|
Showing 1 - 25 of
43 matches in All Departments
This is the first complete translation into a modern language of
the first part of the pagan Neoplatonist Simplicius of Cilicia's
commentary on Aristotle's argument that the world neither came to
be nor will perish. It is notable and unusual among the
commentaries because Simplicius includes in his discussion lengthy
representations of the Christian John Philoponus' criticisms of
Aristotle along with his own, frequently heavily sarcastic,
responses.
This is the first English translation of Simplicius' responses to
Philoponus' "Against Aristotle on the Eternity of the World." The
commentary is published in two volumes: Ian Mueller's previous book
in the series, " Simplicius: On Aristotle On the Heavens 1.2-3,"
and this book on 1.3-4. Philoponus, the Christian, had argued that
Aristotle's arguments do not succeed. For all they show to the
contrary, Christianity may be right that the heavens were brought
into existence by the only divine being and one moment in time, and
will cease to exist at some future moment. Simplicius upholds the
pagan view that the heavens are eternal and divine, and argues that
their eternity is shown by their astronomical movements coupled
with certain principles of Aristotle.Until the launch of this
series, the 15,000 volumes of the ancient Greek commentators on
Aristotle constituted the largest corpus of Greek philosophical
writings which had not been translated into English or other
European languages. There are now over 100 volumes in the series.
In this volume Simplicius deals with Aristotle's account of the
Presocratics, and for many of them he is our chief or even sole
authority. He quotes at length from Melissus, Parmenides and Zeno,
sometimes from their original works but also from later writers
from Plato onwards, drawing particularly on Alexander's lost
commentary on Aristotle's Physics and on Porphyry. Much of his
approach is just scholarly, but in places he reveals his
Neoplatonist affiliation and attempts to show the basic agreement
among his predecessors in spite of their apparent differences. This
volume, part of the groundbreaking Ancient Commentators on
Aristotle series, translates into English for the first time
Simplicius' commentary, and includes a detailed introduction,
extensive explanatory notes and a bibliography.
Commentaries on Aristotle's writings have been produced since the
2nd century AD. This edition contains Greek commentaries on his
work from the 3rd to the 8th centuries AD by, among others,
Alexander of Aphrodiensias, Themistios, Joh. Philoponus, Simplicius
in Greek.
Commentaries on Aristotle's writings have been produced since the
2nd century AD. This edition contains Greek commentaries on his
work from the 3rd to the 8th centuries AD by, among others,
Alexander of Aphrodiensias, Themistios, Joh. Philoponus, Simplicius
in Greek.
Commentaries on Aristotle's writings have been produced since the
2nd century AD. This edition contains Greek commentaries on his
work from the 3rd to the 8th centuries AD by, among others,
Alexander of Aphrodiensias, Themistios, Joh. Philoponus, Simplicius
in Greek.
Aristotle's "Physics "Book 3 covers two subjects: the definition of
change and the finitude of the universe. Change enters into the
very definition of nature as an internal source of change. Change
receives two definitions in chapters 1 and 2, as involving the
actualisation of the potential or of the changeable. Alexander of
Aphrodisias is reported as thinking that the second version is
designed to show that Book 3, like Book 5, means to disqualify
change in relations from being genuine change. Aristotle's
successor Theophrastus, we are told, and Simplicius himself, prefer
to admit relational change. Chapter 3 introduces a general causal
principle that the activity of the agent causing change is in the
patient undergoing change, and that the causing and undergoing are
to be counted as only one activity, however different in
definition. Simplicius points out that this paves the way for
Aristotle's God who moves the heavens, while admitting no motion in
himself. It is also the basis of Aristotle's doctrine, central to
Neoplatonism, that intellect is one with the objects it
contemplates.In defending Aristotle's claim that the universe is
spatially finite, Simplicius has to meet Archytas' question, "What
happens at the edge?." He replies that, given Aristotle's
definition of place, there is nothing, rather than an empty place,
beyond the furthest stars, and one cannot stretch one's hand into
nothing, nor be prevented by nothing. But why is Aristotle's
beginningless universe not temporally infinite? Simplicius answers
that the past years no longer exist, so one never has an infinite
collection.
Aristotle believed that the outermost stars are carried round us on
a transparent sphere. There are directions in the universe and a
preferred direction of rotation. The sun, moon and planets are
carried on different revolving spheres. The spheres and celestial
bodies are composed of an everlasting fifth element, which has none
of the ordinary contrary properties like heat and cold which could
destroy it, but only the facility for uniform rotation. But this
creates problems as to how the heavenly bodies create light, and,
in the case of the sun, heat. The topics covered in this part of
Simplicius' commentary are: the speeds and distances of the stars;
that the stars are spherical; why the sun and moon have fewer
motions than the other five planets; why the sphere of the fixed
stars contains so many stars whereas the other heavenly spheres
contain no more than one (Simplicius has a long excursus on
planetary theory in his commentary on this chapter); discussion of
people's views on the position, motion or rest, shape, and size of
the earth; that the earth is a relatively small sphere at rest in
the centre of the cosmos.
Simplicius' commentary on Aristotle's Categories is the most
comprehensive philosophical critique of the work ever written,
representing 600 years of criticism. In his Categories, Aristotle
divides what exists in the sensible world into ten categories of
Substance, Quantity, Relative, Quality and so on. Simplicius starts
with a survey of previous commentators, and an introductory set of
questions about Aristotle's philosophy and about the Categories in
particular. The commentator, he says, needs to present Plato and
Aristotle as in harmony on most things. Why are precisely ten
categories named, given that Plato did with fewer distinctions? We
have a survey of views on this. And where in the scheme of
categories would one fit a quality that defines a substance - under
substance or under quality? In his own commentary, Porphyry
suggested classifying a defining quality as something distinct, a
substantial quality, but others objected that this would constitute
an eleventh. The most persistent question dealt with here is
whether the categories classify words, concepts, or things.
|
You may like...
Ab Wheel
R209
R149
Discovery Miles 1 490
|