|
Showing 1 - 22 of
22 matches in All Departments
We shall be concemed in the following pages with some issues common
to the systems of both Kant and Husserl. Given the structured
nature of philosophical systems, however, the topics cannot be
isolated from the systems in which they function, imbuing them in
each case with a specific direction. An examination of the basic
concept of Anschauung will indicate the difference between the two
systems. To be sure, Anschauung points in both to the visual aspect
of knowledge, an element inherent in the classical concept of
theoria, which is related to the word horao, to see. In Kant,
however, the visual aspect is not the highest component of
cognition, since it is related to sensuality. Anschauung belongs to
the synthesis and not the summit of knowledge. It is given before
thinking, and is present in the ongoing search for relations
between data. In Kant's understanding, pure reason can be related
to data only through the medium of understanding. In this sense, we
could say that Anschauung, being a variation of Schau, is that
which can be perceived with the eyes. In Kant's system, it points
to the presence of that which is given and thus to reception,
whereas knowledge proper is a synthesis of reception and
spontaneity .
There are several characteristics of Nathan Rotenstreich's work
which are striking: his thoughtful writings are both subtle and
deep; they are steeped in his critical appreciation of other
thinkers of this and preceding times, an appreciation which is
formed by his learned understanding of the history of philosophy;
and with all this, he has an original and independent intelligence.
He has from time to time brought his skills to bear upon historical
scholarship, most notably perhaps in his book Between Past and
Present (1958, 2nd edition, 1973), his interpretive essays in the
philosophy of history Philosophy, History and Politics (1976) and
his scholarly work concerned with the influence of historical
development upon modern Jewish thought, Tradition and Reality
(1972). Related to these, and equally works of that philosophical
humanity which Professor Rotenstreich embodies, are his Humanism in
the Contemporary Era (1963), Spirit and Man: An Essay on Being and
Value (1963) and Reflection and Action (1983). Rotenstreich
combines both the naturalistic and the phenomenological attitudes
in an interesting and illuminating way through the full spectrum of
issues in the philosophy of history in this century. Surely he sets
boundaries to any doubtful extrapolation. Not only would he bring
the understanding of history back from those who claim it as only a
positive science but equally would he prevent the transformation of
that understanding into merely speculative inquiry.
Originally published in 1991, this book focuses on a major
problem in the philosophy of Martin Buber. This is the topic of
immediacy which is presented in terms of the contact between human
beings on the one hand, and man and God on the other. The basic
theme throughout is whether the I-Thou relation refers to immediate
contact between human beings, as Buber saw it, or whether that
relation is something established or aspired to. This is an
important study which should be consulted in any future discussion
of Martin Buber's thought. At the same time, it raises critical
issues for recent European philosophy. Students of philosophy, and
religious and social thought will find its critical exposition
extremely helpful.
The present book is concerned with the nature of philosophy and
with the scope of philosophical interest. It combines an analysis
of the major types of philosophical thinking as they emerged in the
history of philosophical ideas with an attempt to examine problems
which recurrent ly emerge in philosophical discourse. It is from
this point of view that the historical and the systematic
approaches are meant to be mutually reinforcing. I am grateful to
my friends who helped me to formulate the line of thinking
expressed in this book: Z. Bar-On, A. Margalit, E. I. I. Poznanski,
Z. Werblovsky and E. Zemach. Some years ago when I visited the
Center for the Study of Democratic Institutions in Santa Barbara,
Dr. Robert M. Hutchins encouraged me to write the present book. I
am dedicating the book to him not only because of that
encouragement but more importantly because as an educational
thinker Dr. Hutchins represents the position which assigns to the
great ideas of the past validity and value in the analysis of
topical problems of the present."
The present book is an exp]oration of some basic issues of Kant's
moral phi losophy. The point of departure is the concept offreedom
and the self-legisla tion of reason. Since self-Iegislation is
expressed in the sphere of practice or morality, it is meant to
overcome some of the vulnerable aspects of Kant's theoretical
philosophy, namely that which Kant himself pointed to and called
the 'lucky chance, ' in so far as the application of reason to
sensuous data is concerned. The book attempts to show that Kant's
practical or moral philosophy faces questions which are parallel to
those he faced in the sphere ofhis theore tical philosophy. The
problematic situation of realization of practice is parallel to the
problematic situation of application of theory. It is in the line
of the problems emerging from Kant's practical philosophy that the
present book deals with some of Kant's minor writings, or
less-known ones, in cluding his writings in the sphere of politics,
history and education. The limitations of self-Iegislation - this
is the theme of the book. The book is parallel to the author's
previous one on Kant: 'Experience and its Systema tization -
Studies in Kant" (Nijhoff, 1965, 2nd edition 1973), as well as to:
"From Substance to Subject -Studies in Hegel" (Nijhoff, 1974).
Jerusalem 1978 ABBREVIATIONS As to the references to Kant's major
works, the following procedme will be ob served: Kritik der reinen
Vernunft will be quoted as Kr. d. r. V."
