|
Books > Religion & Spirituality > General > Philosophy of religion
The recovery of nature has been a unifying and enduring aim of the
writings of Ralph McInerny, Michael P. Grace Professor of Medieval
Studies at the University of Notre Dame, director of the Jacques
Maritain Center, former director of the Medieval Institute, and
author of numerous works in philosophy, literature, and journalism.
While many of the fads that have plagued philosophy and theology
during the last half-century have come and gone, recent
developments suggest that McInerny's commitment to
Aristotelian-Thomism was boldly, if quietly, prophetic. In his
persistent, clear, and creative defenses of natural theology and
natural law, McInerny has appealed to nature to establish a
dialogue between theists and non-theists, to contribute to the
moral and political renewal of American culture, and particularly
to provide some of the philosophical foundations for Catholic
theology.
This volume brings together essays by an impressive group of
scholars, including William Wallace, O.P., Jude P. Dougherty, John
Haldane, Thomas DeKoninck, Alasdair MacIntyre, David Solomon,
Daniel McInerny, Janet E. Smith, Michael Novak, Stanley Hauerwas,
Laura Garcia, Alvin Plantinga, Alfred J. Freddoso, and David B.
Burrell, C.S.C.
Our digital technologies have inspired new ways of thinking about
old religious topics. Digitalists include computer scientists,
transhumanists, singularitarians, and futurists. Writers such as
Moravec, Bostrom, Kurzweil, and Chalmers are digitalists. Although
they are usually scientists, rationalists, and atheists,
digitalists they have worked out novel and entirely naturalistic
ways of thinking about bodies, minds, souls, universes, gods, and
life after death. Your Digital Afterlives starts with three
digitalist theories of life after death. It examines personality
capture, body uploading, and promotion to higher levels of
simulation. It then examines the idea that reality itself is
ultimately a system of self-surpassing computations. On that view,
you will have infinitely many digital lives across infinitely many
digital worlds. Your Digital Afterlives looks at superhuman bodies
and infinite bodies. Thinking of nature in purely computational
terms has the potential to radically and positively change our
understanding of life after death.
'A Theory of the Absolute' develops a worldview that is opposed to
the dominant paradigm of physicalism and atheism. It provides
powerful arguments for the existence of the soul and the existence
of the absolute, showing that faith is not in contradiction to
reason.
In the twentieth century, many contemporary epistemologists in the
analytic tradition have entered into debate regarding the right to
belief with new tools: Richard Swinburne, Anthony Kenny, Alvin
Plantinga, Nicholas Wolterstorff, Peter van Inwagen (who
contributes a piece in this volume) defending or contesting the
requirement of evidence for any justified belief. The best things
we can do, it seems, is to examine more attentively the true notion
of "right to believe", especially about religious matters. This is
exactly what authors of the papers in this book do.
This book pursues the implications for linking Lenin with theology,
which is not a project that has been undertaken thus far. What does
this inveterate atheist known for describing religion as 'spiritual
booze' (a gloss on Marx's 'opium of the people') have to do with
theology? This book reveals far more than might initially be
expected, so much so that Lenin and the Russian Revolution cannot
be understood without this complex engagement with theology.
It also seeks to bring Lenin into recent debates over the
intersections between theology and the Left, between the Bible and
political thought. The key names involved in this debate are
reasonably well-known, including Alain Badiou, Slavoj Zižek,
Giorgio Agamben, Antonio Negri, Terry Eagleton, Ernst Bloch,
Theodor Adorno, Louis Althusser, Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari.
Boer has written concerning these critics, among others, in Boer's
earlier five-volume Criticism of Heaven and Earth (Brill and
Haymarket, 2007-13). Lenin and Theology builds upon this earlier
project but it also stands alone as a substantial study in its own
right. But it will be recognised as a contribution that follows a
series that has, as critics have pointed out, played a major role
in reviving and taking to a new level the debate over Marxism and
religion.
The book is based upon a careful, detailed and critical reading of
the whole 45 volumes of his Collected Works in English translation
- 55 volumes in the Russian original. From that close attention to
the texts, a number of key themes have emerged: the ambivalence
over freedom of choice in matters of religion; his love of the
sayings and parables of Jesus in the Gospels; his own love of
constructing new parables; the extended and complex engagements
with Christian socialists and 'God-builders' among the Bolsheviks;
the importance of Hegel for his reassessments of religion; the
arresting suggestion that a revolution is a miracle, which
redefines the meaning of miracle; and the veneration of Lenin after
his death.
