|
Showing 1 - 15 of
15 matches in All Departments
What makes the words we speak mean what they do? Possible-worlds
semantics articulates the view that the meanings of words
contribute to determining, for each sentence, which possible worlds
would make the sentence true, and which would make it false. M. J.
Cresswell argues that the non-semantic facts on which such semantic
facts supervene are facts about the causal interactions between the
linguistic behaviour of speakers and the facts in the world that
they are speaking about, and that the kind of causation involved is
best analysed using David Lewis's account of causation in terms of
counterfactuals. Although philosophers have worked on the question
of the connection between meaning and linguistic behaviour, it has
mostly been without regard to the work done in possible-worlds
semantics, and Language in the world is the first book-length
examination of this problem.
In ordinary discourse we appear to ta1k about many things that have
seemed mysterious to philosophers. We say that there has been a
hitch in our arrangements or that the solution to the problem
required us to examine all the probable outcomes of our action. So
it would seem that we speak as if in addition to eloeks, mountains,
queens and grains of sand there are hitches, arrangements,
solutions, probiems, and probable outcomes. It is not immediately
obvious when we must take such ta1k as really assuming that there
are such to develop tests for things, and one of the tasks in this
book is discerning what has eome to be called ontological
commitment, in naturallanguage. Among the entities that natural
language appears to make reference to are those connected with
temporal and modal discourse, times, possibilities, and so on. Such
entities play a crueial role in the kind of semantieal theories
that I and others have defended over many years. These theories are
based on the idea that an essential part of the meaning of a
sentence is constituted by the conditions under whieh that sentenee
is true. To know what a sentence says is to know what the world
would have to be !ike for that sentence to be true.
Over a longer period than I sometimes care to contemplate I have
worked on possible-worlds semantics. The earliest work was in modal
logic, to which I keep returning, but a sabbatical in 1970 took me
to UCLA, there to discover the work of Richard Montague in applying
possible-worlds semantics to natural lan guage. My own version of
this appeared in Cresswell (1973) and was followed up in a number
of articles, most of which were collected in Cresswell (1985b). A
central problem for possible worlds semantics is how to accommodate
propositional attitudes. This problem was addressed in Cresswell
(1985a), and the three books mentioned so far represent a
reasonably complete picture of my positive views on formal
semantics. I have regarded the presentation of a positive view as
more important than the criticism of alternatives, although the
works referred to do contain many passages in which I have tried to
defend my own views against those of others. But such criticism is
important in that a crucial element in establishing the content of
a theory is that we be able to evaluate it in relation to its com
petitors. It is for that reason that I have collected in this
volume a number of articles in which I attempt to defend the
positive semantical picture I favour against objections and
competing theories."
Semantic Indexicality shows how a simple syntax can be combined
with a propositional language at the level of logical analysis. It
is the adoption of such a base language which has not been
attempted before, and it is this which constitutes the originality
of the book. Cresswell's simple and direct style makes this book
accessible to a wider audience than the somewhat specialized
subject matter might initially suggest.
This long-awaited book replaces Hughes and Cresswell's two classic studies of modal logic: An Introduction to Modal Logic and A Companion to Modal Logic. A New Introduction to Modal Logic is an entirely new work, completely re-written by the authors. They have incorporated all the new developments that have taken place since 1968 in both modal propositional logic and modal predicate logic, without sacrificing tha clarity of exposition and approachability that were essential features of their earlier works. The book takes readers from the most basic systems of modal propositional logic right up to systems of modal predicate with identity. It covers both technical developments such as completeness and incompleteness, and finite and infinite models, and their philosophical applications, especially in the area of modal predicate logic.
Originally published in 1973, this book shows that methods
developed for the semantics of systems of formal logic can be
successfully applied to problems about the semantics of natural
languages; and, moreover, that such methods can take account of
features of natural language which have often been thought
incapable of formal treatment, such as vagueness, context
dependence and metaphorical meaning. Parts 1 and 2 set out a class
of formal languages and their semantics. Parts 3 and 4 show that
these formal languages are rich enought to be used in the precise
description of natural languages. Appendices describe some of the
concepts discussed in the text.
Originally published in 1973, this book shows that methods
developed for the semantics of systems of formal logic can be
successfully applied to problems about the semantics of natural
languages; and, moreover, that such methods can take account of
features of natural language which have often been thought
incapable of formal treatment, such as vagueness, context
dependence and metaphorical meaning. Parts 1 and 2 set out a class
of formal languages and their semantics. Parts 3 and 4 show that
these formal languages are rich enought to be used in the precise
description of natural languages. Appendices describe some of the
concepts discussed in the text.
This long-awaited book replaces not one but both of Hughes and
Cresswell's two previous classic studies of modal logic: "An
Introduction to Modal Logic" and "A Companion to Modal Logic."
"A New Introduction to Modal Logic" has been completely rewritten
by the authors to incorporate all the developments that have taken
place since 1968 both in modal propositional logical and modal
predicate logic, but without sacrificing the clarity of exposition
and approachability that were essential features of the earlier
works.
The book takes readers through the most basic systems of modal
prepositional logic right up to systems of modal predicate with
identity. It deals with both technical developments such as
completeness and incompleteness, and finite and infinite models,
and discusses philosophical applications, especially, in the area
of modal predicate logic.
