|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Epistemology, theory of knowledge
Investigation of the Percept is a short (eight verses and a three
page autocommentary) work that focuses on issues of perception and
epistemology. Its author, Dignaga, was one of the most influential
figures in the Indian Buddhist epistemological tradition, and his
ideas had a profound and wide-ranging impact in India, Tibet, and
China. The work inspired more than twenty commentaries throughout
East Asia and three in Tibet, the most recent in 2014. This book is
the first of its kind in Buddhist studies: a comprehensive history
of a text and its commentarial tradition. The volume editors
translate the root text and commentary, along with Indian and
Tibetan commentaries, providing detailed analyses of the
commentarial innovations of each author, as well as critically
edited versions of all texts and extant Sanskrit fragments of
passages. The team-based approach made it possible to study and
translate a corpus of treatises in Sanskrit, Tibetan, and Chinese
and to employ the methods of critical philology and cross-cultural
philosophy to provide readers with a rich collection of studies and
translations, along with detailed philosophical analyses that open
up the intriguing implications of Dignaga's thought and demonstrate
the diversity of commentarial approaches to his text. This rich
text has inspired some of the greatest minds in India and Tibet. It
explores some of the key issues of Buddhist epistemology: the
relationship between minds and their percepts, the problems of
idealism and realism, and error and misperception.
We must all make choices about how we want to live. We evaluate our
possibilities by relying on historical, moral, personal, political,
religious, and scientific modes of evaluations, but the values and
reasons that follow from them conflict. Philosophical problems are
forced on us when we try to cope with such conflicts. There are
reasons for and against all proposed ways of coping with the
conflicts, but none of them has been generally accepted by
reasonable thinkers. The constructive aim of The Nature of
Philosophical Problems is to propose a way of understanding the
nature of such philosophical problems, explain why they occur, why
they are perennial, and propose a pluralist approach as the most
reasonable way of coping with them. This approach is practical,
context-dependent, and particular. It follows from it that the
recurrence of philosophical problems is not a defect, but a welcome
consequence of the richness of our modes of understanding that
enlarges the range of possibilities by which we might choose to
live. The critical aim of the book is to give reasons against both
the absolutist attempt to find an overriding value or principle for
resolving philosophical problems and of the relativist claim that
reasons unavoidably come to an end and how we want to live is
ultimately a matter of personal preference, not of reasons.
Why should inquiry be possible, only if some knowledge is required
to guide it, as conventionally understood? Contrary to the
conventional wisdom held by many thinkers in all human history
hitherto existing, there are some fundamental dialectic principles
hidden behind any categories of understanding in knowing. And these
principles impose some constraints, at both methodological and
ontological levels, together with other levels in culture, society,
nature, and the mind - on how reality is to be understood.
Furthermore, the specific categories of understanding (as
conventionally understood), even if valid at all (which are often
not the case), are often not that important, when compared with
these more fundamental dialectic principles hidden behind them. The
focus on understanding the nature of knowledge has been much
misplaced, in this sense, in the intellectual history hitherto
existing, and much time and talent have been wasted for something
less important. If true, this thesis will alter the way of how
knowledge is to be understood across the board.
Is written by a highly knowledgeable and well-respected scholarA
new theory called The Holistic Theory of KnowledgeA comprehensive
analysis of knowledge in relation to methodology and ontology, from
the perspectives of nature, the mind, society, and culture
Katja Maria Vogt's Belief and Truth: A Skeptic Reading of Plato
explores a Socratic intuition about the difference between belief
and knowledge. Beliefs - doxai - are deficient cognitive attitudes.
