|
Showing 1 - 9 of
9 matches in All Departments
|
Coming to be, 1. 6-2. 4 (Hardcover)
John Philoponus; Volume editing by C.J.F. Williams; Translated by C.J.F. William
|
R4,131
Discovery Miles 41 310
|
Ships in 12 - 17 working days
|
These chapters of Aristotle's treatise are about physical
interactions. In his innovative commentary, Philoponus discusses
Aristotle's idea that certain qualities of the elements are basic.
In what way are they basic? he asks. To what extent can the other
qualities be reduced to the basic ones? And if the other qualities
depend on the basic ones, how is it that they can vary
independently of each other when the basic qualities change?
Philoponus develops the idea that the other qualities merely
supervene on the basic ones, rather than resulting from them.
Moreover, physical qualities admit of different ranges of
variation, and so have different thresholds at which they appear or
disappear. Philoponus also discusses Aristotle's idea that the
elements and their basic qualities survive potentially when mixed
together. He explains this by drawing a third sense of 'potential'
out of Aristotle's texts to take the place of the two senses which
Aristotle explicitly recognises. Philoponus adds further
restrictions to Aristotle's principles of causation. Black can
contaminate white, but the black in ebony does not have the right
matter for affecting the white of milk. He asks why fluids can
affect each other more easily than solids. In every case,
Philoponus takes Aristotle's discussions further, and his ideas on
the dependence of some qualities on others are very relevant to the
continuing philosophical debate on the subject.
|
Coming to be, 1-1. 5 (Hardcover)
John Philoponus; Volume editing by C.J.F. Williams; Translated by C.J.F. Williams
|
R4,132
Discovery Miles 41 320
|
Ships in 12 - 17 working days
|
The first five chapters of Aristotle's De Generatione et
Corruptione distinguish creation and destruction from mere
qualitative change and from growth. They include a fascinating
debate about the atomists' analysis of creation and destruction as
due to the rearrangement of indivisible atoms. Aristotle's rival
belief in the infinite divisibility of matter is explained and
defended against the atomists' powerful attack on infinite
divisibility. But what inspired Philoponus most in his commentary
is the topic of organic growth. How does it take place without
ingested matter getting into the same place as the growing body?
And how is personal identity preserved, if our matter is always in
flux, and our form depends on our matter? If we do not depend on
the persistence of matter why are we not immortal? Analogous
problems of identity arise also for inanimate beings. Philoponus
draws out a brief remark of Aristotle's to show that cause need not
be like effect. For example, what makes something hard may be cold,
not hard. This goes against a persistent philosophical prejudice,
but Philoponus makes it plausible that Aristotle recognized this
truth. These topics of identity over time and the principles of
causation are still matters of intense discussion.
Philosophers have met with many problems in discussing the
interconnected concepts being, identity, and truth, and have
advanced many theories to deal with them. Professor Williams argues
that most of these problems and theories result from an inadequate
appreciation of the ways in which the words `be', `same', and
`true' work. By means of linguistic analysis he shows that being
and truth are not properties, and identity is not a relation. He is
thus able to demystify a number of metaphysical issues concerning
the meaning of the word `I', the relation between the mental and
the physical, objects of thought, times and places, and the nature
of reality. Williams presents his views clearly, with a minimum of
technicality, and with rich and apt examples, so that they will be
accessible to readers not versed in symbolic logic.
A study in philosophical logic of the meaning of 'true'. Dr
Williams demonstrates the shortcomings of various analyses which
interpret 'true' as a predicate or truth as a relational property,
and clears up a number of important points about propositions,
quantification, definite descriptions and correspondence. This
'deflationary metaphysics' is interwoven with a positive theory of
his own, which seeks to develop ideas about the late Arthur Prior.
The work is marked throughout by great clarity, precision and
thoroughness.
The concept of identity has been seen to lead to paradox: we cannot
truly and usefully say that a thing is the same either as itself or
as something else. This book is a full examination of this paradox
in philosophical logic, and of its implications for the philosophy
of mathematics, the philosphy of mind, and relativism about
identity. The author's account involves detailed discussion of the
views of Wittgenstein, Russell, Frege, and Hintikka.
The first five chapters of Aristotle's De Generatione et
Corruptione distinguish creation and destruction from mere
qualitative change and from growth. They include a fascinating
debate about the atomists' analysis of creation and destruction as
due to the rearrangement of indivisible atoms. Aristotle's rival
belief in the infinite divisibility of matter is explained and
defended against the atomists' powerful attack on infinite
divisibility. But what inspired Philoponus most in his commentary
is the topic of organic growth. How does it take place without
ingested matter getting into the same place as the growing body?
And how is personal identity preserved, if our matter is always in
flux, and our form depends on our matter? If we do not depend on
the persistence of matter why are we not immortal? Analogous
problems of identity arise also for inanimate beings. Philoponus
draws out a brief remark of Aristotle's to show that cause need not
be like effect. For example, what makes something hard may be cold,
not hard. This goes against a persistent philosophical prejudice,
but Philoponus makes it plausible that Aristotle recognized this
truth. These topics of identity over time and the principles of
causation are still matters of intense discussion.
These chapters of Aristotle's treatise are about physical
interactions. In his innovative commentary, Philoponus discusses
Aristotle's idea that certain qualities of the elements are basic.
In what way are they basic? he asks. To what extent can the other
qualities be reduced to the basic ones? And if the other qualities
depend on the basic ones, how is it that they can vary
independently of each other when the basic qualities change?
Philoponus develops the idea that the other qualities merely
supervene on the basic ones, rather than resulting from them.
Moreover, physical qualities admit of different ranges of
variation, and so have different thresholds at which they appear or
disappear. Philoponus also discusses Aristotle's idea that the
elements and their basic qualities survive potentially when mixed
together. He explains this by drawing a third sense of 'potential'
out of Aristotle's texts to take the place of the two senses which
Aristotle explicitly recognises. Philoponus adds further
restrictions to Aristotle's principles of causation. Black can
contaminate white, but the black in ebony does not have the right
matter for affecting the white of milk. He asks why fluids can
affect each other more easily than solids. In every case,
Philoponus takes Aristotle's discussions further, and his ideas on
the dependence of some qualities on others are very relevant to the
continuing philosophical debate on the subject.
|
You may like...
Loot
Nadine Gordimer
Paperback
(2)
R205
R168
Discovery Miles 1 680
Loot
Nadine Gordimer
Paperback
(2)
R205
R168
Discovery Miles 1 680
|