|
Books > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Metaphysics & ontology
The Use of Exodus in Hebrews illustrates how traditions and
hermeneutics have significantly determined people's valuations of
the relationship between the Old and New Covenants in Hebrews. By
showing how the author of Hebrews uses the canonical revelation
from Exodus to argue rhetorically, ontologically, and
hermeneutically that Jesus Christ is the New Covenant priest in the
heavenly tabernacle, this book offers an epistemological lens from
Exodus to identify the correct view of the relationship between the
Old and New Covenants.
Antonia Lolordo presents an original interpretation of John Locke's
conception of moral agency-one that has implications both for his
metaphysics and for the foundations of his political theory. Locke
denies that species boundaries exist independently of human
convention, holds that the human mind may be either an immaterial
substance or a material one to which God has superadded the power
of thought, and insists that animals possess the ability to
perceive, will, and even reason-indeed, in some cases to reason
better than humans. Thus, he eliminates any sharp distinction
between humans and the rest of the animal kingdom. However, in his
ethical and political work Locke assumes that there is a sharp
distinction between moral agents and other beings. He thus needs to
be able to delineate the set of moral agents precisely, without
relying on the sort of metaphysical and physical facts his
predecessors appealed to. Lolordo argues that for Locke, to be a
moral agent is simply to be free, rational, and a person.
Interpreting the Lockean metaphysics of moral agency in this way
helps us to understand both Locke's over-arching philosophical
project and the details of his accounts of liberty, personhood, and
rationality.
The human world is in a mess. The human mind is in a mess. And now
the human species is threatening its own survival by its own
inventions and by war. For thousands of years, human beings
conducted a great debate about the human condition and human
possibilities, about philosophy and society and law. In 1516,
Thomas More, in his book Utopia, contributed to the ancient debate,
at another time of profound transformation in the human world. In
our own time, we have witnessed a collapse in intellectual life,
and a collapse in the theory and practice of education. The old
debate is, for all practical purposes, dead. In 2016, Philip
Allott's Eutopia resumes the debate about the role of philosophy
and society and law in making a better human future, responding to
a human world that More could not have imagined. And he lets us
hear the voices of some of those who contributed to the great
debate in the past, voices that still resonate today.
This book showcases a range of views on topics at the forefront of
current controversies in the field of metaphysics. It will give
readers a varied and alive introduction to the field, and cover
such key issues as: modality, fundamentality, composition, the
object/property distinction, and indeterminacy. The contributors
include some of the most important philosophers currently writing
on these issues. The questions and philosophers are: Are there any
individuals at the fundamental level? / (1) Shamik Dasgupta (2)
Jason Turner Is there an objective difference between essential and
accidental properties? / (1) Meghan Sullivan (2) Kris McDaniel and
Steve Steward Are there any worldly states of affairs? / (1) Daniel
Nolan (2) Joseph Melia Are there any intermediate states of
affairs? / (1) Jessica Wilson (2) Elizabeth Barnes and Ross Cameron
Do ordinary objects exist? / (1) Trenton Merricks (2) Helen Beebee
Editor Elizabeth Barnes guides readers through these controversies
(all published here for the first time), with a synthetic
introduction and succinct abstracts of each debate.
This volume collects 12 essays by various contributors on the
subject of the importance and influence of Schopenhauer's doctoral
dissertation (On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient
Reason) for both Schopenhauer's more well-known philosophy and the
ongoing discussion of the subject of the principle of sufficient
reason. The contributions deal with the historical context of
Schopenhauer's reflections, their relationship to (transcendental)
idealism, the insights they hold for Schopenhauer's views of
consciousness and sensation, and how they illuminate Schopenhauer's
theory of action. This is the first full-length, English volume on
Schopenhauer's Fourfold Root and its relevance for Schopenhauer's
philosophy. The thought-provoking essays collected in this volume
will undoubtedly enrich the burgeoning field of
Schopenhauer-studies.
Offering new and original readings of literature, poetry, and
education as interpreted through the conceptual lens of Heidegger's
later philosophy of the "Turn", this book helps readers understand
Heidegger's later thought and presents new takes on how to engage
the themes that emerged from his later writing. Suggesting novel
ways to consider Heidegger's ideas on literature, poetry, and
education, Magrini and Schwieler provide a deep understanding of
the "Turn," a topic not often explored in contemporary Heideggerian
scholarship. Their inter- and extra-disciplinary postmodern
approaches offer a nuanced examination, taking into account
Heidegger's controversial place in history, and filling a gap in
educational research.
Nature and Normativity argues that the problem of the place of
norms in nature has been essentially misunderstood when it has been
articulated in terms of the relation of human language and thought,
on the one hand, and the world described by physics on the other.
Rather, if we concentrate on the facts that speaking and thinking
are activities of organic agents, then the problem of the place of
the normative in nature becomes refocused on three related
questions. First, is there a sense in which biological processes
and the behavior of organisms can be legitimately subject to
normative evaluation? Second, is there some sense in which, in
addition to having ordinary causal explanations, organic phenomena
can also legitimately be seen to happen because they should happen
in that way, in some naturalistically comprehensible sense of
'should', or that organic phenomena happen in order to achieve some
result, because that result should occur? And third, is it possible
to naturalistically understand how human thought and language can
be legitimately seen as the normatively evaluable behavior of a
particular species of organism, behavior that occurs in order to
satisfy some class of norms? This book develops, articulates, and
defends positive answers to each of these questions.