In believing something, one accepts some content as true without
knowing that it is true; one holds something to be true that could
turn out to be false. Since our actions reflect what we hold to be
true, holding beliefs is potentially harmful for oneself and
others. Accordingly, beliefs are ethically worrisome and even, in
the words of Plato's Socrates, "shameful." As Vogt argues, this is
a serious philosophical proposal and it speaks to intuitions we are
likely to share. But it involves a notion of belief that is rather
different from contemporary notions. Today, it is a widespread
assumption that true beliefs are better than false beliefs, and
that some true beliefs (perhaps those that come with
justifications) qualify as knowledge. Socratic epistemology offers
a genuinely different picture. In aiming for knowledge, one must
aim to get rid of beliefs. Knowledge does not entail belief -
belief and knowledge differ in such important ways that they cannot
both count as kinds of belief. As long as one does not have
knowledge, one should reserve judgment and investigate by thinking
through possible ways of seeing things. According to Vogt, the
ancient skeptics and Stoics draw many of these ideas from Plato's
dialogues, revising Socratic-Platonic arguments as they see fit.
Belief and Truth retraces their steps through interpretations of
the Apology, Ion, Republic, Theaetetus, and Philebus, reconstructs
Pyrrhonian investigation and thought, and illuminates the
connections between ancient skepticism and relativism, as well as
the Stoic view that beliefs do not even merit the evaluations
"true" and "false."
Indian thought is well known for diverse philosophical and
contemplative excursions into the nature of selfhood. Led by
Buddhists and the yoga traditions of Hinduism and Jainism, Indian
thinkers have engaged in a rigorous analysis and
reconceptualization of our common notion of self. Less understood
is the way in which such theories of self intersect with issues
involving agency and free will; yet such intersections are
profoundly important, as all major schools of Indian thought
recognize that moral goodness and religious fulfillment depend on
the proper understanding of personal agency. Moreover, their
individual conceptions of agency and freedom are typically nodes by
which an entire school's epistemological, ethical, and metaphysical
perspectives come together as a systematic whole. Free Will,
Agency, and Selfhood in Indian Philosophy explores the contours of
this issue, from the perspectives of the major schools of Indian
thought. With new essays by leading specialists in each field, this
volume provides rigorous analysis of the network of issues
surrounding agency and freedom as developed within Indian thought.
Ernest Lepore and Kirk Ludwig examine the foundations and
applications of Davidson's influential program of truth-theoretic
semantics for natural languages. The program uses an axiomatic
truth theory for a language, which meets certain constraints, to
serve the goals of a compositional meaning theory. Lepore and
Ludwig explain and clarify the motivations for the approach, and
then consider how to apply the framework to a range of important
natural language constructions, including quantifiers, proper
names, indexicals, simple and complex demonstratives, quotation,
adjectives and adverbs, the simple and perfect tenses, temporal
adverbials and temporal quantifiers, tense in sentential complement
clauses, attitude and indirect discourse reports, and the problem
of interrogative and imperative sentences. They not only discuss
Davidson's own contributions to these subjects but consider
criticisms, developments, and alternatives as well. They conclude
with a discussion of logical form in natural language in light of
the approach, the role of the concept of truth in the program, and
Davidson's view of it. Anyone working on meaning will find this
book invaluable.
A unifying theme of Loeb's work is epistemological - that Descartes
and Hume advance theories of knowledge that rely on a substantial
'naturalistic' component, adopting one or another member of a
cluster of psychological properties of beliefs as the goal of
inquiry and the standard for assessing belief-forming mechanisms.
Thus Loeb shows a surprising affinity between the epistemologies of
the two figures -- surprising because they are often thought of as
polar opposites in this respect.
Descartes and Hume are unique in that their philosophical texts are
accessible beyond just a narrow audience in the history of
philosophy; their ideas continue to be a vital part of the field at
large. This volume will thus appeal to advanced students and
scholars not just in the history of early modern philosophy but in
epistemology and other core areas of the discipline.
