|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Epistemology, theory of knowledge
We must all make choices about how we want to live. We evaluate our
possibilities by relying on historical, moral, personal, political,
religious, and scientific modes of evaluations, but the values and
reasons that follow from them conflict. Philosophical problems are
forced on us when we try to cope with such conflicts. There are
reasons for and against all proposed ways of coping with the
conflicts, but none of them has been generally accepted by
reasonable thinkers. The constructive aim of The Nature of
Philosophical Problems is to propose a way of understanding the
nature of such philosophical problems, explain why they occur, why
they are perennial, and propose a pluralist approach as the most
reasonable way of coping with them. This approach is practical,
context-dependent, and particular. It follows from it that the
recurrence of philosophical problems is not a defect, but a welcome
consequence of the richness of our modes of understanding that
enlarges the range of possibilities by which we might choose to
live. The critical aim of the book is to give reasons against both
the absolutist attempt to find an overriding value or principle for
resolving philosophical problems and of the relativist claim that
reasons unavoidably come to an end and how we want to live is
ultimately a matter of personal preference, not of reasons.
Ernest Lepore and Kirk Ludwig examine the foundations and
applications of Davidson's influential program of truth-theoretic
semantics for natural languages. The program uses an axiomatic
truth theory for a language, which meets certain constraints, to
serve the goals of a compositional meaning theory. Lepore and
Ludwig explain and clarify the motivations for the approach, and
then consider how to apply the framework to a range of important
natural language constructions, including quantifiers, proper
names, indexicals, simple and complex demonstratives, quotation,
adjectives and adverbs, the simple and perfect tenses, temporal
adverbials and temporal quantifiers, tense in sentential complement
clauses, attitude and indirect discourse reports, and the problem
of interrogative and imperative sentences. They not only discuss
Davidson's own contributions to these subjects but consider
criticisms, developments, and alternatives as well. They conclude
with a discussion of logical form in natural language in light of
the approach, the role of the concept of truth in the program, and
Davidson's view of it. Anyone working on meaning will find this
book invaluable.
Is truth objective or relative? What exists independently of our
minds? This book is about these two questions. The essays in its
pages variously defend and critique answers to each, grapple over
the proper methodology for addressing them, and wonder whether
either question is worth pursuing. In so doing, they carry on a
long and esteemed tradition - for our two questions are among the
oldest of philosophical issues, and have vexed almost every major
philosopher, from Plato, to Kant to Wittgenstein. Fifteen eminent
contributors bring fresh perspectives, renewed energy and original
answers to debates which have been the focus of a tremendous amount
of interest in the last three decades both within philosophy and
the culture at large.
Susanne Bobzien presents the definitive study of one of the most important intellectual legacies of the ancient Greeks: the Stoic theory of causal determinism. She reconstructs the theory and discusses how the Stoics (third century BC to second century AD) justified it, and how it relates to their views on possibility, action, freedom, moral responsibility, and many other topics. She demonstrates the considerable philosophical richness and power that these ideas retain today.
In this incisive new monograph one of Britain's most eminent
philosophers explores the often overlooked tension between
voluntariness and involuntariness in human cognition. He seeks to
counter the widespread tendency for analytic epistemology to be
dominated by the concept of belief. Is scientific knowledge
properly conceived as being embodied, at its best, in a passive
feeling of belief or in an active policy of acceptance? Should a
jury's verdict declare what its members involuntarily believe or
what they voluntarily accept? And should statements and assertions
be presumed to express what their authors believe or what they
accept? Does such a distinction between belief and acceptance help
to resolve the paradoxes of self-deception and akrasia? Must people
be taken to believe everything entailed by what they believe, or
merely to accept everything entailed by what they accept? Through a
systematic examination of these problems, the author sheds new
light on issues of crucial importance in contemporary epistemology,
philosophy of mind, and cognitive science.
Disjunctivism has attracted considerable philosophical attention in
recent years: it has been the source of a lively and extended
debate spanning the philosophy of perception, epistemology, and the
philosophy of action. Adrian Haddock and Fiona Macpherson present
seventeen specially written essays, which examine the different
forms of disjunctivism and explore the connections between them.
This volume will be an essential resource for anyone working in the
central areas of philosophy, and the starting point for future
research in this fascinating field.
Self-knowledge is the focus of considerable attention from
philosophers: Knowing Our Own Minds gives a much-needed overview of
current work on the subject, bringing together new essays by
leading figures. Knowledge of one's own sensations, desires,
intentions, thoughts, beliefs, and other attitudes is
characteristically different from other kinds of knowledge, such as
knowledge of other people's mental attributes: it has greater
immediacy, authority, and salience. The first six chapters examine
philosophical questions raised by these features of self-knowledge.
