|
Showing 1 - 3 of
3 matches in All Departments
This book offers an analysis of humor, comedy, and laughter as
philosophical topics in the 19th Century. It traces the
introduction of humor as a new aesthetic category inspired by
Laurence Sterne's "Tristram Shandy" and shows Sterne's deep
influence on German aesthetic theorists of this period. Through
differentiating humor from comedy, the book suggests important
distinctions within the aesthetic philosophies of G.W.F. Hegel,
Karl Solger, and Jean Paul Richter. The book links Kant's
underdeveloped incongruity theory of laughter to Schopenhauer's
more complete account and identifies humor's place in the
pessimistic philosophy of Julius Bahnsen. It considers how
caricature functioned at the intersection of politics, aesthetics,
and ethics in Karl Rosenkranz's work, and how Kierkegaard and
Nietzsche made humor central not only to their philosophical
content but also to its style. The book concludes with an
explication of French philosopher Henri Bergson's claim that
laughter is a response to mechanical inelasticity.
This book offers an analysis of humor, comedy, and laughter as
philosophical topics in the 19th Century. It traces the
introduction of humor as a new aesthetic category inspired by
Laurence Sterne's "Tristram Shandy" and shows Sterne's deep
influence on German aesthetic theorists of this period. Through
differentiating humor from comedy, the book suggests important
distinctions within the aesthetic philosophies of G.W.F. Hegel,
Karl Solger, and Jean Paul Richter. The book links Kant's
underdeveloped incongruity theory of laughter to Schopenhauer's
more complete account and identifies humor's place in the
pessimistic philosophy of Julius Bahnsen. It considers how
caricature functioned at the intersection of politics, aesthetics,
and ethics in Karl Rosenkranz's work, and how Kierkegaard and
Nietzsche made humor central not only to their philosophical
content but also to its style. The book concludes with an
explication of French philosopher Henri Bergson's claim that
laughter is a response to mechanical inelasticity.
Hegel is known as "the father of art history," yet recent
scholarship has overlooked his contributions. This is the first
comprehensive interpretation of Hegel's philosophy of art in
English in thirty years. In a new analysis of Hegel's notorious
"end of art" thesis, Hegel's Aesthetics shows the indispensability
of Hegel's aesthetics for understanding his philosophical idealism
and introduces a new claim about his account of aesthetic
experience. In a departure from previous interpretations, Lydia
Moland argues for considering Hegel's discussion of individual
arts-architecture, sculpture, painting, music, and poetry-on their
own terms, unlocking new insights about his theories of perception,
feeling, selfhood, and freedom. This new approach allows Hegel's
philosophy to engage with modern aesthetic theories and opens new
possibilities for applying Hegel's aesthetics to contemporary art.
Moland further elucidates his controversial analysis of symbolic,
classical, and romantic art through clarifying Hegel's examples of
each. By incorporating newly available sources from Hegel's
lectures on art, this book widely expands our understanding of the
particular artworks Hegel discusses as well as the theories he
rejects. Hegel's Aesthetics further situates his arguments in the
intense philosophizing about art among his contemporaries,
including Kant, Lessing, Herder, Schelling, and the Schlegel
brothers. Ultimately, the book offers a rich vision of the
foundation of his ideas about art and the range of their
application, confirming Hegel as one of the most important
theorists of art in the history of philosophy.
|
|