|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Western philosophy, c 500 to c 1600
This book examines the concept of " Neurosemantics", a term
currently used in two different senses: the informational meaning
of the physical processes in the neural circuits, and semantics in
its classical sense, as the meaning of language, explained in terms
of neural processes. The book explores this second sense of
neurosemantics, yet in doing so, it addresses much of the first
meaning as well. Divided into two parts, the book starts with a
description and analysis of the mathematics of the brain, including
computational units, representational mechanisms and algorithmic
principles. This first part pays special attention to the neural
architecture which has been used in developing models of
neurosemantics. The second part of the book presents a collection
of models, and describes each model reproducing specific aspects of
the semantics of language. Some of these models target one of the
core problems of semantics, the reference of nouns, and in
particular of nouns with a strong perceptual characterization.
Others address the semantics of predicates, with a detailed
analysis of colour attributes. While this book represents a radical
shift from traditional semantics, it still pursues a line of
continuity that is based on the idea that meaning can be captured,
and explained, by a sort of computation.
This book reassesses the seminal work of Wilhelm Wundt by
discussing the history and philosophy of psychology. It traces the
pioneering theorist's intellectual development and the evolution of
psychology throughout his career. The author draws on little-known
sources to situate psychological concepts in Wundt's philosophical
thought and address common myths and misconceptions relating to
Wundt's ideas. The ideas presented in this book show why Wundt's
work remains relevant in this era of ongoing mind/brain debate and
interest continues in the links between psychology and philosophy.
Featured topics include: Theoretical and philosophical foundations
of Wundt's early work in scientific psychology. Wundt's conception
of scientific philosophy in relation to his theory of knowledge.
The epistemological dimensions of Wundt's final project in
scientific psychology. Wundt and the Philosophical Foundations of
Psychology is a valuable resource for researchers, professors, and
graduate students in cognitive and related psychology and
philosophy disciplines.
This book explores the philosophy of love through the thought and
life of Rabbi Akiva ben Joseph. Readers of the Talmud are
introduced to Rabbi Akiva through the iconic story of his love for
his wife Rachel. From this starting point, Naftali Rothenberg
conducts a thorough examination of the harmonious approach to love
in the obstacle-laden context of human reality. Discussing the
deterioration of passion into simple lust, the ability to contend
with suffering and death, and so forth, Rothenberg addresses the
deepest and most pressing questions about human love. The readings
and observations offered here allow readers to acquire the wisdom
of love-not merely as an assemblage of theoretical arguments and
abstract statements, but as an analysis of the internal
contradictions and difficulties revealed in the context of attempts
to realize and implement harmonious love.
This book aims to answer two simple questions: what is it to want
and what is it to intend? Because of the breadth of contexts in
which the relevant phenomena are implicated and the wealth of views
that have attempted to account for them, providing the answers is
not quite so simple. Doing so requires an examination not only of
the relevant philosophical theories and our everyday practices, but
also of the rich empirical material that has been provided by work
in social and developmental psychology. The investigation is
carried out in two parts, dedicated to wanting and intending
respectively. Wanting is analysed as optative attitudinising, a
basic form of subjective standard-setting at the core of compound
states such as 'longings', 'desires', 'projects' and 'whims'. The
analysis is developed in the context of a discussion of
Moore-paradoxicality and deepened through the examination of rival
theories, which include functionalist and hedonistic conceptions as
well as the guise-of-the-good view and the pure entailment
approach, two views popular in moral psychology. In the second part
of the study, a disjunctive genetic theory of intending is
developed, according to which intentions are optative attitudes on
which, in one way or another, the mark of deliberation has been
conferred. It is this which explains intention's subjection to the
requirements of practical rationality. Moreover, unlike wanting,
intending turns out to be dependent on normative features of our
life form, in particular on practices of holding responsible. The
book will be of particular interest to philosophers and
psychologists working on motivation, goals, desire, intention,
deliberation, decision and practical rationality.
