|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Epistemology, theory of knowledge
Radical Skepticism and the Shadow of Doubt brings something new to
epistemology both in content and style. At the outset we are asked
to imagine a person named Vatol who grows up in a world containing
numerous people who are brains-in-vats and who hallucinate their
entire lives. Would Vatol have reason to doubt whether he himself
is in contact with reality? If he does have reason to doubt, would
he doubt, or is it impossible for a person to have such doubts? And
how do we ourselves compare to Vatol? After reflection, can we
plausibly claim that Vatol has reason to doubt, but we don't? These
are the questions that provide the novel framework for the debates
in this book. Topics that are treated here in significantly new
ways include: the view that we ought to doubt only when we
philosophize; epistemological "dogmatism"; and connections between
radical doubt and "having a self." The book adopts the innovative
form of a "dialogue/play." The three characters, who are Talmud
students as well as philosophers, hardly limit themselves to pure
philosophy, but regale each other with Talmudic allusions,
reminiscences, jokes, and insults. For them the possibility of
doubt emerges as an existential problem with potentially deep
emotional significance. Setting complex arguments about radical
skepticism within entertaining dialogue, this book can be
recommended for both beginners and specialists.
In this comprehensive tour of the long history and philosophy of
expertise, from ancient Greece to the 20th century, Jamie Carlin
Watson tackles the question of expertise and why we can be
skeptical of what experts say, making a valuable contribution to
contemporary philosophical debates on authority, testimony,
disagreement and trust. His review sketches out the ancient origins
of the concept, discussing its early association with cunning,
skill and authority and covering the sort of training that ancient
thinkers believed was required for expertise. Watson looks at the
evolution of the expert in the middle ages into a type of "genius"
or "innate talent" , moving to the role of psychological research
in 16th-century Germany, the influence of Darwin, the impact of
behaviorism and its interest to computer scientists, and its
transformation into the largely cognitive concept psychologists
study today.
This book offers a rigorous analysis of why commitment matters and
the challenges it presents to a range of believers. Peter Forrest
treats commitment as a response to lost innocence. He considers the
intellectual consequences of this by demonstrating why, for
example, we should not believe in angels. He then explores why
humans are attached to reason and to humanism, recognising the
different commitments made by theist and non-theist humanists.
Finally, he analyses religious faith, specifically fideism,
defining it by way of contrast to Descartes, Pascal and William
James, as well as contemporary philosophers including John
Schellenberg and Lara Buchak. Of particular interest to scholars
working on the philosophy of religion, the book makes the case both
for and against committing to God, recognising that God's divine
character sets up an emotional rather than an intellectual barrier
to commitment to worship.
In an age of internet scrolling and skimming, where concentration
and attention are fast becoming endangered skills, it is timely to
think about the act of reading and the many forms that it can take.
Slow Philosophy: Reading Against the Institution makes the case for
thinking about reading in philosophical terms. Boulous Walker
argues that philosophy involves the patient work of thought; in
this it resembles the work of art, which invites and implores us to
take our time and to engage with the world. At its best, philosophy
teaches us to read slowly; in fact, philosophy is the art of
reading slowly - and this inevitably clashes with many of our
current institutional practices and demands. Slow reading shares
something in common with contemporary social movements, such as
that devoted to slow food; it offers us ways to engage the
complexity of the world. With the help of writers as diverse as
Nietzsche, Wittgenstein, Woolf, Adorno, Levinas, Critchley,
Beauvoir, Le Doeuff, Irigaray, Cixous, Weil, and others, Boulous
Walker offers a foundational text in the emerging field of slow
philosophy, one that explores the importance of unhurried time in
establishing our institutional encounters with complex and
demanding works.
What is given to us in conscious experience? The Given is an
attempt to answer this question and in this way contribute to a
general theory of mental content. The content of conscious
experience is understood to be absolutely everything that is given
to one, experientially, in the having of an experience. Michelle
Montague focuses on the analysis of conscious perception, conscious
emotion, and conscious thought, and deploys three fundamental
notions in addition to the fundamental notion of content: the
notions of intentionality, phenomenology, and consciousness. She
argues that all experience essentially involves all four things,
and that the key to an adequate general theory of what is given in
experience-of 'the given'-lies in giving a correct specification of
the nature of these four things and the relations between them.
Montague argues that conscious perception, conscious thought, and
conscious emotion each have a distinctive, irreducible kind of
phenomenology-what she calls 'sensory phenomenology', 'cognitive
phenomenology', and 'evaluative phenomenology' respectively-and
that these kinds of phenomenology are essential in accounting for
the intentionality of these mental phenomena.
