|
Showing 1 - 11 of
11 matches in All Departments
Widespread moral disagreement raises ethical, epistemological,
political, and metaethical questions. Is the best explanation of
our widespread moral disagreements that there are no objective
moral facts and that moral relativism is correct? Or should we
think that just as there is widespread disagreement about whether
we have free will but there is still an objective fact about
whether we have it, similarly, moral disagreement has no bearing on
whether morality is objective? More practically, is it arrogant to
stick to our guns in the face of moral disagreement? Must we
suspend belief about the morality of controversial actions such as
eating meat and having an abortion? And does moral disagreement
affect the laws that we should have? For instance, does
disagreement about the justice of heavily redistributive taxation
affect whether such taxation is legitimate? In this thorough and
clearly written introduction to moral disagreement and its
philosophical and practical implications, Richard Rowland examines
and assesses the following topics and questions: How does moral
disagreement affect what we should do and believe in our day-to-day
lives? Epistemic peerhood and moral disagreements with our
epistemic peers. Metaethics and moral disagreement. Relativism,
moral objectivity, moral realism, and non-cognitivism. Moral
disagreement and normative ethics. Liberalism, democracy, and
disagreement. Moral compromise. Moral uncertainty. Combining clear
philosophical analysis with summaries of the latest research and
suggestions for further reading, Moral Disagreement is ideal for
students of ethics, metaethics, political philosophy, and
philosophical topics that are closely related, such as relativism
and scepticism. It will also be of interest to those in related
disciplines such as public policy and philosophy of law.
Widespread moral disagreement raises ethical, epistemological,
political, and metaethical questions. Is the best explanation of
our widespread moral disagreements that there are no objective
moral facts and that moral relativism is correct? Or should we
think that just as there is widespread disagreement about whether
we have free will but there is still an objective fact about
whether we have it, similarly, moral disagreement has no bearing on
whether morality is objective? More practically, is it arrogant to
stick to our guns in the face of moral disagreement? Must we
suspend belief about the morality of controversial actions such as
eating meat and having an abortion? And does moral disagreement
affect the laws that we should have? For instance, does
disagreement about the justice of heavily redistributive taxation
affect whether such taxation is legitimate? In this thorough and
clearly written introduction to moral disagreement and its
philosophical and practical implications, Richard Rowland examines
and assesses the following topics and questions: How does moral
disagreement affect what we should do and believe in our day-to-day
lives? Epistemic peerhood and moral disagreements with our
epistemic peers. Metaethics and moral disagreement. Relativism,
moral objectivity, moral realism, and non-cognitivism. Moral
disagreement and normative ethics. Liberalism, democracy, and
disagreement. Moral compromise. Moral uncertainty. Combining clear
philosophical analysis with summaries of the latest research and
suggestions for further reading, Moral Disagreement is ideal for
students of ethics, metaethics, political philosophy, and
philosophical topics that are closely related, such as relativism
and scepticism. It will also be of interest to those in related
disciplines such as public policy and philosophy of law.
In this major reassessment of his subject, Richard Rowland restores
Thomas Heywood-playwright, miscellanist and translator-to his
rightful place in early modern theatre history. Rowland
contextualizes and historicizes this important contemporary of
Shakespeare, locating him on the geographic and cultural map of
London through the business Heywood conducts in his writing.
Arguing that Heywood's theatrical output deserves the same
attention and study that has been directed towards Shakespeare,
Jonson, and more recently Middleton, this book looks at three
periods of Heywood's creativity: the end of the Elizabethan era and
the beginning of the Jacobean, the mid 1620s, and the mid to late
1630s. By locating the works of those years precisely in the
political and cultural conflicts to which they respond, Rowland
initiates a major reassessment of the remarkable achievements of
this playwright. Rowland also pays attention to Heywood in
performance, seeing this writer as a jobbing playwright working in
an industry that depended on making writing work. Finally, the
author explores how Heywood participated in the civic life of
London in his writings beyond the playhouse. Here Rowland examines
pamphlets, translations, and the sequence of lord mayor's pageants
that Heywood produced as the political crisis deepened. Offering
close readings of Heywood that establish the range, quality and
theatrical significance of the writing, Thomas Heywood's Theatre,
1599-1639 fits a fascinating piece into the emerging picture of the
'complete' early modern English theatre.