With the publication of Arthur Farndell's "Gardens of Philosophy"
(Shepheard-Walwyn 2006), there remained only four of Ficino's
commentaries on Plato's dialogues which had not yet been translated
into English. Farndell's translation of the commentaries on "The
Republic and the Laws" will comprise the third volume under the
title "When Philosophers Rule" and the fourth, "All Things
Natural", will contain the "Timaeus". As Carol Kaske of Cornell
University wrote when reviewing "Gardens of Philosophy" in
"Renaissance Quarterly", these translations fill 'A need. Even
those Anglophone scholars who know Latin still need a translation
in order to read quickly through a large body of material'. The
central message of 'Parmenides', that everything depends on the
One, resonates with the growing awareness around the world of the
inter-relatedness of all things, be it in the biosphere, the
intellectual or spiritual realms. Philosophers in ancient Greece
appreciated this unity and employed reason and dialectic to draw
the mind away from its preoccupation with the material world and
attract it towards contemplation of the soul, and ultimately of
that Oneness which embraces, but is distinct from, the multifarious
forms of creation. Thus Parmenides carefully instructed the young
Socrates, and Plato recorded their dialogue in this work which he
named after the elderly philosopher. Nearly 2000 years later,
Marsilio Ficino made 'Parmenides' available to the West by
translating it into Latin, the language of scholars in his time.
Ficino added a lengthy commentary to this translation, a commentary
which "Evermore Shall Be So" puts into English for the first time,
more than 500 years after its original composition. Ficino's
crucial influence upon the unfolding of the Renaissance and his
presentation of Plato's understanding of the One and the so-called
Platonic Ideas or Forms make "Evermore Shall Be So" an important
work in the history of thought. Though it will be an essential buy
for renaissance scholars and historians, its freshness of thought
and wisdom are as relevant today as they ever were to inspire a new
generation seeking spiritual and philosophical direction in their
lives.
This monograph details a new solution to an old problem of
metaphysics. It presents an improved version of Ostrich Nominalism
to solve the Problem of Universals. This innovative approach allows
one to resolve the different formulations of the Problem, which
represents an important meta-metaphysical achievement.In order to
accomplish this ambitious task, the author appeals to the notion
and logic of ontological grounding. Instead of defending Quine's
original principle of ontological commitment, he proposes the
principle of grounded ontological commitment. This represents an
entirely new application of grounding. Some metaphysicians regard
Ostrich Nominalism as a rejection of the problem rather than a
proper solution to it. To counter this, the author presents
solutions for each of the formulations. These include: the problem
of predication, the problem of abstract reference, and the One Over
Many as well as the Many Over One and the Similar but Different
variants. This book will appeal to anyone interested in
contemporary metaphysics. It will also serve as an ideal resource
to scholars working on the history of philosophy. Many will
recognize in the solution insights resembling those of traditional
philosophers, especially of the Middle Ages.
Ethics was a central preoccupation of medieval philosophers, and
medieval ethical thought is rich, diverse, and inventive. Yet
standard histories of ethics often skip quickly over the medievals,
and histories of medieval philosophy often fail to do justice to
the centrality of ethical concerns in medieval thought. This volume
presents the full range of medieval ethics in Christian, Islamic,
and Jewish philosophy in a way that is accessible to a
non-specialist and reveals the liveliness and sophistication of
medieval ethical thought. In Part I there is a series of historical
chapters presenting developmental and contextual accounts of
Christian, Islamic, and Jewish ethics. Part II offers topical
chapters on such central themes as happiness, virtue, law, and
freedom, as well as on less-studied aspects of medieval ethics such
as economic ethics, the ethical dimensions of mysticism, and sin
and grace. This will be an important volume for students of ethics
and medieval philosophy.
The Old English Boethius boldly refashions in Anglo-Saxon guise a
great literary monument of the late-antique world, The Consolation
of Philosophy. Condemned to death for treason around 525 ce, the
Roman scholar Boethius turned to philosophy to transform his
personal distress into a powerful meditation on fate, free will,
and the human capacity for virtue in a flawed, fallen world.
Boethius's Latin dialogues found a receptive audience in
Anglo-Saxon England, where they were translated into Old English
some time around 900. The translator (traditionally identified with
King Alfred) freely adapts the Latin for a new audience: the Roman
Fabricius, for example, becomes the Germanic weapon-smith Weland.
The translation replicates Boethius's alternation of prose and
verse-only in this case Old English prose alternates with
alliterative verse. In later centuries Chaucer and Queen Elizabeth
each turned The Consolation of Philosophy into English, but the Old
English translation was the first to bring it to a wider vernacular
audience. Verse prologues and epilogues for works traditionally
associated with King Alfred fill out the volume, offering readers a
fascinating glimpse of the moment when English confidently claimed
its birthright as a literature capable of anything, from sublime
ideas to subtle poetry.