The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception is a survey by
leading philosophical thinkers of contemporary issues and new
thinking in philosophy of perception. It includes sections on the
history of the subject, introductions to contemporary issues in the
epistemology, ontology and aesthetics of perception, treatments of
the individual sense modalities and of the things we perceive by
means of them, and a consideration of how perceptual information is
integrated and consolidated. New analytic tools and applications to
other areas of philosophy are discussed in depth. Each of the
forty-five entries is written by a leading expert, some
collaborating with younger figures; each seeks to introduce the
reader to a broad range of issues. All contain new ideas on the
topics covered; together they demonstrate the vigour and innovative
zeal of a young field. The book is accessible to anybody who has an
intellectual interest in issues concerning perception.
What if anything justifies us in believing the testimony of others?
How should we react to disagreement between ourselves and our
peers, and to disagreement among the experts when we ourselves are
novices? Can beliefs be held by groups of people in addition to the
people composing those groups? And if so, how should groups go
about forming their beliefs? How should we design social systems,
such as legal juries and scientific research-sharing schemes, to
promote knowledge among the people who engage in them? When
different groups of people judge different beliefs to be justified,
how can we tell which groups are correct? These questions are at
the heart of the vital discipline of social epistemology. The
classic articles in this volume address these questions in ways
that are both cutting-edge and easy to understand. This volume will
be of great interest to scholars and students in epistemology.
Perception is our main source of epistemic access to the outside
world. Perception and Basic Beliefs addresses two central questions
in epistemology: which beliefs are epistemologically basic (i.e.,
noninferentially justified) and where does perception end and
inferential cognition begin. Jack Lyons offers a highly externalist
theory, arguing that what makes a belief a basic belief or a
perceptual belief is determined by the nature of the cognitive
system, or module, that produced the beliefs. On this view, the
sensory experiences that typically accompany perceptual beliefs
play no indispensable role in the justification of these beliefs,
and one can have perceptual beliefs--justified perceptual
beliefs--even in the absence of any sensory experiences whatsoever.
Lyons develops a general theory of basic beliefs and argues that
perceptual beliefs are a species of basic beliefs. This results
from the fact that perceptual modules are a special type of basic
belief-producing modules. Importantly, some beliefs are not the
outputs of this class of cognitive module; these beliefs are
therefore non-basic, thus requiring inferential support from other
beliefs for their justification. This last point is used to defend
a reliabilist epistemology against an important class of
traditional objections (where the agent uses a reliable process
that she doesn't know to be reliable).
Perception and Basic Beliefs brings together an important treatment
of these major epistemological topics and provides a positive
solution to the traditional problem of the external world.
Adrian Bardon's A Brief History of the Philosophy of Time is a
short yet thorough introduction to the history, philosophy, and
science of the study of time-from the pre-Socratic philosophers
through Einstein and beyond. Its treatment is roughly
chronological, starting with the ancient Greek philosophers
Heraclitus and Parmenides and proceeding through the history of
Western philosophy and science up to the present. Using
illustrations and keeping technical language to a minimum, A Brief
History of the Philosophy of Time covers subjects such as time and
change, the experience of time, physical and metaphysical
approaches to the nature of time, the direction of time,
time-travel, time and freedom of the will, and scientific and
philosophical approaches to eternity and the beginning of time.
Bardon brings the resources of over 2500 years of philosophy and
science to bear on some of humanity's most fundamental and enduring
questions.
We typically think we have free will. But how could we have free
will, if for anything we do, it was already true in the distant
past that we would do that thing? Or how could we have free will,
if God already knows in advance all the details of our lives? Such
issues raise the specter of "fatalism". This book collects sixteen
previously published articles on fatalism, truths about the future,
and the relationship between divine foreknowledge and human
freedom, and includes a substantial introductory essay and
bibliography. Many of the pieces collected here build bridges
between discussions of human freedom and recent developments in
other areas of metaphysics, such as philosophy of time. Ideal for
courses in free will, metaphysics, and philosophy of religion,
Freedom, Fatalism, and Foreknowledge will encourage important new
directions in thinking about free will, time, and truth.
