|
Showing 1 - 11 of
11 matches in All Departments
How exactly could God achieve infallible foreknowledge of every
future event, including the free actions of human persons? How
could God exercise careful providence over these same events?
Byerly offers a novel response to these important questions by
contending that God exercises providence and achieves foreknowledge
by ordering the times. The first part of the book defends the
importance of the above questions. After characterizing the
contemporary freedom-foreknowledge debate, Byerly argues that this
debate has focused too narrowly on a certain argument for
theological fatalism. This argument attempts to show that the
existence of infallible divine foreknowledge poses a unique threat
to the existence of creaturely libertarian freedom. The author
argues, however, that bare existence of infallible divine
foreknowledge cannot threaten freedom in this way; at most, the
mechanics whereby this foreknowledge is achieved might so threaten
human freedom. In the second part of the book, Byerly develops a
model for understanding the mechanics whereby infallible
foreknowledge is achieved which would not threaten creaturely
libertarian freedom.According to the model, God infallibly
foreknows every future event because God has placed the times which
constitute the history of the world in primitive earlier-than
relations to one another. After defending the consistency of this
model of the mechanics of divine foreknowledge with creaturely
libertarian freedom, the author applies the model to divine
providence more generally. A novel defense of concurrentism is the
result.
Intellectual Dependability is the first research monograph devoted
to addressing the question of what it is to be an intellectually
dependable person—the sort of person on whom one’s fellow
inquirers can depend in their pursuit of epistemic goods. While
neglected in recent scholarship, this question is an important one
for both epistemology—how we should conceptualize the ideal
inquirer—and education—how we can enable developing learners to
grow toward this ideal. The book defends a virtue theory according
to which being an intellectually dependable person is distinctively
a matter of possessing a suite of neglected virtues called "the
virtues of intellectual dependability" that are themselves
distinctively concerned with promoting epistemic goods in others’
inquiries. After defending the existence and educational
significance of these virtues as a group, the book turns toward the
project of identifying and conceptualizing several specific
instances of these virtues in detail. Virtues discussed include
intellectual benevolence, intellectual transparency, communicative
clarity, audience sensitivity, and epistemic guidance. In each
case, an interdisciplinary treatment of the nature of the virtue
and its relationship to other virtues, vices, and personality
features is offered, drawing especially on relevant research in
Philosophy and Psychology. The book concludes with a chapter
devoted to identifying distinctive ways these virtues of
intellectual dependability are manifested when it is inquiring
communities, rather than individuals, that occupy the position of
intellectual dependence. By directing attention to the ideal of
intellectual dependability, the book marks a novel turn of
scholarly interest explicitly toward a neglected dimension of the
ideal inquirer that will inform both epistemological theorizing and
educational practice.
When deciding what to do, is it best to treat one's own interests
as more important than the interests of others, others' interests
as more important than one's own, or one's own and others'
interests as equally important? This book develops an account of
others-centeredness, a way of putting others first in the process
of deciding what to do. Over the course of six chapters, Putting
Others First investigates other-centeredness by drawing upon a wide
range of academic disciplines including biblical studies, feminist
scholarship, philosophy, psychology, and theology. The author
begins by explaining the nature of others-centeredness as a
character trait in detail and connecting it with other contemporary
projects in virtue theory. He argues that foundational texts of the
New Testament can be plausibly read as advocating for
others-centeredness. He then develops a provisional case for the
value of others-centeredness from the perspective of each of the
three major approaches to normative ethics: consequentialism,
deontology, and virtue ethics. Next, the author confronts
challenging questions about the value of others-centeredness,
including whether others-centeredness requires an impossibly strong
sort of altruism, whether it leads its possessors into
self-destructive relationships, and whether it leads to offering
help that hurts others. Finally, he examines the place of
others-centeredness within a person's moral psychology by
considering the relationship between it and other virtues and
vices, and reviews relevant scientific findings that illuminate the
value and causal role of others-centeredness.