Drawing connections between madness, philosophy and autobiography,
this book addresses the question of how Nietzsche's madness might
have affected his later works. It also explores why continental
philosophy after Nietzsche is so fascinated with madness, and how
it (re)considers, (re)evaluates and (re)valorizes madness. To
answer these questions, the book analyzes the work of three major
figures in twentieth-century French philosophy who were
significantly influenced by Nietzsche: Bataille, Foucault and
Derrida, examining the ways in which their responses to Nietzsche's
madness determine how they understand philosophy as well as
philosophy's relation to madness. For these philosophers, posing
the question about madness renders the philosophical subject
vulnerable and implicates it in a state of responsibility towards
that about which it asks. Out of this analysis of their engagement
with the question of madness emerges a new conception of
'autobiographical philosophy', which entails the insertion of this
vulnerable subject into the philosophical work, to which each of
these philosophers adheres or resists in different ways.
With an emphasis on exploring measurable aspects of ancient
narratives, Maths Meets Myths sets out to investigate age-old
material with new techniques. This book collects, for the first
time, novel quantitative approaches to studying sources from the
past, such as chronicles, epics, folktales, and myths. It
contributes significantly to recent efforts in bringing together
natural scientists and humanities scholars in investigations aimed
at achieving greater understanding of our cultural inheritance.
Accordingly, each contribution reports on a modern quantitative
approach applicable to narrative sources from the past, or
describes those which would be amenable to such treatment and why
they are important. This volume is a unique state-of-the-art
compendium on an emerging research field which also addresses
anyone with interests in quantitative approaches to humanities.
The rehabilitation of Confucian tradition raised new challenges to
Chinese feminist thinkers. Can a Confucian ideal of reciprocity
help women realize their equality? What is the hope for Chinese
women seeking a social ideal of equality given the growing gender
gap in the current economic development of China? Yuan argues
Confucianism cannot help unless it is integrated with feminism. In
this book, Yuan explores why gendered stratifications perpetuated
so deeply in today's China through the influences of Confucian
cultural tradition, but reading early Confucian texts as a
cosmological vision of Ren with Dao and ontological oneness as a
whole that is the unity of heaven, earth, and humanism, we might
reclaim Confucian egalitarian aspects to develop its openness for
gender equity with integration of feminist critical care ethics.
Throughout the book, Yuan provides multiple perspectives of
comparison: relational self vs. power differentials, gender roles
differences vs. political demand for equality, and individual
reciprocity vs. connection based reciprocity, etc. to embrace
inclusive methodology and caring democracy. We see a great hope to
break through stereotypes of binary thinking of Minben (people
oriented) and Minzhu (autonomous democracy), gender division of
labor, reason and emotion, etc. Yuan argues we should integrate
feminist critical thoughts of global justice/care with early
Confucianism, since both traditions emphasize caring relationships
in humanity and interdependency between social individuals within
and beyond their communities in a global scale. Importantly, the
integration enlarges our philosophical visions of how cultural
traditions can be undeniable sources for strengthening contemporary
social ideas of humanity, democracy, equality, and freedom for all.
The fourteenth and fifteenth centuries witnessed a rising interest
in Arabic texts describing and explaining the rituals of the Coptic
Church of Egypt. This book provides readers with an English
translation of excerpts from three key texts on the Coptic liturgy
by Abu al-Barakat ibn Kabar, Yuh.anna ibn Sabba', and Pope Gabriel
V. With a scholarly introduction to the works, their authors, and
the Coptic liturgy, as well as a detailed explanatory apparatus,
this volume provides a useful and needed introduction to the
worship tradition of Egypt's Coptic Christians. Presented for the
first time in English, these texts provide valuable points of
comparison to other liturgical commentaries produced elsewhere in
the medieval Christian world.
