|
Showing 1 - 15 of
15 matches in All Departments
Introduction to New Realism provides an overview of the movement of
contemporary thought named New Realism, by its creator and most
celebrated practitioner, Maurizio Ferraris. Sharing significant
concerns and features with Speculative Realism and Object Oriented
Ontology, New Realism can be said to be one of the most prescient
philosophical positions today. Its desire to overcome the
postmodern antirealism of Kantian origin, and to reassert the
importance of truth and objectivity in the name of a new
Enlightenment, has had an enormous resonance both in Europe and in
the US. Introduction to New Realism is the first volume dedicated
to exposing this continental movement to an anglophone audience.
Featuring a foreword by the eminent contemporary philosopher and
leading exponent of Speculative Realism, Iain Hamilton Grant, the
book begins by tracing the genesis of New Realism, and outlining
its central theoretical tenets, before opening onto three distinct
sections. The first, 'Negativity', is a critique of the postmodern
idea that the world is constructed by our conceptual schemas, all
the more so as we have entered the age of digitality and
virtuality. The second thesis, 'positivity', proposes the
fundamental ontological assertion of New Realism, namely that not
only are there parts of reality that are independent of thought,
but these parts are also able to act causally over thought and the
human world. The third thesis, 'normativity,' applies New Realism
to the sphere of the social world. Finally, an afterword written by
two young scholars explains in more detail the relationship between
New Realism and other forms of contemporary realism.
A best seller in Italy, Maurizio Ferraris s "Goodbye, Kant "
delivers a nontechnical, entertaining, and occasionally irreverent
overview of Immanuel Kant s "Critique of Pure Reason." He borrows
his title from Wolfgang Becker s "Goodbye Lenin ," the 2003 film
about East Germany after the fall of the Berlin Wall, which depicts
both relief at the passing of the Soviet era and affection for the
ideals it embodied. Ferraris approaches Kant in similar spirits,
demonstrating how the structure that Kant elaborates for the
understanding of human knowledge can generate nostalgia for lost
aspirations, while still leaving room for constructive criticism.
Isolating key themes and concerns in the work, Ferraris evaluates
Kant s claims relative to what science and philosophy have come to
regard as the conditions for knowledge and experience in the
intervening two centuries. He remains attentive to the historical
context and ideals from which Kant s "Critique" emerged but also
resolute in identifying what he sees as the limits and blind spots
in the work. The result is an accessible account of a notoriously
difficult book that will both provoke experts and introduce
students to the work and to these important philosophical debates
about the relations of experience to science."
Presenting legal and philosophical essays on money, this book
explores the conditions according to which an object like a piece
of paper, or an electronic signal, has come to be seen as having a
value. Money plays a crucial role in the regulation of social
relationships and their normative determination. It is thus
integral to the very nature of the "social", and the question of
how society is kept together by a network of agreements,
conventions, exchanges, and codes. All of which must be traced
down. The technologies of money discussed here by Searle, Ferraris,
and Condello show how we conceive the category of the social at the
intersection of individual and collective intentionality,
documentality, and materiality. All of these dimensions, as the
introduction to this volume demonstrates, are of vital importance
for legal theory and for a whole set of legal concepts that are
crucial in reflections on the relationship between law, philosophy,
and society.
Since the 1780s, Western philosophy has been largely under the
spell of Immanuel Kant's transcendental philosophy. In this book,
Maurizio Ferraris offers a number of important criticisms of Kant
in a book of two parts, written 21 years apart. The first part of
the book, 'Observation', originally published in 2001, lays the
foundations of Ferraris' New Realism, foreshadowing the realist
turn that has become characteristic of 21st century philosophy. The
second part, 'Speculation', written in 2021, outlines a complete
metaphysical theory of realism. What ties both parts of the book
together is the the notion of hysteresis, the ability of effects to
survive even when their causes have ceased to exist.
Presenting legal and philosophical essays on money, this book
explores the conditions according to which an object like a piece
of paper, or an electronic signal, has come to be seen as having a
value. Money plays a crucial role in the regulation of social
relationships and their normative determination. It is thus
integral to the very nature of the "social", and the question of
how society is kept together by a network of agreements,
conventions, exchanges, and codes. All of which must be traced
down. The technologies of money discussed here by Searle, Ferraris,
and Condello show how we conceive the category of the social at the
intersection of individual and collective intentionality,
documentality, and materiality. All of these dimensions, as the
introduction to this volume demonstrates, are of vital importance
for legal theory and for a whole set of legal concepts that are
crucial in reflections on the relationship between law, philosophy,
and society.
Since the 1780s, Western philosophy has been largely under the
spell of Immanuel Kant's transcendental philosophy. In this book,
Maurizio Ferraris offers a number of important criticisms of Kant
in a book of two parts, written 21 years apart. The first part of
the book, 'Observation', originally published in 2001, lays the
foundations of Ferraris' New Realism, foreshadowing the realist
turn that has become characteristic of 21st century philosophy. The
second part, 'Speculation', written in 2021, outlines a complete
metaphysical theory of realism. What ties both parts of the book
together is the the notion of hysteresis, the ability of effects to
survive even when their causes have ceased to exist.
This books ushers in a new way of talking about social phenomena.