This book offers a multifaceted exploration of death and the
possibilities for an afterlife. By incorporating a variety of
approaches to these subjects, it provides a unique framework for
extending and reshaping enduring philosophical debates around human
existence up to and after death. Featuring original essays from a
diverse group of international scholars, the book is arranged in
four main sections. Firstly, it addresses how death is or should be
experienced, engaging with topics such as near-death experiences,
continuing bonds with the deceased, and attitudes toward dying.
Secondly, it looks at surviving death, addressing the metaphysics
of human persons, the nature of time, the nature of the true self,
and the nature of the divine. It then evaluates the value of
mortality and immortality, drawing upon the resources of the
history of philosophy, meta-analysis of contemporary debates, and
the analogy between individual death and species extinction.
Finally, it explores what an eternal life might be like, examining
the place of selflessness, embodiment, and racial identity in such
a life. This volume allows for a variety of philosophical and
theological perspectives to be brought to bear on the end of life
and what might be beyond. As such, it will be a fascinating
resource for scholars in the philosophy of religion, theology, and
death studies.
This book offers a multifaceted exploration of death and the
possibilities for an afterlife. By incorporating a variety of
approaches to these subjects, it provides a unique framework for
extending and reshaping enduring philosophical debates around human
existence up to and after death. Featuring original essays from a
diverse group of international scholars, the book is arranged in
four main sections. Firstly, it addresses how death is or should be
experienced, engaging with topics such as near-death experiences,
continuing bonds with the deceased, and attitudes toward dying.
Secondly, it looks at surviving death, addressing the metaphysics
of human persons, the nature of time, the nature of the true self,
and the nature of the divine. It then evaluates the value of
mortality and immortality, drawing upon the resources of the
history of philosophy, meta-analysis of contemporary debates, and
the analogy between individual death and species extinction.
Finally, it explores what an eternal life might be like, examining
the place of selflessness, embodiment, and racial identity in such
a life. This volume allows for a variety of philosophical and
theological perspectives to be brought to bear on the end of life
and what might be beyond. As such, it will be a fascinating
resource for scholars in the philosophy of religion, theology, and
death studies.
Intellectual Dependability is the first research monograph devoted
to addressing the question of what it is to be an intellectually
dependable person-the sort of person on whom one's fellow inquirers
can depend in their pursuit of epistemic goods. While neglected in
recent scholarship, this question is an important one for both
epistemology-how we should conceptualize the ideal inquirer-and
education-how we can enable developing learners to grow toward this
ideal. The book defends a virtue theory according to which being an
intellectually dependable person is distinctively a matter of
possessing a suite of neglected virtues called "the virtues of
intellectual dependability" that are themselves distinctively
concerned with promoting epistemic goods in others' inquiries.
After defending the existence and educational significance of these
virtues as a group, the book turns toward the project of
identifying and conceptualizing several specific instances of these
virtues in detail. Virtues discussed include intellectual
benevolence, intellectual transparency, communicative clarity,
audience sensitivity, and epistemic guidance. In each case, an
interdisciplinary treatment of the nature of the virtue and its
relationship to other virtues, vices, and personality features is
offered, drawing especially on relevant research in Philosophy and
Psychology. The book concludes with a chapter devoted to
identifying distinctive ways these virtues of intellectual
dependability are manifested when it is inquiring communities,
rather than individuals, that occupy the position of intellectual
dependence. By directing attention to the ideal of intellectual
dependability, the book marks a novel turn of scholarly interest
explicitly toward a neglected dimension of the ideal inquirer that
will inform both epistemological theorizing and educational
practice.
Paradise Understood: New Philosophical Essays about Heaven
systematically investigates heaven, or paradise, as conceived
within theistic religious traditions such as Rabbinic Judaism,
Christianity, and Islam. It considers a variety of topics
concerning what life in paradise would, could, or will be like for
human persons. The collection offers novel approaches to questions
about heaven of perennial philosophical interest, and breaks new
ground by expanding the range of questions about heaven that
philosophers have considered. The contributors wrestle with
questions about human life in paradise that span the spectrum of
the major subfields of philosophical enquiry. By employing both
historical and contemporary philosophical resources, the volume
makes a pioneering contribution toward answering pressing questions
about human life in paradise. It will serve as a platform for
future research, reinvigorating philosophical investigation into
these neglected topics within philosophy of religion.