What are the reasons for believing scientific theories to be true?
The contemporary debate around scientific realism exposes questions
about the very nature of scientific knowledge. A Critical
Introduction to Scientific Realism explores and advances the main
topics of the debate, allowing epistemologists to make new
connections with the philosophy of science. Moving from its origins
in logical positivism to some of the most recent issues discussed
in the literature, this critical introduction covers the
no-miracles argument, the pessimistic meta-induction and structural
realism. Placing arguments in their historical context, Paul Dicken
approaches scientific realism debate as a particular instance of
our more general epistemological investigations. The recurrent
theme is that the scientific realism debate is in fact a
pseudo-philosophical question. Concerned with the methodology of
the scientific realism debate, Dicken asks what it means to offer
an epistemological assessment of our scientific practices. Taking
those practices as a guide to our epistemological reflections, A
Critical Introduction to Scientific Realism fills a gap in current
introductory texts and presents a fresh approach to understanding a
crucial debate.
Throughout his career, Keith Hossack has made outstanding
contributions to the theory of knowledge, metaphysics and the
philosophy of mathematics. This collection of previously
unpublished papers begins with a focus on Hossack's conception of
the nature of knowledge, his metaphysics of facts and his account
of the relations between knowledge, agents and facts. Attention
moves to Hossack's philosophy of mind and the nature of
consciousness, before turning to the notion of necessity and its
interaction with a priori knowledge. Hossack's views on the nature
of proof, logical truth, conditionals and generality are discussed
in depth. In the final chapters, questions about the identity of
mathematical objects and our knowledge of them take centre stage,
together with questions about the necessity and generality of
mathematical and logical truths. Knowledge, Number and Reality
represents some of the most vibrant discussions taking place in
analytic philosophy today.
This book aims to study, from an approach linked to epistemology
and the history of ideas, the evolution of economic science and its
differing seminal systems. Today mainstream economics solves
certain problems chosen within the scope of "normal science,"
without questioning the epistemological foundations that support
the paradigm within which they were conceived. Contrary to a
Neoclassical interpretation, the historicist interpretation shows
that, from the incommensurability of the different paradigms, it is
impossible to conceive of a progress of economic science, in a
long-term perspective. This book ultimately reveals, from the
different economic schools of thought analyzed, that there is no
pure form of episteme, or system of understanding. Each concrete
episteme in the history of economic thought is by nature hybrid in
the sense that it contains components from preceding systems of
knowledge.
Superficially, Wittgenstein and Heidegger seem worlds apart: they
worked in different philosophical traditions, seemed mostly
ignorant of one another's work, and Wittgenstein's terse aphorisms
in plain language could not be farther stylistically from
Heidegger's difficult prose. Nevertheless, Wittgenstein's
Philosophical Investigations and Heidegger's Being and Time share a
number of striking parallels. In particular, this book shows that
both authors manifest a similar concern with authenticity. David
Egan develops this position in three stages. Part One explores the
emphasis both philosophers place on the everyday, and how this
emphasis brings with it a methodological focus on recovering what
we already know rather than advancing novel theses. Part Two argues
that the dynamic of authenticity and inauthenticity in Being and
Time finds homologies in Philosophical Investigations. Here Egan
particularly articulates and defends a conception of authenticity
in Wittgenstein that emphasizes the responsiveness and reciprocity
of play. Part Three considers how both philosophers' conceptions of
authenticity apply reflexively to their own work: each is concerned
not only with the question of what it means to exist authentically
but also with the question of what it means to do philosophy
authentically. For both authors, the problematic of authenticity is
intimately linked to the question of philosophical method.
This book examines the U.S economy from 1967 to 2011 and utilizes a
new method to predict the future of the economy as far ahead as
2030. This new method uses population subgroup data. Variables used
in the cross-sectional matrix include ethnicity, sex, age, and
average personal income of those having personal income. The
mathematical basis, the data used, and the results are all
presented in graphic form. The estimates are compared to National
Bureau of Economic Research Dating Committee data. Projections
using estimates from the U.S. Bureau of Census are used to further
project personal income, personal income annual change, and
disposable personal income to 2030. The book concludes that the New
Energy Movement and their development of non-polluting energy and
electricity production methods that do not consume uranium,
radioactive material, or fossil fuels. Therefore, large amounts of
money should be invested in these devices, their development, and
implementation.
|
You may like...
Witches Tarot
Ellen Dugan
Paperback
(1)
R709
Discovery Miles 7 090
|