In this short monograph, John Horty explores the difficulties
presented for Gottlob Frege's semantic theory, as well as its
modern descendents, by the treatment of defined expressions.
The book begins by focusing on the psychological constraints
governing Frege's notion of sense, or meaning, and argues that,
given these constraints, even the treatment of simple stipulative
definitions led Frege to important difficulties. Horty is able to
suggest ways out of these difficulties that are both
philosophically and logically plausible and Fregean in spirit. This
discussion is then connected to a number of more familiar topics,
such as indexicality and the discussion of concepts in recent
theories of mind and language.
In the latter part of the book, after introducing a simple
semantic model of senses as procedures, Horty considers the
problems that definitions present for Frege's idea that the sense
of an expression should mirror its grammatical structure. The
requirement can be satisfied, he argues, only if defined
expressions--and incomplete expressions as well--are assigned
senses of their own, rather than treated contextually. He then
explores one way in which these senses might be reified within the
procedural model, drawing on ideas from work in the semantics of
computer programming languages.
With its combination of technical semantics and history of
philosophy, Horty's book tackles some of the hardest questions in
the philosophy of language. It should interest philosophers,
logicians, and linguists.
This book is not aimed at exhuming Kant, but resurrecting him. It
is inspired by the Critique of Pure Reason , yet is not about it:
perhaps over-ambitiously, it tries to delineate not Kant's
metaphysics of experience but the truth of the matter. The author
shows rather than says where he agrees and disagrees with the first
Critique , in so far as he understood that profound but obscure,
over-systematic yet carelessly written, inspiring and infuriating,
magnificent but flawed masterpiece. The book attempts a highly
systematic presentation, in which the very form of the work
reflects the content of the arguments. Kant is often derided for
the extent to which he allows his penchant for architectonic
structure to distort his insights, but it is argued that he had the
right instinct in assuming that there must be some systematic way
in which the necessary conditions for experience fit together. The
contemporary trend in analytical philosophy seems to be towards
ever more specialized, jargon-infested work, and there is a need to
draw things together into a wider view that can be more generally
appreciated.
What do we see? We are visually conscious of colors and shapes, but
are we also visually conscious of complex properties such as being
John Malkovich? In this book, Susanna Siegel develops a framework
for understanding the contents of visual experience, and argues
that these contents involve all sorts of complex properties. Siegel
starts by analyzing the notion of the contents of experience, and
by arguing that theorists of all stripes should accept that
experiences have contents. She then introduces a method for
discovering the contents of experience: the method of phenomenal
contrast. This method relies only minimally on introspection, and
allows rigorous support for claims about experience. She then
applies the method to make the case that we are conscious of many
kinds of properties, of all sorts of causal properties, and of many
other complex properties. She goes on to use the method to help
analyze difficult questions about our consciousness of objects and
their role in the contents of experience, and to reconceptualize
the distinction between perception and sensation. Siegel's results
are important for many areas of philosophy, including the
philosophy of mind, epistemology, and the philosophy of science.
They are also important for the psychology and cognitive
neuroscience of vision.
For centuries, philosophers have been puzzled by the fact that
people often respect moral obligations as a matter of principle,
setting aside considerations of self-interest. In more recent
years, social scientists have been puzzled by the more general
phenomenon of rule-following, the fact that people often abide by
social norms even when doing so produces undesirable consequences.
Experimental game theorists have demonstrated conclusively that the
old-fashioned picture of "economic man," constantly reoptimizing in
order to maximize utility in all circumstances, cannot provide
adequate foundations for a general theory of rational action. The
dominant response, however, has been a slide toward irrationalism.
If people are ignoring the consequences of their actions, it is
claimed, it must be because they are making some sort of a mistake.
