|
Showing 1 - 5 of
5 matches in All Departments
The seventeenth century witnesses the demise of two core doctrines
in the theory of perception: naive realism about color, sound, and
other sensible qualities and the empirical theory, drawn from
Alhacen and Roger Bacon, which underwrote it. This created a
problem for seventeenth century philosophers: how is that we use
qualities such as color, feel, and sound to locate objects in the
world, even though these qualities are not real? Ejecting such
sensible qualities from the mind-independent world at once makes
for a cleaner ontology, since bodies can now be understood in
purely geometrical terms, and spawns a variety of fascinating
complications for the philosophy of perception. If sensible
qualities are not part of the mind-independent world, just what are
they, and what role, if any, do they play in our cognitive economy?
We seemingly have to use color to visually experience objects. Do
we do so by inferring size, shape, and motion from color? Or is it
a purely automatic operation, accomplished by divine decree? This
volume traces the debate over perceptual experience in early modern
France, covering such figures as Antoine Arnauld, Robert Desgabets,
and Pierre-Sylvain Regis alongside their better-known countrymen
Rene Descartes and Nicolas Malebranche.
Some philosophers think physical explanations stand on their own:
what happens, happens because things have the properties they do.
Others think that any such explanation is incomplete: what happens
in the physical world must be partly due to the laws of nature.
Causation and Laws of Nature inEarly Modern Philosophy examines the
debate between these views from Descartes to Hume.
Ott argues that the competing models of causation in the period
grow out of the scholastic notion of power. On this Aristotelian
view, the connection between cause and effect is logically
necessary. Causes are 'intrinsically directed' at what they
produce. But when the Aristotelian view is faced with the challenge
of mechanism, the core notion of a power splits into two distinct
models, each of which persists throughout the early modern period.
It is only when seen in this light that the key arguments of the
period can reveal their true virtues and flaws.
To make his case, Ott explores such central topics as
intentionality, the varieties of necessity, and the nature of
relations. Arguing for controversial readings of many of the
canonical figures, the book also focuses on lesser-known writers
such as Pierre-Sylvain Regis, Nicolas Malebranche, and Robert
Boyle.
Some philosophers think physical explanations stand on their own:
what happens, happens because things have the properties they do.
Others think that any such explanation is incomplete: what happens
in the physical world must be partly due to the laws of nature.
Causation and Laws of Nature in Early Modern Philosophy examines
the debate between these views from Descartes to Hume. Ott argues
that the competing models of causation in the period grow out of
the scholastic notion of power. On this Aristotelian view, the
connection between cause and effect is logically necessary. Causes
are 'intrinsically directed' at what they produce. But when the
Aristotelian view is faced with the challenge of mechanism, the
core notion of a power splits into two distinct models, each of
which persists throughout the early modern period. It is only when
seen in this light that the key arguments of the period can reveal
their true virtues and flaws. To make his case, Ott explores such
central topics as intentionality, the varieties of necessity, and
the nature of relations. Arguing for controversial readings of many
of the canonical figures, the book also focuses on lesser-known
writers such as Pierre-Sylvain Regis, Nicolas Malebranche, and
Robert Boyle.
It can seem obvious that we live in a world governed by laws of
nature, yet it was not until the seventeenth century that the
concept of a law came to the fore. Ever since, it has been attended
by controversy: what does it mean to say that Boyle's law governs
the expansion of a gas, or that the planets obey the law of
gravity? Laws are rules that permit calculations and predictions.
What does the universe have to be like, if it is to play by them?
This book sorts the most prominent answers into three families.
Laws first arose in a theological context; they govern events only
because God enforces them. Those wishing to reverse the order of
explanation, and argue that the powers of objects fix the laws,
struggled to claim for themselves the results of new science. The
stand-off between these two families bred a third which rejects any
kind of enforcer for the laws. On this view, laws summarize events;
they do not govern anything. This book traces the fortunes of the
three families, from their origins to the present day. It uses
objections - and the revisions needed to answer them - to produce
the best representative of each. Along the way, it tries to settle
the rules of this game, the debate over laws of nature. What should
we expect from an account of laws? The book aims to help readers
develop their own desiderata and judge the merits of the competing
positions.
What is the origin of the concept of a law of nature? How much does
it owe to theology and metaphysics? To what extent do the laws of
nature permit contingency? Are there exceptions to the laws of
nature? Is it possible to give a reductive analysis of lawhood, or
is it a primitive? Twelve new essays by an international team of
leading philosophers take up these and other central questions on
the laws of nature, whilst also examining some of the most
important intuitions and assumptions that have guided the debate
over laws of nature since the concepts invention in the seventeenth
century. Laws of Nature spans the history of philosophy and of
science, contemporary metaphysics, and contemporary philosophy of
science.
|
You may like...
Origins
Imagine Dragons
CD
R289
Discovery Miles 2 890
Loot
Nadine Gordimer
Paperback
(2)
R391
R362
Discovery Miles 3 620
|