It develops an ontology of social objects on the basis of the claim
that registration or inscription—the leaving of a trace to be
called up later—is what is most fundamental to them. In doing so,
it systematically organizes concepts and theories that Ferraris’s
predecessors—most notably Derrida, in his project of a positive
grammatology—left in an impressionistic state. Ferraris begins by
redefining ontology as a way of cataloguing the world. Before any
epistemology can discuss the validity of scientific or
nonscientific judgments, one faces a collection of objects, be they
natural, ideal, or social. Among these, Ferraris focuses on social
objects, elaborating a theory of experience in the social world
that leads him to define social objects as “inscribed acts.” He
then uses this notion to interpret social phenomena, also in light
of a systematic discussion of the concept of performatives, from
Austin to Derrida and Searle. Moving into considerations of the
present technological revolution, Ferraris develops a
“symptomatology of the document” that leads to a consideration
of legal systems, finding in them original applications for his
theory that an object equals a written act. Written in an easy,
often witty style, Documentality revises Foucault’s late concept
of the “ontology of actuality” into the project of an
“ontological laboratory,” thereby reinventing philosophy as a
pragmatic activity that is directly applicable to our everyday
life.
This books ushers in a new way of talking about social phenomena.
It develops an ontology of social objects on the basis of the claim
that registration or inscription-the leaving of a trace to be
called up later-is what is most fundamental to them. In doing so,
it systematically organizes concepts and theories that Ferraris's
predecessors-most notably Derrida, in his project of a positive
grammatology-left in an impressionistic state. Ferraris begins by
redefining ontology as a way of cataloguing the world. Before any
epistemology can discuss the validity of scientific or
nonscientific judgments, one faces a collection of objects, be they
natural, ideal, or social. Among these, Ferraris focuses on social
objects, elaborating a theory of experience in the social world
that leads him to define social objects as "inscribed acts." He
then uses this notion to interpret social phenomena, also in light
of a systematic discussion of the concept of performatives, from
Austin to Derrida and Searle. Moving into considerations of the
present technological revolution, Ferraris develops a
"symptomatology of the document" that leads to a consideration of
legal systems, finding in them original applications for his theory
that an object equals a written act. Written in an easy, often
witty style, Documentality revises Foucault's late concept of the
"ontology of actuality" into the project of an "ontological
laboratory," thereby reinventing philosophy as a pragmatic activity
that is directly applicable to our everyday life.
This book sheds light on the most philosophically interesting of
contemporary objects: the cell phone. "Where are you?"-a question
asked over cell phones myriad times each day-is arguably the most
philosophical question of our age, given the transformation of
presence the cell phone has wrought in contemporary social life and
public space. Throughout all public spaces, cell phones are now a
ubiquitous prosthesis of what Descartes and Hegel once considered
the absolute tool: the hand. Their power comes in part from their
ability to move about with us-they are like a computer, but we can
carry them with us at all times-in part from what they attach to us
(and how), as all that computational and connective power becomes
both handy and hand-sized. Quite surprisingly, despite their name,
one might argue, as Ferraris does, that cell phones are not really
all that good for sound and speaking. Instead, the main
philosophical point of this book is that mobile phones have come
into their own as writing machines-they function best for text
messages, e-mail, and archives of all kinds. Their philosophical
urgency lies in the manner in which they carry us from the effects
of voice over into reliance upon the written traces that are,
Ferraris argues, the basic stuff of human culture. Ontology is the
study of what there is, and what there is in our age is a huge
network of documents, papers, and texts of all kinds. Social
reality is not constructed by collective intentionality; rather, it
is made up of inscribed acts. As Derrida already prophesized, our
world revolves around writing. Cell phones have attached writing to
our fingers and dragged it into public spaces in a new way. This is
why, with their power to obliterate or morph presence and replace
voice with writing, the cell phone is such a philosophically
interesting object.
Positive Realism could be seen as the "sequel" to Maurizio
Ferraris' Manifesto of New Realism and Introduction to New Realism.
The focus here is the other side of unamendability: a notion,
described in his previous books, according to which reality is
"unamendable", it cannot be corrected at will. This "resistance" of
the real is what ultimately tells us that, in opposition to the
claims of post-Kantian philosophy, the world is not a result of our
conceptual work: if it were so, our power over reality would be
much greater. Now, the often disappointing limits that the real
sets against our expectations are also a resource: and this is the
key point of the present book. Things exist, and therefore
undoubtedly resist us, but in doing so they offer affordances,
resources, opportunities. And that the greatest opportunity, which
underlies all the other ones, is the fact that we share a world
that is far from liquid: on the contrary, it provides the solid
ground on which everything rests, starting from our happiness or
unhappiness.
In ontology, realism and anti-realism may be taken as opposite
attitudes towards entities of different kinds, so that one may turn
out to be a realist with respect to certain entities, and an
anti-realist with respect to others. In this book, the editors
focus on this controversy concerning social entities in general and
fictional entities in particular, the latter often being considered
nowadays as kinds of social entities. More specifically,
fictionalists (those who maintain that we only make-believe that
there are entities of a certain kind) and creationists (those who
believe that entities of a certain kind are the products of human
activity) present themselves as the champions of the anti-realist
and the realist stance, respectively, regarding the above entities.
By evaluating the pros and cons of both these positions, this book
intends to focus new light on a longstanding debate.
|
You may like...
Tenet
John David Washington, Robert Pattinson, …
DVD
(1)
R51
Discovery Miles 510
|