Originally published in 1991, this book focuses on a major problem
in the philosophy of Martin Buber. This is the topic of immediacy
which is presented in terms of the contact between human beings on
the one hand, and man and God on the other. The basic theme
throughout is whether the I-Thou relation refers to immediate
contact between human beings, as Buber saw it, or whether that
relation is something established or aspired to. This is an
important study which should be consulted in any future discussion
of Martin Buber's thought. At the same time, it raises critical
issues for recent European philosophy. Students of philosophy, and
religious and social thought will find its critical exposition
extremely helpful.
This volume, first published in 1984, contains the principal papers
from a distinguished colloquium held in 1982. Its avowed purpose is
to investigate further the notion of "totalitarian democracy" and
to look at its repercussions in the contemporary world.
The present book is an exp]oration of some basic issues of Kant's
moral phi losophy. The point of departure is the concept offreedom
and the self-legisla tion of reason. Since self-Iegislation is
expressed in the sphere of practice or morality, it is meant to
overcome some of the vulnerable aspects of Kant's theoretical
philosophy, namely that which Kant himself pointed to and called
the 'lucky chance,' in so far as the application of reason to
sensuous data is concerned. The book attempts to show that Kant's
practical or moral philosophy faces questions which are parallel to
those he faced in the sphere ofhis theore tical philosophy. The
problematic situation of realization of practice is parallel to the
problematic situation of application of theory. It is in the line
of the problems emerging from Kant's practical philosophy that the
present book deals with some of Kant's minor writings, or
less-known ones, in cluding his writings in the sphere of politics,
history and education. The limitations of self-Iegislation - this
is the theme of the book. The book is parallel to the author's
previous one on Kant: 'Experience and its Systema tization -
Studies in Kant" (Nijhoff, 1965, 2nd edition 1973), as well as to:
"From Substance to Subject -Studies in Hegel" (Nijhoff, 1974).
Jerusalem 1978 ABBREVIATIONS As to the references to Kant's major
works, the following procedme will be ob served: Kritik der reinen
Vernunft will be quoted as Kr. d. r. V.
There are several characteristics of Nathan Rotenstreich's work
which are striking: his thoughtful writings are both subtle and
deep; they are steeped in his critical appreciation of other
thinkers of this and preceding times, an appreciation which is
formed by his learned understanding of the history of philosophy;
and with all this, he has an original and independent intelligence.
He has from time to time brought his skills to bear upon historical
scholarship, most notably perhaps in his book Between Past and
Present (1958, 2nd edition, 1973), his interpretive essays in the
philosophy of history Philosophy, History and Politics (1976) and
his scholarly work concerned with the influence of historical
development upon modern Jewish thought, Tradition and Reality
(1972). Related to these, and equally works of that philosophical
humanity which Professor Rotenstreich embodies, are his Humanism in
the Contemporary Era (1963), Spirit and Man: An Essay on Being and
Value (1963) and Reflection and Action (1983). Rotenstreich
combines both the naturalistic and the phenomenological attitudes
in an interesting and illuminating way through the full spectrum of
issues in the philosophy of history in this century. Surely he sets
boundaries to any doubtful extrapolation. Not only would he bring
the understanding of history back from those who claim it as only a
positive science but equally would he prevent the transformation of
that understanding into merely speculative inquiry.
We shall be concemed in the following pages with some issues common
to the systems of both Kant and Husserl. Given the structured
nature of philosophical systems, however, the topics cannot be
isolated from the systems in which they function, imbuing them in
each case with a specific direction. An examination of the basic
concept of Anschauung will indicate the difference between the two
systems. To be sure, Anschauung points in both to the visual aspect
of knowledge, an element inherent in the classical concept of
theoria, which is related to the word horao, to see. In Kant,
however, the visual aspect is not the highest component of
cognition, since it is related to sensuality. Anschauung belongs to
the synthesis and not the summit of knowledge. It is given before
thinking, and is present in the ongoing search for relations
between data. In Kant's understanding, pure reason can be related
to data only through the medium of understanding. In this sense, we
could say that Anschauung, being a variation of Schau, is that
which can be perceived with the eyes. In Kant's system, it points
to the presence of that which is given and thus to reception,
whereas knowledge proper is a synthesis of reception and
spontaneity .
The present book is concerned with the nature of philosophy and
with the scope of philosophical interest. It combines an analysis
of the major types of philosophical thinking as they emerged in the
history of philosophical ideas with an attempt to examine problems
which recurrent ly emerge in philosophical discourse. It is from
this point of view that the historical and the systematic
approaches are meant to be mutually reinforcing. I am grateful to
my friends who helped me to formulate the line of thinking
expressed in this book: Z. Bar-On, A. Margalit, E. I. I. Poznanski,
Z. Werblovsky and E. Zemach. Some years ago when I visited the
Center for the Study of Democratic Institutions in Santa Barbara,
Dr. Robert M. Hutchins encouraged me to write the present book. I
am dedicating the book to him not only because of that
encouragement but more importantly because as an educational
thinker Dr. Hutchins represents the position which assigns to the
great ideas of the past validity and value in the analysis of
topical problems of the present."
Haskala is the Hebrew term for 'Enlightenment', which the Jerusalem
symposium evolved in the facets of its evaluation. As a result the
confrontation was resolved; there were conflicts, even
controversies among Jews as well as among non-Jews, of which much
was included in this volume.
Traces the dialectical connections between Zionism's past and
present.
|
|