This book addresses the need for maturational growth in
undergraduate and entry-level graduate students as a foundation for
professional and civic development. It presents an engaged learning
curriculum for higher education, Know Your Self, which strengthens
psychological resilience and interpersonal community-building
skills through person-centered growth in five dimensions of self:
bio-behavioral, cognitive-sociocultural, social-emotional,
existential-spiritual, and resilient worldview formation. This
growth promotes well-being and a positive campus culture, preparing
students to build cultures of health, social justice, and peace in
the social systems where they will work and live. This project
emerged from Kass' professional work in humanistic psychology with
Dr. Carl Rogers. Case studies and statistical data illustrate the
formation of health-promoting, pro-social behaviors,
culturally-inclusive community building, and secure existential
attachment. This book will help faculty and student life
professionals address the urgent need in young adults for
person-centered psychospiritual maturation.
This book is a collection of studies on topics related to
subjectivity and selfhood in medieval and early modern philosophy.
The individual contributions approach the theme from a number of
angles varying from cognitive and moral psychology to metaphysics
and epistemology. Instead of a complete overview on the historical
period, the book provides detailed glimpses into some of the most
important figures of the period, such as Augustine, Avicenna,
Aquinas, Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz and Hume. The questions
addressed include the ethical problems of the location of one's
true self and the proper distribution of labour between desire,
passion and reason, and the psychological tasks of accounting for
subjective experience and self-knowledge and determining different
types of self-awareness.
Originally published in 1940, this book provides a thorough
discussion of Rene Descartes philosophy of metaphysics, examining
the three major points of the mind and body, freedom of the will
and religion and science. Specific chapters are devoted to the
Cartesian theory and the Meditations, in particular the Sixth.
In this book, Christopher Celenza provides an intellectual history
of the Italian Renaissance during the long fifteenth century, from
c.1350-1525. His book fills a bibliographic gap between Petrarch
and Machiavelli and offers clear case studies of contemporary
luminaries, including Leonardo Bruni, Poggio Bracciolini, Lorenzo
Valla, Marsilio Ficino, Angelo Poliziano, and Pietro Bembo.
Integrating sources in Italian and Latin, Celenza focuses on the
linked issues of language and philosophy. He also examines the
conditions in which Renaissance intellectuals operated in an era
before the invention of printing, analyzing reading strategies and
showing how texts were consulted, and how new ideas were generated
as a result of conversations, both oral and epistolary. The result
is a volume that offers a new view on both the history of
philosophy and Italian Renaissance intellectual life. It will serve
as a key resource for students and scholars of early modern Italian
humanism and culture.
This book examines the phenomenological anthropology of Edith
Stein. It specifically focuses on the question which Stein
addressed in her work Finite and Eternal Being: What is the
foundational principle that makes the individual unique and
unrepeatable within the human species? Traditional analyses of
Edith Stein’s writings have tended to frame her views on this
issue as being influenced by Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas, while
neglecting her interest in the lesser-known figure of Duns Scotus.
Yet, as this book shows, with regard to the question of
individuality, Stein was critical of Aquinas’ approach, finding
that of Duns Scotus to be more convincing. In order to get to the
heart of Stein’s readings of Duns Scotus, this book looks at her
published writings and her personal correspondence, in addition to
conducting a meticulous analysis of the original codexes on which
her sources were based. Written with diligence and flair, the book
critically evaluates the authenticity of Stein’s sources and
shows how the position of Scotus himself evolved. It highlights the
originality of Stein’s contribution, which was to rediscover the
relevance of Mediaeval scholastic thought and reinterpret it in the
language of the Phenomenological school founded by Edmund Husserl.
Fresh translations of key texts, exhaustive coverage from Plato to
Kant, and detailed commentary by expert scholars of philosophy add
up to make this sourcebook the first and most comprehensive account
of the history of the philosophy of mind. Published at a time when
the philosophy of mind and philosophical psychology are
high-profile domains in current research, the volume will inform
our understanding of philosophical questions by shedding light on
the origins of core conceptual assumptions often arrived at before
the instauration of psychology as a recognized subject in its own
right. The chapters closely follow historical developments
in our understanding of the mind, with sections dedicated to
ancient, medieval Latin and Arabic, and early modern periods of
development. The volume’s structural clarity enables readers to
trace the entire progression of philosophical understanding on
specific topics related to the mind, such as the nature of
perception. Doing so reveals the fascinating contrasts between
current and historical approaches. In addition to its all-inclusive
source material, the volume provides subtle expert commentary that
includes critical introductions to each thematic section as well as
detailed engagement with the central texts. A voluminous
bibliography includes hundreds of primary and secondary sources.
