|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy
A Treatise of Human Nature was published between 1739 and 1740.
Book I, entitled Of the Understanding, contains Hume's
epistemology, i.e., his account of the manner in which we acquire
knowledge in general, its justification (to the extent that he
thought it could be justified), and its limits. Book II, entitled
Of the Passions, expounds most of what could be called Hume's
philosophy of psychology in general, and his moral psychology
(including discussions of the problem of the freedom of the will
and the rationality of action) in particular. Book III, entitled Of
Morals, is also divided into three parts. Part II of Book III,
entitled Of justice and injustice, is the subject of the present
volume. In it Hume attempts to give an empiricist theory of
justice. He rejects the view, approximated to in varying degrees by
Cumberland, Cudworth, Locke, Clarke, Wollaston, and Butler, that
justice is something natural and part of the nature of things, and
that its edicts are eternal and immutable, and discernible by
reason. Hume maintains, on the contrary, as did Hobbes and
Mandeville, that justice is a matter of observing rules or
conventions which are of human invention, and that, in consequence,
our acquiring a knowledge of justice is an empirical affair of
ascertaining what these rules or conventions are.
If we do what is right, everything else will follow: happiness,
success, meaning, reputation, love. This is central to Stoic wisdom.
The path isn't always easy, but it is essential, and the alternative -
taking the easy route - leads only to cowardice and folly.
In the third book in his bestselling Stoic Virtues series, Ryan Holiday
explores the crucial role that integrity plays in every good life. From
pillars of upright living like Ulysses S. Grant and Marcus Aurelius, to
the cautionary tales of Napoleon and F. Scott Fitzgerald, this book
shows us the power of owning our convictions and acting in accordance
with our beliefs - and the perils of an ill-formed conscience.
Our conscience, our sense of justice, is our first and our last
strength: we can train it, hone it and fortify it, but above all, we
must never lose it. This book shows us how.
The fifteen new essays collected in this volume address questions
concerning the ethics of self-defense, most centrally when and to
what extent the use of defensive force, especially lethal force,
can be justified. Scholarly interest in this topic reflects public
concern stemming from controversial cases of the use of force by
police, and military force exercised in the name of defending
against transnational terrorism. The contributors pay special
attention to determining when a threat is liable to defensive harm,
though doubts about this emphasis are also raised. The legitimacy
of so-called "stand your ground" policies and laws is also
addressed. This volume will be of great interest to readers in
moral, political, and legal philosophy.
Eric Santner offers a radically new interpretation of Marx's labor
theory of value as one concerned with the afterlife of political
theology in secular modernity. What Marx characterized as the dual
character of the labor embodied in the commodity, he argues, is the
doctrine of the King's Two Bodies transferred from the political
theology of sovereignty to the realm of political economy. This
genealogy, leading from the fetishism of the royal body to the
fetishism of the commodity, also suggests a new understanding of
the irrational core at the center of economic busyness today, its
24/7 pace. The frenetic negotiations of our busy-bodies continue
and translate into the doxology of everyday life the liturgical
labor that once sustained the sovereign's glory. Maintaining that
an effective critique of capitalist political economy must engage
this liturgical dimension, Santner proposes a counter-activity,
which he calls "paradoxological." With commentaries by Bonnie
Honig, Peter Gordon, and Hent de Vries, an introduction by Kevis
Goodman, and a response from Santner, this important new book by a
leading cultural theorist and scholar of German literature, cinema,
and history will interest readers of political theory, literature
and literary theory, and religious studies.
What is consciousness? How does the subjective character of
consciousness fit into an objective world? How can there be a
science of consciousness? In this sequel to his groundbreaking and
controversial The Conscious Mind, David Chalmers develops a unified
framework that addresses these questions and many others. Starting
with a statement of the "hard problem" of consciousness, Chalmers
builds a positive framework for the science of consciousness and a
nonreductive vision of the metaphysics of consciousness. He replies
to many critics of The Conscious Mind, and then develops a positive
theory in new directions. The book includes original accounts of
how we think and know about consciousness, of the unity of
consciousness, and of how consciousness relates to the external
world. Along the way, Chalmers develops many provocative ideas: the
"consciousness meter", the Garden of Eden as a model of perceptual
experience, and The Matrix as a guide to the deepest philosophical
problems about consciousness and the external world. This book will
be required reading for anyone interested in the problems of mind,
brain, consciousness, and reality.
