|
Showing 1 - 18 of
18 matches in All Departments
Mary Warnock's Critical Reflections on Ownership is a sustained
meditation on the significance that ownership has for us from one
of our finest philosophical voices. First exploring the
responsibility and love we have for things that are owned, she goes
on to provide a penetrating investigation of the relationship we
have to those things which we do not, indeed cannot, own, in
particular the natural world. Critical Reflections on Ownership is
required reading for anyone who wants to think deeply, and clearly,
about the prospect of a global environmental cataclysm and what we
might do to address it.' - J.E. Penner, author of The Idea of
Property in LawIn this thought-provoking work, Mary Warnock
explores what it is to own things, and the differences in our
attitude to what we own and what we do not. Starting from the
philosophical standpoints of Locke and Hume, the ownership of
gardens is presented as a prime example, exploring both private and
common ownership, historically and autobiographically. The author
concludes that, besides pleasure and pride, ownership brings a
sense of responsibility for what is owned and a fundamental
question is brought to light: can we feel the same responsibility
for what we do not, and never can, own? Applying this question to
the natural world and the planet as a whole, a realistic and
gradualist perspective is offered on confronting global
environmental degradation. Critical Reflections on Ownership
examines the effect of the Romantic Movement on our attitudes to
nature and is a salient commentary on the history of ideas.
Providing an accessible entrance into moral philosophy and its
practical applications, this book is an invaluable source for
students in the fields of politics and philosophy. Academics
interested in conceptions of ownership, and in the interface
between philosophy, morality and politics, will find this deeply
considered insight to be a stimulating read.
This text was originally published in France, in 1940, under the
title of "L'Imaginaire". It was designed as an essay in
phenomenology and it constitutes an attempt to introduce Husserl's
work into French culture, and from there to the English speaking
world. Published three years before "Being and Nothingness", it
reveals Sartre's extended examination of such concepts as
nothingness and freedom, both derived here from the consciousness's
ability to imagine objects not only as they are but as they are
not, and to imagine objects not in existence. According to Sartre,
an object can be given to us in three ways: by perceiving it, by
having an idea of it, and by imagining it (having an image of it).
Although we may try to respond to the image in the same way as we
would to the object itself, the fact remains that an image, however
vivid, presents its object as not being.
This book, first published in 1965, is a critical exposition of the
philosophical doctrines of Jean-Paul Sartre. His contribution to
ethical and political theory, and to metaphysics and ontology, is
reviewed against the background of German idealism and
phenomenology, and his arguments are presented clearly so that
readers may assess their philosophical value in their own right.
Mary Warnock's Critical Reflections on Ownership is a sustained
meditation on the significance that ownership has for us from one
of our finest philosophical voices. First exploring the
responsibility and love we have for things that are owned, she goes
on to provide a penetrating investigation of the relationship we
have to those things which we do not, indeed cannot, own, in
particular the natural world. Critical Reflections on Ownership is
required reading for anyone who wants to think deeply, and clearly,
about the prospect of a global environmental cataclysm and what we
might do to address it.' - J.E. Penner, author of The Idea of
Property in LawIn this thought-provoking work, Mary Warnock
explores what it is to own things, and the differences in our
attitude to what we own and what we do not. Starting from the
philosophical standpoints of Locke and Hume, the ownership of
gardens is presented as a prime example, exploring both private and
common ownership, historically and autobiographically. The author
concludes that, besides pleasure and pride, ownership brings a
sense of responsibility for what is owned and a fundamental
question is brought to light: can we feel the same responsibility
for what we do not, and never can, own? Applying this question to
the natural world and the planet as a whole, a realistic and
gradualist perspective is offered on confronting global
environmental degradation. Critical Reflections on Ownership
examines the effect of the Romantic Movement on our attitudes to
nature and is a salient commentary on the history of ideas.