Many people believe that during the Middle Ages Christianity was
actively hostile toward science (then known as natural philosophy)
and impeded its progress. This comprehensive survey of science and
religion during the period between the lives of Aristotle and
Copernicus demonstrates how this was not the case. Medieval
theologians were not hostile to learning natural philosophy, but
embraced it. Had they had not done so, the science that developed
during the Scientific Revolution would not--and could not--have
occurred. Students and lay readers will learn how the roots of much
of the scientific culture of today originated with the religious
thinkers of the Middle Ages. Science and Religion, 400 B.C. to A.D.
1550 thoroughly covers the relationship between science and
religion in the medieval period, and provides many resources for
the student or lay reader: Discusses how the influx of Greek and
Arabic science in the 12th and 13th centuries-- especially the
works of Aristotle in logic and natural philosophy--dramatically
changed how science was viewed in Western Europe. Demonstrates how
medieval universities and their teachers disseminated a positive
attitude toward rational inquiry and made it possible for Western
Europe to become oriented toward science. Includes primary
documents that allow the reader to see how important scholars of
the period understood the relationship of science and religion.
Provides an annotated bibliography of the most important works on
science and religion in the Middle Ages, helping students to study
the topic in more detail. BL
"Individualism Old and New" is a serious study of public and
cultural issues surrounding the place of the individual in a
technologically advanced society. Dewey outlines the fear that
personal creative potential will be stomped on by assembly-line
monotony, political bureaucracy and an industrialized culture of
uniformity. Dewey beoieves in the power of critical intelligence
and says that individualism has in fact been offered a unique
higher kevek of technological development upon which to grow,
mature and redine itself. In "Liberalism and Social Action" Dewey
looks at earlier forms of liberalism where the State sunction is to
rotect its citizens while allowing free reign to social-economic
forces. He believes that as a society matures, so must liberalism.
He believes that liberalism must redefine itself in a world where
government must play a dynamic role in creating an enviornment in
which citizens can achieve their potential. Dewey's advocacy of a
posiive role for government - a new liberalism - is a natural
application of Hegel's dialetic. "A Common Faith" presents a
compelling prescription for a union of religious and social ideals,
inluding consistency in both idea and action. His thesis is thought
provoking. This book should not only be read by social scientist,
but also people if faith who wish to intelligently enhance their
own faith. A Collector's Edition.
In a violation of our destiny, something is killing every one of
us. The judge of ignorance has long sentenced every living being to
death, has sentenced you, and I, all our ancestors, and our
children to death. In a relentless holocaust, there are no
survivors. Hope has not been enough to win an appeal, nor the
visions of faith, nor the dream of justice and beauty, not even
love. To the hearless judge of ignorance, these mean nothing. We
will be saved in the end y knowledge. We will learn to overcome
aging and death by engendering the noble and supreme intelligences.
We will create the gods who will call us back to life, or we will
not return at all. It is in our hands. It is time to inspire and
begin the ultimate scientific, moral, and spiritual quest. The end
of death.
Leo Strauss and Emmanuel Levinas, two twentieth-century Jewish
philosophers and two extremely provocative thinkers whose
reputations have grown considerably, are rarely studied together.
This is due to the disparate interests of many of their
intellectual heirs. Strauss has influenced political theorists and
policy makers on the right while Levinas has been championed in the
humanities by different cadres associated with postmodernist
thought. In Leo Strauss and Emmanuel Levinas: Philosophy and the
Politics of Revelation, first published in 2006, Leora Batnitzky
brings together these two seemingly incongruous contemporaries,
demonstrating that they often had the same philosophical sources
and their projects had many formal parallels. While such a
comparison is valuable in itself for better understanding each
figure, it also raises profound questions in the debate on the
definitions of 'religion', suggesting ways that religion makes
claims on both philosophy and politics.