The next two look at the role of our knowledge of our own
psychological states in our functioning as rational agents. The
third group of essays examine the tension between the distinctive
characteristics of self-knowledge and arguments that psychological
content is externally-socially and environmentally-determined. The
final pair of chapters extend the discussion to knowledge of one's
own language. Together these original, stimulating, and closely
interlinked essays demonstrate the special relevance of
self-knowledge to a broad range of issues in epistemology,
philosophy of mind, and philosophy of language.
In Phenomenology and Lacan on Schizophrenia, Alphonse De Waelhens
provides a clear summary of Lacan's theory of schizophrenia, as
Lacan derived it from his commentary of Freud's study of the
Memoirs of Schreber. De Waelhens also shows how Lacan's
understanding of the schizophrenic as having a defective relation
to language can also explain four other characteristics of
schizophrenic behavior: the fragmented body image; lack of
realistic evaluation of the world; so-called bisexuality; and
confusion of birth and death. Third, De Waelhens gives a Hegelian
interpretation of the pre-Oedipal experience of the child. He makes
use of Freud's study on his grand-child using a bobbin and later
the words fort-da (away-here), to demonstrate that a transitional
object allows the child to take distance from its attachment to the
mother so that it can start to separate itself from the mother.
Taking distance is, according to De Waelhens, introducing the
Hegelian negative, which is the birth of the subject. Fourth, De
Waelhens gives a dialectic reading of the history of German and
French psychiatry. He shows the epistemological contradictions in
the work of some of the great nineteenth century psychiatrists
relying too exclusively on a biological model of schizophrenia.In
his contribution to this volume, Wilfried Ver Eecke draws several
lessons from evaluating the literature on schizophrenia. He argues
that epistemologically neither a biological nor a psychological
method of reasoning can capture all the factors that can play a
role in the creation of schizophrenia. He relies heavily, but not
exclusively, on the Finnish studies of Tienari, Myrhman, and
Wahlberg and their colleagues to provide statistical evidence that
non-biological factors also play an important role in causing
schizophrenia. He relies heavily, but again not exclusively, on the
study by Karon and VandenBos to demonstrate statistically the
efficiency of psychodynamically inspired therapy of
schizophrenics.Ver Eecke also addresses an apparent inconsistency
in De Waelhens' presentation of Lacan's theory of schizophrenia.
Where De Waelhens seemed to argue at one time that the mother
figure was the crucial figure to explain schizophrenia (leading to
a defective relation to the body) and at another time that it was
the role of the father which was crucial (leading to a defective
relation to language and the symbolic), there Ver Eecke argues that
the defective function of each influences the function of the
other. He then draws a conclusion for the therapy of
schizophrenics: to be helpful a therapist will have to address both
deficiencies. The problem for treating schizophrenics is that
correcting an unconscious deficiency to the body-a deficiency in
the imaginary-requires a totally different kind of intervention
than an attempt to correct a symbolic deficiency-a deficiency in
the paternal function. A correction of the imaginary requires a
kind of maternal mirroring; a correction of the symbolic requires
making a distinction or a prohibition stick. One further difficulty
arises. Psychotherapy uses language in its treatment. However,
language in schizophrenics is deficient. We can therefore expect
that language will be inefficient. This is so unless the therapist
uses language, first, to make a repair at the imaginary level and
only thereafter makes an attempt to make a correction in the
symbolic. In analyzing successful therapeutic techniques reported
by several therapists Ver Eecke discovers that all of them first
try to repair the imaginary before they attempt to make corrections
to the symbolic.
Proclus (412-485 A.D.) was one of the last official 'successors' of
Plato at the head of the Academy in Athens at the end of Antiquity,
before the school was finally closed down in 529. As a prolific
author of systematic works on a wide range of topics and one of the
most influential commentators on Plato of all times, the legacy of
Proclus in the cultural history of the west can hardly be
overestimated. This book introduces the reader to Proclus' life and
works, his place in the Platonic tradition of Antiquity and the
influence his work exerted in later ages. Various chapters are
devoted to Proclus' metaphysical system, including his doctrines
about the first principle of all reality, the One, and about the
Forms and the soul. The broad range of Proclus' thought is further
illustrated by highlighting his contribution to philosophy of
nature, scientific theory, theory of knowledge and philosophy of
language. Finally, also his most original doctrines on evil and
providence, his Neoplatonic virtue ethics, his complex views on
theology and religious practice, and his metaphysical aesthetics
receive separate treatments. This book is the first to bring
together the leading scholars in the field and to present a state
of the art of Proclean studies today. In doing so, it provides the
most comprehensive introduction to Proclus' thought currently
available.
This is the third volume of philosophical writings by Donald
Davidson. He presents a selection of his work on knowledge, mind,
and language from the 1980s and the 1990s. We all have knowledge of
our own minds, knowledge of the contents of other minds, and
knowledge of the shared environment. Davidson examines the nature
and status of each of these three sorts of knowledge, and the
connections and differences among them. Along the way he has
illuminating things to say about truth, human rationality, and the
relations between language, thought, and the world.