Semantic Indexicality shows how a simple syntax can be combined
with a propositional language at the level of logical analysis. It
is the adoption of such a base language which has not been
attempted before, and it is this which constitutes the originality
of the book. Cresswell's simple and direct style makes this book
accessible to a wider audience than the somewhat specialized
subject matter might initially suggest.
Over a longer period than I sometimes care to contemplate I have
worked on possible-worlds semantics. The earliest work was in modal
logic, to which I keep returning, but a sabbatical in 1970 took me
to UCLA, there to discover the work of Richard Montague in applying
possible-worlds semantics to natural lan guage. My own version of
this appeared in Cresswell (1973) and was followed up in a number
of articles, most of which were collected in Cresswell (1985b). A
central problem for possible worlds semantics is how to accommodate
propositional attitudes. This problem was addressed in Cresswell
(1985a), and the three books mentioned so far represent a
reasonably complete picture of my positive views on formal
semantics. I have regarded the presentation of a positive view as
more important than the criticism of alternatives, although the
works referred to do contain many passages in which I have tried to
defend my own views against those of others. But such criticism is
important in that a crucial element in establishing the content of
a theory is that we be able to evaluate it in relation to its com
petitors. It is for that reason that I have collected in this
volume a number of articles in which I attempt to defend the
positive semantical picture I favour against objections and
competing theories."
In ordinary discourse we appear to ta1k about many things that have
seemed mysterious to philosophers. We say that there has been a
hitch in our arrangements or that the solution to the problem
required us to examine all the probable outcomes of our action. So
it would seem that we speak as if in addition to eloeks, mountains,
queens and grains of sand there are hitches, arrangements,
solutions, probiems, and probable outcomes. It is not immediately
obvious when we must take such ta1k as really assuming that there
are such to develop tests for things, and one of the tasks in this
book is discerning what has eome to be called ontological
commitment, in naturallanguage. Among the entities that natural
language appears to make reference to are those connected with
temporal and modal discourse, times, possibilities, and so on. Such
entities play a crueial role in the kind of semantieal theories
that I and others have defended over many years. These theories are
based on the idea that an essential part of the meaning of a
sentence is constituted by the conditions under whieh that sentenee
is true. To know what a sentence says is to know what the world
would have to be !ike for that sentence to be true.
Adverbial modification is probably one of the least understood
areas of linguistics. The essays in this volume all address the
problem of how to give an analysis of adverbial modifiers within
truth-conditional semantics. Chapters I-VI provide analyses of
particular modifiers within a possible worlds framework, and were
written between 1974 and 1981. Original publication details of
these chapters may be found on p. vi. Of these, all but Chapter I
make essential use of the idea that the time reference involved in
tensed sentences should be a time interval rather than a single
instant. The final chapter (Chapter VII) was written especially for
this volume and investigates the question of how the 'situation
semantics' recently devised by Jon Barwise and John Perry, as a
rival to possible-worlds semantics, might deal with adverbs. In
addition I have included an appendix to Chapter III and an
introduction which links all the chapters together."
Is what could have happened but never did as real as what did
happen? What did happen, but isn't happening now, happened at
another time. Analogously, one can say that what could have
happened happens in another possible world. Whatever their views
about the reality of such things as possible worlds, philosophers
need to take this analogy seriously. Adriane Rini and Max Cresswell
exhibit, in an easy step-by-step manner, the logical structure of
temporal and modal discourse, and show that every temporal
construction has an exact parallel that requires a language that
can refer to worlds, and vice versa. They make precise, in a way
which can be articulated and tested, the claim that the parallel is
at work behind even ordinary talk about time and modality. The book
gives metaphysicians a sturdy framework for the investigation of
time and modality - one that does not presuppose any particular
metaphysical view.
Is what could have happened but never did as real as what did
happen? What did happen, but isn't happening now, happened at
another time. Analogously, one can say that what could have
happened happens in another possible world. Whatever their views
about the reality of such things as possible worlds, philosophers
need to take this analogy seriously. Adriane Rini and Max Cresswell
exhibit, in an easy step-by-step manner, the logical structure of
temporal and modal discourse, and show that every temporal
construction has an exact parallel that requires a language that
can refer to worlds, and vice versa. They make precise, in a way
which can be articulated and tested, the claim that the parallel is
at work behind even ordinary talk about time and modality. The book
gives metaphysicians a sturdy framework for the investigation of
time and modality - one that does not presuppose any particular
metaphysical view.
What makes the words we speak mean what they do? Possible-worlds
semantics articulates the view that the meanings of words
contribute to determining, for each sentence, which possible worlds
would make the sentence true, and which would make it false. M. J.
Cresswell argues that the non-semantic facts on which such semantic
facts supervene are facts about the causal interactions between the
linguistic behaviour of speakers and the facts in the world that
they are speaking about, and that the kind of causation involved is
best analysed using David Lewis's account of causation in terms of
counterfactuals. Although philosophers have worked on the question
of the connection between meaning and linguistic behaviour, it has
mostly been without regard to the work done in possible-world
semantics and Language in the World is a book-length examination of
this problem.
|
You may like...
Loot
Nadine Gordimer
Paperback
(2)
R205
R168
Discovery Miles 1 680
|