"Following Vattimo's postmodern philosophy, Badiou's
postmetaphysical ontology, and i ek's revolutionary style, the
authors of this marvelous book invites us to reactivate our
politics of resistance against our greatest enemy: corporate
capitalism. The best solution to the ecological, energy, and
financial crisis corporate capitalism has created, as Crockett
Clayton and Jeffrey Robbins suggest, is a new theological
materialism where Being is conceived as energy both subjectively
and objectively. All my graduate students will have to read this
book carefully if they want to become philosophers." - Santiago
Zabala, ICREA Research Professor at the University of Barcelona
"This is a book of an extraordinary timeliness, written in an
accessible and strikingly informative way. It is excellently poised
to become a synthetic and agenda setting statement about the
implications of a new materialism for the founding of a new radical
theology, a new kind of spirituality. I consider this therefore
quite a remarkable book which will be influential in ongoing
discussions of psychoanalysis, continental philosophy, and
theology. Moreover, it will be, quite simply, the best book about
spirituality and the new materialism on the market today. While all
of the work of the new materialists engage at one level or another
the question of a new spirituality, I do not think there is
anything comparable in significance to what Crockett and Robbins
have provided here." - Ward Blanton, University of Kent "This book
will perhaps be most appreciated by the reader with an intuitive
cast of mind, able to recognize the force of an argument in its
imaginative suggestiveness . . . New Materialism is about energy
transformation, we are told, energy which cannot be reduced to
matter because it resonates with spirit and life . . . Yet the book
strikes a fundamental note of hard reality: 'if we want our
civilization to live on earth a little longer we will have to
recognize our coexistence with and in earth'." - Christian Ecology
Link
In The Ends of Philosophy of Religion, Timothy D. Knepper advances
a new, historically grounded and religiously diverse program for
the philosophy of religion. Knepper first critiques existing
efforts in analytic and continental philosophy of religion for
neglect of diversity among its objects and subjects of inquiry, as
well as for failing to thickly describe, formally compare, and
critically evaluate historical acts of reason-giving in the
religions of the world. Knepper then constructs an alternative
vision for the philosophy of religion, one in which religious
reason-giving is described with empathetic yet suspicious
sensitivity, compared with methodological and categorical
awareness, and explained and evaluated with a plurality of
resources and criteria."The Ends of Philosophy of Religion casts a
critical eye over both analytic and continental philosophy of
religion and finds an ailment that besets them both. Knepper
provides an analysis that is not only clear and eloquent but also
sometimes frustrated and angry one. This gives his book the feeling
of a manifesto, something I judge that the discipline needs." -
Kevin Schilbrack, Professor, Philosophy and Religion Department,
Western Carolina University, USA"Philosophy of religion is entering
a new dawn, beyond the Western confines of bare theism and pale
postmodernism, and towards the religions of the world, Eastern and
Western, in all their rich diversity and complexity. Knepper's
timely and insightful book outlines these broad and deep changes
that have yet to be acknowledged by practitioners from both the
analytic and Continental schools." - Nick Trakakis, Assistant
Director of the Centre for the Philosophy and Phenomenology of
Religion, Australian Catholic University, Australia"Those of us who
believe philosophy of religion should be about religion in all its
complexity and diversity will welcome this book with relief.
Knepper attacks the pretense of using the phrase 'philosophy of
religion' to describe parochial philosophy of western theism or the
disorganized religious insights of postmodern philosophers. He
argues for historically grounded philosophy of religions,
up-to-date on religious studies, and fearless about analyzing
reasons for religious beliefs and practices. This is the kind of
philosophy of religion that belongs in university religious studies
departments. Here's hoping it catches on quickly." - Wesley J.
Wildman, Professor of Philosophy, Theology, and Ethics, Boston
University School of Theology, US
This book offers a fascinating account of Heidegger's middle and
later thought."Heidegger and Philosophical Atheology" offers an
important new reading of Heidegger's middle and later thought.
Beginning with Heidegger's early dissertation on the doctrine of
categories in Duns Scotus, Peter S. Dillard shows how Heidegger's
middle and later works develop a philosophical anti-theology or
'atheology' that poses a serious threat to traditional metaphysics,
natural theology and philosophy of religion.Drawing on the insights
of Scholastic thinkers such as St Thomas Aquinas and Duns Scotus,
the book reveals the problematic assumptions of Heideggerian
'atheology' and shows why they should be rejected. Dillard's
critique paves the way for a rejuvenation of Scholastic metaphysics
and reveals its relevance to some contemporary philosophical
disputes. In addition to clarifying the question of being and
explaining the role of phenomenology in metaphysics, Dillard sheds
light on the nature of nothingness, necessity and contingency.
Ultimately the book offers a revolutionary reorientation of our
understanding, both of the later Heidegger and of the legacy of
Scholasticism.