In Following the Rules, Joseph Heath attempts to reverse this
trend, by showing how rule-following can be understood as an
essential element of rational action. The first step involves
showing how rational choice theory can be modified to incorporate
deontic constraint as a feature of rational deliberation. The
second involves disarming the suspicion that there is something
mysterious or irrational about the psychological states underlying
rule-following. According to Heath, human rationality is a
by-product of the so-called "language upgrade" that we receive as a
consequence of the development of specific social practices. As a
result, certain constitutive features of our social
environment-such as the rule-governed structure of social
life-migrate inwards, and become constitutive features of our
psychological faculties. This in turn explains why there is an
indissoluble bond between practical rationality and deontic
constraint. In the end, what Heath offers is a naturalistic,
evolutionary argument in favor of the traditional Kantian view that
there is an internal connection between being a rational agent and
feeling the force of one's moral obligations.
In this short, lucid, rich book Michael Dummett sets out his views
about some of the deepest questions in philosophy. The fundamental
question of metaphysics is: what does reality consist of? To answer
this, Dummett holds, it is necessary to say what kinds of fact
obtain, and what constitutes their holding good. Facts correspond
with true propositions, or true thoughts: when we know which
propositions, or thoughts, in general, are true, we shall know what
facts there are in general. Dummett considers the relation between
metaphysics, our conception of the constitution of reality, and
semantics, the theory that explains how statements are determined
as true or as false in terms of their composition out of their
constituent expressions. He investigates the two concepts on which
the bridge that connects semantics to metaphysics rests, meaning
and truth, and the role of justification in a theory of meaning. He
then examines the special semantic and metaphysical issues that
arise with relation to time and tense. On this basis Dummett puts
forward his controversial view of reality as indeterminate: there
may be no fact of the matter about whether an object does or does
not have a given property. We have to relinquish our deep-held
realist understanding of language, the illusion that we know what
it is for any proposition that we can frame to be true
independently of our having any means of recognizing its truth, and
accept that truth depends on our capacity to apprehend it. Dummett
concludes with a chapter about God.
In Everything Ancient Was Once New, Emalani Case explores
Indigenous persistence through the concept of Kahiki, a term that
is at once both an ancestral homeland for Kanaka Maoli (Hawaiians)
and the knowledge that there is life to be found beyond Hawai'i's
shores. It is therefore both a symbol of ancestral connection and
the potential that comes with remembering and acting upon that
connection. Tracing physical, historical, intellectual, and
spiritual journeys to and from Kahiki, Emalani frames it as a place
of refuge and sanctuary, a place where ancient knowledge can
constantly be made anew. It is in Kahiki, she argues, and in the
sanctuary it creates, that today's Kanaka Maoli can find safety and
reprieve from the continued onslaught of settler colonial violence,
while also confronting some of the often uncomfortable and
challenging realities of being Indigenous in Hawai'i, in the
Pacific, and in the world. Each chapter of the book engages with
Kahiki as a shifting term, employed by Kanaka Maoli to explain
their lives and experiences to themselves at different points in
history. In doing so, Everything Ancient Was Once New proposes and
argues for reactivated and reinvigorated engagements with Kahiki,
each supporting ongoing work aimed at decolonizing physical and
ideological spaces, and reconnecting Kanaka Maoli to other peoples
and places in the Pacific region and beyond in ways that are both
purposeful and meaningful. In the book, Kahiki is therefore traced
through pivotal moments in history and critical moments in
contemporary times, explaining that while not always mentioned by
name, the idea of Kahiki was, and is, always full of potential. In
writing that is both personal and theoretical, Emalani weaves the
past and the present together, reflecting on ancient concepts and
their continued relevance in movements to protect lands, waters,
and oceans; to fight for social justice; to reexamine our
responsibilities and obligations to each other across the Pacific
region; and to open space for continued dialogue on what it means
to be Indigenous both when at home and when away. Combining
personal narrative and reflection with research and critical
analysis, Everything Ancient Was Once New journeys to and from
Kahiki, the sanctuary for reflection, deep learning, and continued
dreaming with the past, in the present, and far into the future.
|
|