When deciding what to do, is it best to treat one's own interests
as more important than the interests of others, others' interests
as more important than one's own, or one's own and others'
interests as equally important? This book develops an account of
others-centeredness, a way of putting others first in the process
of deciding what to do. Over the course of six chapters, Putting
Others First investigates other-centeredness by drawing upon a wide
range of academic disciplines including biblical studies, feminist
scholarship, philosophy, psychology, and theology. The author
begins by explaining the nature of others-centeredness as a
character trait in detail and connecting it with other contemporary
projects in virtue theory. He argues that foundational texts of the
New Testament can be plausibly read as advocating for
others-centeredness. He then develops a provisional case for the
value of others-centeredness from the perspective of each of the
three major approaches to normative ethics: consequentialism,
deontology, and virtue ethics. Next, the author confronts
challenging questions about the value of others-centeredness,
including whether others-centeredness requires an impossibly strong
sort of altruism, whether it leads its possessors into
self-destructive relationships, and whether it leads to offering
help that hurts others. Finally, he examines the place of
others-centeredness within a person's moral psychology by
considering the relationship between it and other virtues and
vices, and reviews relevant scientific findings that illuminate the
value and causal role of others-centeredness.
Faith, Flourishing, and Agnosticism uses conceptual and empirical
methods to argue that the many individuals who have ambiguous
evidence for God can grow in virtue and attain greater flourishing
by engaging in practices of faith toward God. The book develops a
way of thinking about God, called minimal theism. It argues that a
sizeable number of people have ambiguous evidence for God, and it
provides support for arguments for agnosticism through an
evaluation of theistic and atheistic arguments and higher-order
evidence about God. It discusses what kind of cognitive commitments
toward God are required to engage in faith practices such as
thanking or praising God, and develops unique arguments that these
can be supplied by beliefs or non-doxastic assumptions but not
other states. Four pathways whereby individuals with ambiguous
evidence for God can grow in virtue through such faith practices
are identified. First, they can grow in general virtuous tendencies
to give other people the benefit of the doubt by giving God the
benefit of the doubt. Second, they can indirectly grow in a broad
range of virtues by experiencing better mental health as a
consequence of accepting God's love. Third, they can make skilled
use of the worldview of minimal theism to cultivate transformative
experiences of awe and connectedness, thereby supporting the
specific virtue of spiritual excellence. Finally, by this same
process, they can reap further downstream benefits in character
growth, independently of whether spiritual excellence is virtuous.
This robust, clear, and well-researched textbook for classes in
logic introduces students to both formal logic and to the virtues
of intellectual inquiry. Part 1 challenges students to develop the
analytical skills of deductive and inductive reasoning, showing
them how to identify and evaluate arguments. Part 2 helps students
develop the intellectual virtues of the wise inquirer. The book
includes helpful pedagogical features such as practice exercises
and a concluding summary with definitions of key concepts for each
chapter. Resources for professors and students are available
through Baker Academic's Textbook eSources.
How exactly could God achieve infallible foreknowledge of every
future event, including the free actions of human persons? How
could God exercise careful providence over these same events?
Byerly offers a novel response to these important questions by
contending that God exercises providence and achieves foreknowledge
by ordering the times. The first part of the book defends the
importance of the above questions. After characterizing the
contemporary freedom-foreknowledge debate, Byerly argues that it
has focused too narrowly on a certain argument for theological
fatalism, which attempts to show that the existence of infallible
divine foreknowledge poses a unique threat to the existence of
creaturely libertarian freedom. Byerly contends, however, that bare
existence of infallible divine foreknowledge cannot threaten
freedom in this way; at most, the mechanics whereby this
foreknowledge is achieved might so threaten human freedom. In the
second part of the book, Byerly develops a model for understanding
the mechanics whereby infallible foreknowledge is achieved that
would not threaten creaturely libertarian freedom. According to the
model, God infallibly foreknows every future event because God has
placed the times that constitute the history of the world in
primitive earlier-than relations to one another. After defending
the consistency of this model of the mechanics of divine
foreknowledge with creaturely libertarian freedom, the author
applies it to divine providence more generally. A novel defense of
concurrentism is the result.
|
|