Rae Langton offers a new interpretation and defence of Kant's
doctrine of things in themselves. Kant distinguishes things in
themselves from phenomena, and in so doing he makes a metaphysical
distinction between intrinsic and relational properties of
substances. Kant says that phenomena-things as we know them-consist
'entirely of relations', by which he means forces. His claim that
we have no knowledge of things in themselves is not idealism, but
epistemic humility: we have no knowledge of the intrinsic
properties of substances. This humility has its roots in some
plausible philosophical beliefs: an empiricist belief in the
receptivity of human knowledge and a metaphysical belief in the
irreducibility of relational properties. Langton's interpretation
vindicates Kant's scientific realism, and shows his
primary/secondary quality distinction to be superior even to
modern-day competitors. And it answers the famous charge that
Kant's tale of things in themselves is one that makes itself
untellable.
This book is not aimed at exhuming Kant, but resurrecting him. It
is inspired by the Critique of Pure Reason , yet is not about it:
perhaps over-ambitiously, it tries to delineate not Kant's
metaphysics of experience but the truth of the matter. The author
shows rather than says where he agrees and disagrees with the first
Critique , in so far as he understood that profound but obscure,
over-systematic yet carelessly written, inspiring and infuriating,
magnificent but flawed masterpiece. The book attempts a highly
systematic presentation, in which the very form of the work
reflects the content of the arguments. Kant is often derided for
the extent to which he allows his penchant for architectonic
structure to distort his insights, but it is argued that he had the
right instinct in assuming that there must be some systematic way
in which the necessary conditions for experience fit together. The
contemporary trend in analytical philosophy seems to be towards
ever more specialized, jargon-infested work, and there is a need to
draw things together into a wider view that can be more generally
appreciated.
Colin Howson offers a solution to one of the central, unsolved problems of Western philosophy, the problem of induction. In the mid-eighteenth century David Hume argued that successful prediction tells us nothing about the truth or probable truth of the predicting theory. Howson claims that Hume's argument is correct, and examines what follows about the relation between science and its empirical base.
In Contradiction advocates and defends the view that there are true
contradictions (dialetheism), a view that flies in the face of
orthodoxy in Western philosophy since Aristotle. The book has been
at the center of the controversies surrounding dialetheism ever
since its first publication in
1987. This second edition of the book substantially expands upon
the original in various ways, and also contains the author's
reflections on developments over the last two decades. Further
aspects of dialetheism are discussed in the companion volume, Doubt
Truth to be a Liar, also published by
Oxford University Press in 2006.
In this short, lucid, rich book Michael Dummett sets out his views
about some of the deepest questions in philosophy. The fundamental
question of metaphysics is: what does reality consist of? To answer
this, Dummett holds, it is necessary to say what kinds of fact
obtain, and what constitutes their holding good. Facts correspond
with true propositions, or true thoughts: when we know which
propositions, or thoughts, in general, are true, we shall know what
facts there are in general. Dummett considers the relation between
metaphysics, our conception of the constitution of reality, and
semantics, the theory that explains how statements are determined
as true or as false in terms of their composition out of their
constituent expressions. He investigates the two concepts on which
the bridge that connects semantics to metaphysics rests, meaning
and truth, and the role of justification in a theory of meaning. He
then examines the special semantic and metaphysical issues that
arise with relation to time and tense. On this basis Dummett puts
forward his controversial view of reality as indeterminate: there
may be no fact of the matter about whether an object does or does
not have a given property. We have to relinquish our deep-held
realist understanding of language, the illusion that we know what
it is for any proposition that we can frame to be true
independently of our having any means of recognizing its truth, and
accept that truth depends on our capacity to apprehend it. Dummett
concludes with a chapter about God.
Now in a new edition, this volume updates Davidson's exceptional
Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (1984), which set out his
enormously influential philosophy of language. The original volume
remains a central point of reference, and a focus of controversy,
with its impact extending into linguistic theory, philosophy of
mind, and epistemology. Addressing a central question--what it is
for words to mean what they do--and featuring a previously
uncollected, additional essay, this work will appeal to a wide
audience of philosophers, linguists, and psychologists.
Frederick F. Schmitt offers a systematic interpretation of David
Hume's epistemology, as it is presented in the indispensable A
Treatise of Human Nature. Hume's text alternately manifests
scepticism, empiricism, and naturalism in epistemology.