Providing an accessible entrance into moral philosophy and its
practical applications, this book is an invaluable source for
students in the fields of politics and philosophy. Academics
interested in conceptions of ownership, and in the interface
between philosophy, morality and politics, will find this deeply
considered insight to be a stimulating read.
This book, first published in 1965, is a critical exposition of the
philosophical doctrines of Jean-Paul Sartre. His contribution to
ethical and political theory, and to metaphysics and ontology, is
reviewed against the background of German idealism and
phenomenology, and his arguments are presented clearly so that
readers may assess their philosophical value in their own right.
First published in 1972. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor &
Francis, an informa company.
Sir Arthur Stanley Eddington (1882 1944) was a key figure in the
development of modern astrophysics, who also made important
contributions to the philosophy of science and popular science
writing. The Arthur Eddington Memorial Trust was set up after his
death in order to hold annual lectures on the relationship between
scientific thought and aspects of philosophy, religion or ethics.
This 2012 collection gathers together six of these lectures,
including contributions by Sir Edmund Whittaker, Herbert Dingle,
Richard B. Braithwaite, John C. Eccles, Dame Kathleen Lonsdale, and
Baroness Mary Warnock, together with Eddington's 1929 Swarthmore
Lecture on Science and the Unseen World. A preface written by the
Astronomer Royal, Baron Rees of Ludlow, is also included. This is a
fascinating book that will be of value to anyone with an interest
in the philosophy of science and Eddington's legacy.
Sir Arthur Stanley Eddington (1882-1944) was a key figure in the
development of modern astrophysics, who also made important
contributions to the philosophy of science and popular science
writing. The Arthur Eddington Memorial Trust was set up after his
death in order to hold annual lectures on the relationship between
scientific thought and aspects of philosophy, religion or ethics.
This 2012 collection gathers together six of these lectures,
including contributions by Sir Edmund Whittaker, Herbert Dingle,
Richard B. Braithwaite, John C. Eccles, Dame Kathleen Lonsdale, and
Baroness Mary Warnock, together with Eddington's 1929 Swarthmore
Lecture on Science and the Unseen World. A preface written by the
Astronomer Royal, Baron Rees of Ludlow, is also included. This is a
fascinating book that will be of value to anyone with an interest
in the philosophy of science and Eddington's legacy.
When Did I Begin? investigates the theoretical, moral, and biological issues surrounding the debate over the beginning of human life. With the continuing controversy over the use of in vitro fertilization techniques and experimentation with human embryos, these issues have been forced into the arena of public debate. Following a detailed analysis of the history of the question, Reverend Ford argues that a human individual could not begin before definitive individuation occurs with the appearance of the primitive streak about two weeks after fertilization. This, he argues, is when it becomes finally known whether one or more human individuals are to form from a single egg. Thus, he questions the idea that the fertilized egg itself could be regarded as the beginning of the development of the human individual. The author also differs sharply, however, from those who would delay the beginning of the human person until the brain is formed, or until birth or the onset of conscious states.
Mary Warnock steers a clear path through the web of complex issues underlying the use of new reproductive technologies. She begins by analysing what it means to claim something as a 'right', and goes on to discuss the cases of different groups of people. She also examines the ethical problems faced by particular types of assisted reproduction, including artificial insemination, in-vitro fertilization, and surrogacy, and argues that in the future human cloning may well be a viable and acceptable form of treatment for some types of infertility.
The development of new reproductive technologies has raised urgent
questions and debates about how and by whom these treatments should
be controlled. On the one hand individuals and groups have claimed
access to assisted reproduction as a right, and some have also
claimed that this access should be available free of charge. As
well as clinically infertile heterosexual couples, this right has
been claimed by single women, gay couples, post-menopausal women,
and couples who wish to delay having children for various reasons.