Weakness of will, the phenomenon of acting contrary to one's own
better judgment, has remained a prominent discussion topic of
philosophy. The history of this discussion in ancient, medieval,
and modern times has been outlined in many studies. Weakness of
Will in Renaissance and ReformationThought is, however, the first
book to cover the fascinating source materials on weakness of will
between 1350 and 1650. In addition to considering the work of a
broad range of Renaissance authors (including Petrarch, Donato
Acciaiuoli, John Mair, and Francesco Piccolomini), Risto Saarinen
explores the theologically coloured debates of the Reformation
period, such as those provided by Martin Luther, Philip
Melanchthon, John Calvin, and Lambert Daneau. He goes on to discuss
the impact of these authors on prominent figures of early
modernity, including Shakespeare, Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz.
While most of the historical research on weakness of will has
focused on the reception history of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics,
Saarinen pays attention to the Platonic and Stoic discussions and
their revival during the Renaissance and the Reformation. He also
shows the ways in which Augustine's discussion of the divided will
is intertwined with the Christian reception of ancient Greek
ethics, and argues that the theological underpinnings of early
modern authors do not rule out weakness of will, but transform the
philosophical discussion and lead it towards new solutions.
Heidegger, Ethics and the Practice of Ontology presents an
important new examination of ethics and ontology in Heidegger.
There remains a basic conviction throughout Heidegger's thought
that the event by which Being is given or disclosed is somehow
'prior' to our relation to the many beings we meet in our everyday
lives. This priority makes it possible to talk about Being 'as
such'. It also sanctions the relegation of ethics to a secondary
position with respect to ontology. However, Heidegger's
acknowledgement that ontology itself must remain intimately bound
to concrete existence problematises the priority accorded to the
ontological dimension. David Webb takes this bond as a key point of
reference and goes on to develop critical perspectives that open up
from within Heidegger's own thought, particularly in relation to
Heidegger's debt to Aristotelian physics and ethics. Webb examines
the theme of continuity and its role in the constitution of the 'as
such' in Heidegger's ontology and argues that to address ontology
is to engage in an ethical practice and vice versa.
Questions concerning free will are intertwined with issues in
almost every area of philosophy, from metaphysics to philosophy of
mind to moral philosophy, and are also informed by work in
different areas of science (principally physics, neuroscience and
social psychology). Free will is also a perennial concern of
serious thinkers in theology and in non-western traditions. Because
free will can be approached from so many different perspectives and
has implications for so many debates, a comprehensive survey needs
to encompass an enormous range of approaches. This book is the
first to draw together leading experts on every aspect of free
will, from those who are central to the current philosophical
debates, to non-western perspectives, to scientific contributions
and to those who know the rich history of the subject. Chapter 37
of this book is freely available as a downloadable Open Access PDF
under a Creative Commons Attribution-Non Commercial-No Derivatives
3.0 license.
https://s3-us-west-2.amazonaws.com/tandfbis/rt-files/docs/Open+Access+Chapters/9781138795815_oachapter37.pdf
George Berkeley notoriously claimed that his immaterialist
metaphysics was not only consistent with common sense but that it
was also integral to its defense. Roberts argues that understanding
the basic connection between Berkeley's philosophy and common sense
requires that we develop a better understanding of the four
principle components of Berkeley's positive metaphysics: The nature
of being, the divine language thesis, the active/passive
distinction, and the nature of spirits.
Roberts begins by focusing on Berkeley's view of the nature of
being. He elucidates Berkeley's view on Locke and the Cartesians
and by examining Berkeley's views about related concepts such as
unity and simplicity. From there he moves on to Berkeley's
philosophy of language arguing that scrutiny of the famous
"Introduction" to the Principles of Human Knowledge reveals that
Berkeley identified the ideational theory of meaning and
understanding as the root cause of some of the worst of man's
intellectual errors, not "abstract ideas." Abstract ideas are,
rather, the most debilitating symptom of this underlying ailment.
In place of the ideational theory, Berkeley defends a rudimentary
"use theory" of meaning. This understanding of Berkeley's approach
to semantics is then applied to the divine language thesis and is
shown to have important consequences for Berkeley's pragmatic
approach to the ontology of natural objects and for his approach to
our knowledge of, and relation to other minds, including God's.
Turning next to Berkeley's much aligned account of spirits, the
author defends the coherence of Berkeley's view of spirits by way
of providing an interpretation of the active/passive distinction as
marking anormative distinction and by focusing on the role that
divine language plays in letting Berkeley identify the soul with
the will. With these four principles of Berkeley's philosophy in
hand, he then returns to the topic of common sense and offers a
defense of Berkeley's philosophy as built upon and expressive of
the deepest metaphysical commitments of mainstream Christianity.
Roberts' reappraisal of this important figure should appeal to all
historians of philosophy as well as scholars in metaphysics and
philosophy of language.
|
|