Edward IV (1599) was printed no less than six times up to 1626, and
was one of the best loved plays of the early modern period, but
this edition is the first since the 1870s. Controversy surrounds
every aspect of the play. Disputes over the ownership of the
inn-yard playhouse in which it was first played erupted into
violence during performances. The little known troop which first
acted Edward IV used it to challenge the domination of the two
principal companies. The play premiered at a moment when the
representation of medieval history in any format was coming under
the hostile scrutiny of the Elizabethan government. Yet the
playwright produced a text which was at once generically complex
(the play blurs the distinction between chronicle history and
'domestic' tragedy), brilliantly assured in its dramatic
craftsmanship, and politically explosive. The play depicts the
streets and houses in which its original spectators lived and
worked with a precision unprecedented in English writing. But this
vividly realised London is under assault, first from rebels outside
its walls, and subsequently (and more seriously) from the
predations of two monarchs. The text of this edition has already
been used by the actors at Shakespeare's Globe when they gave the
first London performance of Edward IV for more than four centuries.
By demonstrating the playwright's dextrous marshalling of a
remarkable range of sources, and by examining afresh the
dramatist's singular theatrical technique, this volume opens up an
exciting if difficult play to a new generation of scholars and
performers.
This book offers an entirely new reception history of the myth of
Hercules and his wife/killer Deianira. The book poses, and attempts
to answer, two important and related questions. First, why have
artists across two millennia felt compelled to revisit this
particular myth to express anxieties about violence at both a
global and domestic level? Secondly, from the moment that Sophocles
disrupted a myth about the definitive exemplar of masculinity and
martial prowess and turned it into a story about domestic abuse,
through to a 2014 production of Handel's Hercules that was set in
the context of the 'war on terror', the reception history of this
myth has been one of discontinuity and conflict; how and why does
each culture reinvent this narrative to address its own concerns
and discontents, and how does each generation speak to, qualify or
annihilate the certainties of its predecessors in order to
understand, contain or exonerate the aggression with which their
governors - of state and of the household - so often enforce their
authority, and the violence to which their nations, and their
homes, are perennially vulnerable?
This book offers an entirely new reception history of the myth of
Hercules and his wife/killer Deianira. The book poses, and attempts
to answer, two important and related questions. First, why have
artists across two millennia felt compelled to revisit this
particular myth to express anxieties about violence at both a
global and domestic level? Secondly, from the moment that Sophocles
disrupted a myth about the definitive exemplar of masculinity and
martial prowess and turned it into a story about domestic abuse,
through to a 2014 production of Handel's Hercules that was set in
the context of the 'war on terror', the reception history of this
myth has been one of discontinuity and conflict; how and why does
each culture reinvent this narrative to address its own concerns
and discontents, and how does each generation speak to, qualify or
annihilate the certainties of its predecessors in order to
understand, contain or exonerate the aggression with which their
governors - of state and of the household - so often enforce their
authority, and the violence to which their nations, and their
homes, are perennially vulnerable?
Marlowe's highly controversial Edward II concerns the conflicting
claims of love and politics, the urgency of homoerotic desire, and
the cruelty with which unscrupulous authority can exert control.
The boldness with which the work confronts these issues makes it
unique in the period, yet this is the first critical edition of the
play with full scholarly apparatus for twenty-five years. Richard
Rowland's edition presents an old-spelling text which adheres more
closely to the first quarto of 1594 than any edition hitherto. The
present volume is the third in the Oxford English Texts Complete
Works of Christopher Marlowe. A full commentary and introduction
contextualize the play and give an entirely original account of the
relationship betweeen the play, Marlowe's own age, and events which
immediately followed it. By re-examining textual cruces, new
interpretative possibilities are opened up, and the play is related
to the language and ideas of Marlowe's contemporaries. A generous
selection from Holinshed, Marlowe's principal source, is also
included. As critics and historians continue to debate attitudes to
love, sexuality, and politics during the English Renaissance, this
edition of Edward II extends that debate, offering a new
understanding of the eroticism and violence of the play.
Comparisons between morality and other 'companion' disciplines -
such as mathematics, religion, or aesthetics - are commonly used in
philosophy, often in the context of arguing for the objectivity of
morality. This is known as the 'companions in guilt' strategy. It
has been the subject of much debate in contemporary ethics and
metaethics. This volume, the first full length examination of
companions in guilt arguments, comprises an introduction by the
editors and a dozen new chapters by leading authors in the field.
They examine the methodology of companions in guilt arguments and
their use in responding to the moral error theory, as well as
specific arguments that take mathematics, epistemic norms, or
aesthetics as a 'companion', and the use of the companions in guilt
strategy to vindicate claims to moral knowledge. Companions in
Guilt Arguments in Metaethics is essential reading for advanced
students and researchers working in moral theory and metaethics, as
well as those in epistemology and philosophy of mathematics
concerned with the intersection of these subjects with ethics.
|
You may like...
Ab Wheel
R209
R149
Discovery Miles 1 490
|