In this volume, Kieran McGroarty provides a philosophical
commentary on a section of the Enneads written by the last great
Neoplatonist thinker, Plotinus. The treatise is entitled
"Concerning Well-Being" and was written at a late stage in
Plotinus' life when he was suffering from an illness that was
shortly to kill him. Its main concern is with the good man and how
he should pursue the good life. The treatise is therefore central
to our understanding of Plotinus' ethical theory, and the
commentary seeks to explicate and elucidate that theory. Plotinus'
views on how one should live in order to fulfill oneself as a human
being are as relevant now as they were in the third century AD. All
Greek and Latin is translated, while short summaries introducing
the content of each chapter help to make Plotinus' argument clear
even to the non-specialist.
This is fundamentally a text about race and antiblack racism and their subsequent production of the problem of alienation (separation) of human beings from one another, from their bodies, and from themselves, globally, but with distinct and conscious focus on the historical context of apartheid and “post”-apartheid South Africa through the psychological lens of one of the country’s first and distinguished clinical psychologists, Noel Chabani Manganyi.
The book is a philosophically critical engagement with his work, and it constitutes, as it were, part of the author’s overarching project of attempting to reclaim and retrieve hitherto overlooked, ignored and invisibilised Black thinkers of the past and present. Although Manganyi has written over 10 books, the most important and popular being Being-Black-in-the-World (1973) and Alienation and the Body in Racist Society (1977), his ideas and work have, for one reason or another, been disregarded by mainstream South African psychology, let alone philosophy. The author foregrounds philosophy as also a culprit because Manganyi himself describes his work as that of “a psychologist who thinks and conceptualises psychological reality in a phenomenological way”.
Manganyi has the distinction of being the first Black clinical psychologist trained in South Africa as the title of his latest book, Apartheid and the Making of a Black Psychologist (2016) indicates. His body of published work reveals that from the beginning he has been involved in an attempt to contextualise his discipline, psychology, to the lived realities of his country, that is, apartheid racism and the alienation it produced on Black people. In other words, his main concern has been to utilise psychological discourse to address issues relevant to what can broadly be called “the Black lived-experience” in an antiblack racist society and their experience of the condition of alienation. As such he stood as a solitary figure whose voice was pushed to the margins of the psychological establishment, which was either silent about or complicit in the oppression of Blacks by the apartheid regime.
By exploring Manganyi’s serious concerns about apartheid racism and its attendant devastating production of alienation among Black people, the author argues that the problem of alienation produced by continuing rampant antiblack racism (even from the hands of a Black government) constitutes itself as a lingering problem of “post”-apartheid South Africa.
The author demonstrates that apartheid and alienation are not only conceptually synonymous but experientially related because what connects antiblack racism (apartheid) and alienation is the fact of our embodied existence in the world and that Black alienation manifests itself through the body. After all, antiblack racism is predicated on bodily appearance and body differences among human beings. Manganyi himself places a high premium on the body precisely because, in his view, the Black subjects have inherited a negative sociological schema of their black bodies as a result of which most of them experience themselves as somethings or objects outside of themselves, that is.
The value of revisiting Manganyi’s contribution can be underlined by reference to imperatives posed in recent incidents of antiblack racism and contemporary approaches to race and embodiment in disciplines such as philosophy (Black existentialism), psychology, sociology, cultural studies and identity politics.
This book's focus spans a wide variety of disciplines, including psychology, philosophy, political philosophy, critical race studies and post-colonialism, and therefore will be of interest to a broad cross-section of undergraduate and graduate students, scholars and activists.
|
You may like...
The Library
Andrew Lang
Paperback
R499
Discovery Miles 4 990
|