Interpretations of his epistemology have tended to emphasise one of
these apparently conflicting positions over the others. But Schmitt
argues that the positions can be reconciled by tracing them to a
single underlying epistemology of knowledge and probability quietly
at work in the text, an epistemology according to which truth is
the chief cognitive merit of a belief, and knowledge and probable
belief are species of reliable belief. Hume adopts Locke's
dichotomy between knowledge and probability and reassigns causal
inference from its traditional place in knowledge to the domain of
probability-his most significant departure from earlier accounts of
cognition. This shift of causal inference to an associative and
imaginative operation raises doubts about the merit of causal
inference, suggesting the counterintuitive consequence that causal
inference is wholly inferior to knowledge-producing demonstration.
To defend his associationist psychology of causal inference from
this suggestion, Hume must favourably compare causal inference with
demonstration in a manner compatible with associationism. He does
this by finding an epistemic status shared by demonstrative
knowledge and causally inferred beliefs-the status of justified
belief. On the interpretation developed here, he identifies
knowledge with infallible belief and justified belief with reliable
belief, i.e., belief produced by truth-conducive belief-forming
operations. Since infallibility implies reliable belief, knowledge
implies justified belief. He then argues that causally inferred
beliefs are reliable, so share this status with knowledge. Indeed
Hume assumes that causally inferred beliefs enjoy this status in
his very argument for associationism. On the reliability
interpretation, Hume's accounts of knowledge and justified belief
are part of a broader veritistic epistemology making true belief
the chief epistemic value and goal of science. The veritistic
interpretation advanced here contrasts with interpretations on
which the chief epistemic value of belief is its empirical
adequacy, stability, or fulfilment of a natural function, as well
as with the suggestion that the chief value of belief is its
utility for common life. Veritistic interpretations are offered of
the natural function of belief, the rules of causal inference,
scepticism about body and matter, and the criteria of
justification. As Schmitt shows, there is much attention to Hume's
sources in Locke and to the complexities of his epistemic
vocabulary.
The Wissenschaftslehre or "doctrine of science" was the great
achievement of the German idealist philosopher J. G. Fichte. Daniel
Breazeale presents accessible new translations of three works in
which Fichte developed this philosophical system. The centerpiece
of this volume is a new English translation of Fichte's only
full-scale presentation of the principles of his philosophy, the
Foundation of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre (1794/95). Accompanying
this are new translations of the work in which Fichte first
publicly introduced his new system, Concerning the Concept of the
Wissenschaftslehre (1794) and the Outline of what is Distinctive of
the Wissenschaftslehre with respect to the Theoretical Power
(1795), which was intended as a companion to the Foundation. In
addition Breazeale includes the transcripts of Fichte's unpublished
"Zurich lectures" on his system (1794), translated here for the
first time in English. Breazeale supplements his translations with
an extensive historical and systematic introduction, detailed
outlines of the contents and structure of the Foundation and
Outline, and copious scholarly annotation of the translated texts,
helping to orient readers who may otherwise find themselves lost in
the wilderness of Fichte's complex "derivations."
In Everything Ancient Was Once New, Emalani Case explores
Indigenous persistence through the concept of Kahiki, a term that
is at once both an ancestral homeland for Kanaka Maoli (Hawaiians)
and the knowledge that there is life to be found beyond Hawai'i's
shores. It is therefore both a symbol of ancestral connection and
the potential that comes with remembering and acting upon that
connection. Tracing physical, historical, intellectual, and
spiritual journeys to and from Kahiki, Emalani frames it as a place
of refuge and sanctuary, a place where ancient knowledge can
constantly be made anew. It is in Kahiki, she argues, and in the
sanctuary it creates, that today's Kanaka Maoli can find safety and
reprieve from the continued onslaught of settler colonial violence,
while also confronting some of the often uncomfortable and
challenging realities of being Indigenous in Hawai'i, in the
Pacific, and in the world. Each chapter of the book engages with
Kahiki as a shifting term, employed by Kanaka Maoli to explain
their lives and experiences to themselves at different points in
history. In doing so, Everything Ancient Was Once New proposes and
argues for reactivated and reinvigorated engagements with Kahiki,
each supporting ongoing work aimed at decolonizing physical and
ideological spaces, and reconnecting Kanaka Maoli to other peoples
and places in the Pacific region and beyond in ways that are both
purposeful and meaningful. In the book, Kahiki is therefore traced
through pivotal moments in history and critical moments in
contemporary times, explaining that while not always mentioned by
name, the idea of Kahiki was, and is, always full of potential. In
writing that is both personal and theoretical, Emalani weaves the
past and the present together, reflecting on ancient concepts and
their continued relevance in movements to protect lands, waters,
and oceans; to fight for social justice; to reexamine our
responsibilities and obligations to each other across the Pacific
region; and to open space for continued dialogue on what it means
to be Indigenous both when at home and when away. Combining
personal narrative and reflection with research and critical
analysis, Everything Ancient Was Once New journeys to and from
Kahiki, the sanctuary for reflection, deep learning, and continued
dreaming with the past, in the present, and far into the future.
|
|