John Foster presents a clear and powerful discussion of a range of
topics relating to our understanding of the universe: induction,
laws of nature, and the existence of God. He begins by developing a
solution to the problem of induction - a solution whose key idea is
that the regularities in the workings of nature that have held in
our experience hitherto are to be explained by appeal to the
controlling influence of laws, as forms of natural necessity. His
second line of argument focuses on the issue of what we should take
such necessitational laws to be, and whether we can even make sense
of them at all. Having considered and rejected various
alternatives, Foster puts forward his own proposal: the obtaining
of a law consists in the causal imposing of a regularity on the
universe as a regularity. With this causal account of laws in
place, he is now equipped to offer an argument for theism. His
claim is that natural regularities call for explanation, and that,
whatever explanatory role we may initially assign to laws, the only
plausible ultimate explanation is in terms of the agency of God.
Finally, he argues that, once we accept the existence of God, we
need to think of him as creating the universe by a method which
imposes regularities on it in the relevant law-yielding way. In
this new perspective, the original nomological-explanatory solution
to the problem of induction becomes a theological-explanatory
solution. The Divine Lawmaker is bold and original in its approach,
and rich in argument. The issues on which it focuses are among the
most important in the whole epistemological and metaphysical
spectrum.
The Roman Catholic Bishops of the Caribbean, the Antilles Episcopal
Conference (AEC), have over the past forty years written statements
addressed to their faithful and people in the wider Caribbean. The
statements covered a wide range of issues impinging on the life and
faith of Caribbean people, including political engagement, crime
and violence, homosexuality, HIV-AIDS, sexuality, the environment.
A key theme running through the statements is the concern with
justice. This collection of critical essays and personal
reflections explores the insights provided by these statements. In
so doing, it presents a critical reading of the corpus with a view
to presenting its relevance to the regional and global conversation
on matters of human flourishing. The authors of the volume
represent the diverse voices from within the Catholic Caribbean,
particularly some fresh new voices. This collection brings together
the voices of men and women--pastors, laity, theologians, political
leaders, educators; each essayist considers a specific statement
and provides a commentary and interpretation of its contents as
well as a considered assessment of its impact on the life of the
faithful. Academics, lay persons, pastors, policy makers and
politicians will find this a useful collection.
Can it be justifiable to commit oneself 'by faith' to a religious
claim when its truth lacks adequate support from one's total
available evidence? In Believing by Faith, John Bishop defends a
version of fideism inspired by William James's 1896 lecture 'The
Will to Believe'. By critiquing both 'isolationist'
(Wittgensteinian) and Reformed epistemologies of religious belief,
Bishop argues that anyone who accepts that our publicly available
evidence is equally open to theistic and naturalist/atheistic
interpretations will need to defend a modest fideist position. This
modest fideism understands theistic commitment as involving
'doxastic venture' - practical commitment to propositions held to
be true through 'passional' causes (causes other than the
recognition of evidence of or for their truth).
While Bishop argues that concern about the justifiability of
religious doxastic venture is ultimately moral concern, he accepts
that faith-ventures can be morally justifiable only if they are in
accord with the proper exercise of our rational epistemic
capacities. Legitimate faith-ventures may thus never be
counter-evidential, and, furthermore, may be made
supra-evidentially only when the truth of the faith-proposition
concerned necessarily cannot be settled on the basis of evidence.
Bishop extends this Jamesian account by requiring that justifiable
faith-ventures should also be morally acceptable both in motivation
and content. Hard-line evidentialists, however, insist that all
religious faith-ventures are morally wrong. Bishop thus conducts an
extended debate between fideists and hard-line evidentialists,
arguing that neither side can succeed in establishing the
irrationality of itsopposition. He concludes by suggesting that
fideism may nevertheless be morally preferable, as a less dogmatic,
more self-accepting, even a more loving, position than its
evidentialist rival.
Philosophical naturalism, according to which philosophy is continuous with the natural sciences, has dominated the Western academy for well over a century; but Michael Rea claims that it is without rational foundation, and that the costs of embracing it are surprisingly high. Rea argues compellingly to the surprising conclusion that naturalists are committed to rejecting realism about material objects, materialism, and perhaps realism about other minds. That is surely a price that naturalists are unwilling to pay: this philosophical orthodoxy should be rejected.
|
|