The sheer scale of this new publication sheds light on the
progression, and discontinuities, in our study of the philosophy of
mind, and represents a major new sourcebook in a field of extreme
importance to our understanding of humanity as a whole.
New concepts arise in science when apparently unrelated fields of
knowledge are put together in a coherent way. The recent results in
molecular biology allow to explain the emergence of body patterns
in animals that before could not be understood by zoologists. There
are no ”fancy curiosities” in nature. Every pattern is a
product of a molecular cascade originating in genes and a living
organism arises from the collaboration of these genes with the
outer physical environment. Tropical fishes are as startling in
their colors and geometric circles as peacocks. Tortoises are
covered with the most regular triangles, squares and concentric
circles that can be green, brown or yellow. Parallel scarlet bands
are placed side by side of black ones along the body of snakes.
Zebras and giraffes have patterns which are lessons in geometry,
with their transversal and longitudinal stripes, their circles and
other geometric figures. Monkeys, like the mandrills, have a
spectacularly colored face scarlet nose with blue parallel
flanges and yellow beard. All this geometry turns out to be highly
molecular. The genes are many and have been DNA sequenced. Besides
they not only deal with the coloration of the body but with the
development of the brain and the embryonic process. A precise
scenario of molecular events unravels in the vertebrates. It may
seem far-fetched, but the search for the origin of this geometry
made it mandatory to study the evolution of matter and the origin
of the brain. It turned out that matter from its onset is pervaded
by geometry and that the brain is also a prisoner of this ordered
construction. Moreover, the brain is capable of altering the body
geometry and the geometry of the environment changes the brain.
Nothing spectacular occurred when the brain arrived in evolution.
Not only it came after the eye, which had already established
itself long ago, but it had a modest origin. It started from
sensory cells on the skin that later aggregated into clusters of
neurons that formed ganglia. It also became evident that pigment
cells, that decide the establishment of the body pattern, originate
from the same cell population as neurons (the neural crest cells).
This is a most revealing result because it throws light on the
power that the brain has to rapidly redirect the coloration of the
body and to change its pattern. Recent experiments demonstrate how
the brain changes the body geometry at will and within seconds, an
event that could be hardly conceived earlier. Moreover, this change
is not accidental it is related to the surrounding environment and
is also used as a mating strategy. Chameleons know how to do it as
well as flat fishes and octopuses. No one would have dared to think
that the brain had its own geometry. How could the external
geometry of solids or other figures of our environment be
apprehended by neurons if these had no architecture of their own?
Astonishing was that the so called ”simple cells”, in the
neurons of the primary visual cortex, responded to a bar of light
with an axis of orientation that corresponded to the axis of the
cell’s receptive field. We tend to consider our brain a reliable
organ. But how reliable is it? From the beginning the brain is
obliged to transform reality. Brain imagery involves: form, color,
motion and sleep. Unintentionally these results led to unexpected
philosophical implications. Plato’s pivotal concept that
”forms” exist independently of the material world is reversed.
Atoms have been considered to be imaginary for 2,000 years but at
present they can be photographed, one by one, with electron
microscopes. The reason why geometry has led the way in this
inquiry is due to the fact that where there is geometry there is
utter simplicity coupled to rigorous order that underlies the
phenomenon where it is recognized. Order allows variation but
imposes at the same time a canalization that is patent in what we
call evolution.
This work argues that teleological motives lie at the heart of
Kant's critical philosophy and that a precise analysis of
teleological structures can both illuminate the basic strategy of
its fundamental arguments and provide a key to understanding its
unity. It thus aims, through an examination of each of Kant's major
writings, to provide a detailed interpretation of his claim that
philosophy in the true sense must consist of a teleologia rationis
humanae.The author argues that Kant's critical philosophy forged a
new link between traditional teleological concepts and the basic
structure of rationality, one that would later inform the dynamic
conception of reason at the heart of German Idealism. The process
by which this was accomplished began with Kant's development of a
uniquely teleological conception of systematic unity already in the
precritical period. The individual chapters of this work attempt to
show how Kant adapted and refined this conception of systematic
unity so that it came to form the structural basis for the critical
philosophy.
|
You may like...
The Prophet
Kahlil Gibran
Hardcover
R483
Discovery Miles 4 830
|