|
Showing 1 - 6 of
6 matches in All Departments
Decolonizing Universalism argues that feminism can respect cultural
and religious differences and acknowledge the legacy of imperialism
without surrendering its core ethical commitments. Transcending
relativism/ universalism debates that reduce feminism to a Western
notion, Serene J. Khader proposes a feminist vision that is
sensitive to postcolonial and antiracist concerns. Khader
criticizes the false universalism of what she calls 'Enlightenment
liberalism,' a worldview according to which the West is the one
true exemplar of gender justice and moral progress is best achieved
through economic independence and the abandonment of tradition. She
argues that anti-imperialist feminists must rediscover the
normative core of feminism and rethink the role of moral ideals in
transnational feminist praxis. What emerges is a nonideal
universalism that rejects missionary feminisms that treat Western
intervention and the spread of Enlightenment liberalism as the path
to global gender injustice. The book draws on evidence from
transnational women's movements and development practice in
addition to arguments from political philosophy and postcolonial
and decolonial theory, offering a rich moral vision for
twenty-first century feminism.
The Routledge Companion to Feminist Philosophy is an outstanding
guide and reference source to the key topics, subjects, thinkers,
and debates in feminist philosophy. Fifty-six chapters, written by
an international team of contributors specifically for the
Companion, are organized into five sections: (1) Engaging the Past;
(2) Mind, Body, and World; (3) Knowledge, Language, and Science;
(4) Intersections; (5) Ethics, Politics, and Aesthetics. The volume
provides a mutually enriching representation of the several
philosophical traditions that contribute to feminist philosophy. It
also foregrounds issues of global concern and scope; shows how
feminist theory meshes with rich theoretical approaches that start
from transgender identities, race and ethnicity, sexuality,
disabilities, and other axes of identity and oppression; and
highlights the interdisciplinarity of feminist philosophy and the
ways that it both critiques and contributes to the whole range of
subfields within philosophy.
Women and other oppressed and deprived people sometimes collude
with the forces that perpetuate injustice against them. Women's
acceptance of their lesser claim on household resources like food,
their positive attitudes toward clitoridectemy and infibulations,
their acquiescence to violence at the hands of their husbands, and
their sometimes fatalistic attitudes toward their own poverty or
suffering are all examples of "adaptive preferences," wherein women
participate in their own deprivation.
Adaptive Preferences and Women's Empowerment offers a definition of
adaptive preference and a moral framework for responding to
adaptive preferences in development practice. Khader defines
adaptive preferences as deficits in the capacity to lead a
flourishing human life that are causally related to deprivation and
argues that public institutions should conduct deliberative
interventions to transform the adaptive preferences of deprived
people. She insists that people with adaptive preferences can
experience value distortion, but she explains how this fact does
not undermine those people's claim to participate in designing
development interventions that determine the course of their lives.
Khader claims that adaptive preference identification requires a
commitment to moral universalism, but this commitment need not be
incompatible with a respect for culturally variant conceptions of
the good. She illustrates her arguments with examples from
real-world development practice.
Khader's deliberative perfectionist approach moves us beyond
apparent impasses in the debates about internalized oppression and
autonomous agency, relativism and universalism, and feminism and
multiculturalism.
The Routledge Companion to Feminist Philosophy is an outstanding
guide and reference source to the key topics, subjects, thinkers,
and debates in feminist philosophy. Fifty-six chapters, written by
an international team of contributors specifically for the
Companion, are organized into five sections: (1) Engaging the Past;
(2) Mind, Body, and World; (3) Knowledge, Language, and Science;
(4) Intersections; (5) Ethics, Politics, and Aesthetics. The volume
provides a mutually enriching representation of the several
philosophical traditions that contribute to feminist philosophy. It
also foregrounds issues of global concern and scope; shows how
feminist theory meshes with rich theoretical approaches that start
from transgender identities, race and ethnicity, sexuality,
disabilities, and other axes of identity and oppression; and
highlights the interdisciplinarity of feminist philosophy and the
ways that it both critiques and contributes to the whole range of
subfields within philosophy.
Women and other oppressed and deprived people sometimes collude
with the forces that perpetuate injustice against them. Women's
acceptance of their lesser claim on household resources like food,
their positive attitudes toward clitoridectemy and infibulations,
their acquiescence to violence at the hands of their husbands, and
their sometimes fatalistic attitudes toward their own poverty or
suffering are all examples of "adaptive preferences," wherein women
participate in their own deprivation.
Adaptive Preferences and Women's Empowerment offers a definition of
adaptive preference and a moral framework for responding to
adaptive preferences in development practice. Khader defines
adaptive preferences as deficits in the capacity to lead a
flourishing human life that are causally related to deprivation and
argues that public institutions should conduct deliberative
interventions to transform the adaptive preferences of deprived
people. She insists that people with adaptive preferences can
experience value distortion, but she explains how this fact does
not undermine those people's claim to participate in designing
development interventions that determine the course of their lives.
Khader claims that adaptive preference identification requires a
commitment to moral universalism, but this commitment need not be
incompatible with a respect for culturally variant conceptions of
the good. She illustrates her arguments with examples from
real-world development practice.
Khader's deliberative perfectionist approach moves us beyond
apparent impasses in the debates about internalized oppression and
autonomous agency, relativism and universalism, and feminism and
multiculturalism.
Decolonizing Universalism argues that feminism can respect cultural
and religious differences and acknowledge the legacy of imperialism
without surrendering its core ethical commitments. Transcending
relativism/ universalism debates that reduce feminism to a Western
notion, Serene J. Khader proposes a feminist vision that is
sensitive to postcolonial and antiracist concerns. Khader
criticizes the false universalism of what she calls 'Enlightenment
liberalism,' a worldview according to which the West is the one
true exemplar of gender justice and moral progress is best achieved
through economic independence and the abandonment of tradition. She
argues that anti-imperialist feminists must rediscover the
normative core of feminism and rethink the role of moral ideals in
transnational feminist praxis. What emerges is a nonideal
universalism that rejects missionary feminisms that treat Western
intervention and the spread of Enlightenment liberalism as the path
to global gender injustice. The book draws on evidence from
transnational women's movements and development practice in
addition to arguments from political philosophy and postcolonial
and decolonial theory, offering a rich moral vision for
twenty-first century feminism.
|
You may like...
Oh My My
OneRepublic
CD
(4)
R68
Discovery Miles 680
Dune: Part 2
Timothee Chalamet, Zendaya, …
DVD
R221
Discovery Miles 2 210
|