnam argue that key elements of the classical
pragmatism of William James and John Dewey provide a framework for
the most progressive and forward-looking forms of philosophy in
contemporary thought. The Putnams present a compelling defense of
the radical originality of the philosophical ideas of James and
Dewey and their usefulness in confronting the urgent social,
political, and moral problems of the twenty-first century.
Pragmatism as a Way of Life brings together almost all of the
Putnams' pragmatist writings-essays they wrote as individuals and
as coauthors. The pragmatism they endorse, though respectful of the
sciences, is an open experience-based philosophy of our everyday
lives that trenchantly criticizes the fact/value dualism running
through contemporary culture. Hilary Putnam argues that all facts
are dependent on cognitive values, while Ruth Anna Putnam turns the
problem around, illuminating the factual basis of moral principles.
Together, they offer a shared vision which, in Hilary's words,
"could serve as a manifesto for what the two of us would like
philosophy to look like in the twenty-first century and beyond."
Normativity concerns what we ought to think or do and the
evaluations we make. For example, we say that we ought to think
consistently, we ought to keep our promises, or that Mozart is a
better composer than Salieri. Yet what philosophical moral can we
draw from the apparent absence of normativity in the scientific
image of the world? For scientific naturalists, the moral is that
the normative must be reduced to the nonnormative, while for
nonnaturalists, the moral is that there must be a transcendent
realm of norms.
"Naturalism and Normativity" engages with both sides of this
debate. Essays explore philosophical options for understanding
normativity in the space between scientific naturalism and Platonic
supernaturalism. They articulate a liberal conception of philosophy
that is neither reducible to the sciences nor completely
independent of them--yet one that maintains the right to call
itself naturalism. Contributors think in new ways about the
relations among the scientific worldview, our experience of norms
and values, and our movements in the space of reason. Detailed
discussions include the relationship between philosophy and
science, physicalism and ontological pluralism, the realm of the
ordinary, objectivity and subjectivity, truth and justification,
and the liberal naturalisms of Donald Davidson, John Dewey, John
McDowell, and Ludwig Wittgenstein.
Today the majority of philosophers in the English-speaking world
adhere to the "naturalist" credos that philosophy is continuous
with science, and that the natural sciences provide a complete
account of all that exists--whether human or nonhuman. The new
faith says science, not man, is the measure of all things. However,
there is a growing skepticism about the adequacy of this complacent
orthodoxy. This volume presents a group of leading thinkers who
criticize scientific naturalism not in the name of some form of
supernaturalism, but in order to defend a more inclusive or liberal
naturalism.
The many prominent Anglo-American philosophers appearing in
this book--Akeel Bilgrami, Stanley Cavell, Donald Davidson, John
Dupre, Jennifer Hornsby, Erin Kelly, John McDowell, Huw Price,
Hilary Putnam, Carol Rovane, Barry Stroud, and Stephen White--do
not march in lockstep, yet their contributions demonstrate mutual
affinities and various unifying themes. Instead of attempting to
force human nature into a restricted scientific image of the world,
these papers represent an attempt to place human nature at the
center of renewed--but still scientifically respectful--conceptions
of philosophy and nature.
|
You may like...
Loot
Nadine Gordimer
Paperback
(2)
R205
R168
Discovery Miles 1 680
|