Others have argued that a desire to have children does not make it
a human right, and, moreover, that there are some people who should
not be assisted to become parents, on grounds of age, sexuality, or
lifestyle. Mary Warnock steers a clear path through the web of
complex issues underlying these views. She begins by analyzing what
it means to claim something as a 'right', and goes on to discuss
the cases of different groups of people. She also examines the
ethical problems faced by particular types of assisted
reproduction, including artificial insemination, in-vitro
fertilization, and surrogacy, and argues that in the future human
cloning may well be a viable an
Existentialism enjoyed great popularity in the 1940s and 1950s, and
has probably had a greater impact upon literature than any other
kind of philosophy. The common interest which unites Existentialist
philosophers is their interest in human freedom. Readers of
Existentialist philosophy are being asked, not merely to
contemplate the nature of freedom, but to experience freedom, and
to practise it. In this survey, Mary Warnock begins by considering
the ethical origins of Existentialism, with particular reference to
Kierkegaard and Nietzsche, and outlines the importance of a
systematic account of man's connection with the world as expounded
by Husserl. She discusses at length the common interests and
ancestry of Existentialism in the works of Heidegger,
Merleau-Ponty, and Sartre, and offers some conclusions about the
current nature and future of this committed and practical
philosophy. This revised edition includes a postscript reviewing
the status of Existentialism in the 1990s, and has a thoroughly
updated bibliography.
This title considers the philosophical debates surrounding special
educational needs and inclusion. "Special Educational Needs: A New
Look" by Mary Warnock was initially published by the Philosophy of
Education Society of Great Britain in 2005. In this new edition,
Warnock has updated her argument, Brahm Norwich has contributed a
counter-argument and Lorella Terzi has provided a foreword and
afterword, drawing the two debates together. The issues debated in
this new edition of "Special Educational Needs: A New Look"
include: The statement of special educational need - the concept of
inclusion. "Special Educational Needs: A New Look" raises issues
which will be of interest to all involved in special education and
inclusion, including teachers, policy makers and educationalists.
This innovative series is addressed to practitioners and
policy-makers. It highlights the critical perspectives that
philosophy can bring to bear on current education policy and
provides a lively discussion of the issues. It aims to stimulate
debate and to contribute to better informed educational
initiatives.
Imagination is an outstanding contribution to a notoriously elusive
and confusing subject. It skillfully interrelates problems in
philosophy, the history of ideas and literary theory and criticism,
tracing the evolution of the concept of imagination from Hume and
Kant in the eighteenth century to Ryle, Sartre and Wittgenstein in
the twentieth. She strongly belies that the cultivation of
imagination should be the chief aim of education and one of her
objectives in writing the book has been to put forward reasons why
this is so. Purely philosophical treatment of the concept is shown
to be related to its use in the work of Coleridge and Wordsworth,
who she considers to be the creators of a new kind of awareness
with more than literary implications. The purpose of her historical
account is to suggest that the role of imagination in our
perception and thought is more pervasive than may at first sight
appear, and that the thread she traces is an important link joining
apparently different areas of our experience. She argues that
imagination is an essential element in both our awareness of the
world and our attaching of value to it.
This is a powerful argument that religious and theological issues
should have no place in public morality issues such as euthanasia,
assisted suicide, and abortion. Here is a pugnacious book by a
philosopher who often hits the headlines. The book reflects on the
nature of religion and how it relates or ought to relate to the
rest of life. Many people today are totally indifferent to religion
but religion is far from dead. Indeed religions are intensely
defended and aggressively pursued. Religion is a cause for
dissension and death. This is beyond dispute. Mary Warnock is
concerned with Christianity. She argues that to value religion as
the essential foundation of morality is a profound and probably
dangerous mistake. Warnock's overriding purpose is to prise apart
religion and morality. Judges for example are constantly being
asked to pass judgement on moral issues in court. Because of The
Human Rights Act, the law perforce is involved. Morality is
therefore increasingly a public and not just a private matter. This
book attempts to clarify the foundation of morality in a society
largely indifferent to and ignorant of religion. Religion
nevertheless emerges as a source of deep and unique imaginative
experience.
|
|