|
Books > Humanities > Religion & beliefs > General > Philosophy of religion > General
Plotinus' mysticism of henosis, unification with the One, is a
highly controversial topic in Plotinian scholarship. This book
presents a careful reading of the Enneads and suggests that
Plotinus' mysticism be understood as mystical teaching that offers
practical guidance concerning henosis. It is further argued that a
rational interpretation thereof should be based on Plotinus'
metaphysics, according to which the One transcends all beings but
is immanent in them. The main thesis of this book is that Plotinus'
mystical teaching does not help man attain henosis on his own, but
serves to remind man that he fails to attain henosis because it
already pertains to his original condition. Plotinus' mysticism
seeks to change man's misconception about henosis, rather than his
finite nature.
This book addresses the different forms that religious belief can
take. Two primary forms are discussed: propositional or doctrinal
belief, and belief in God. Religious belief in God, whose affective
content is trust in God, it is seen, opens for believers a
relationship to God defined by trust in God. The book addresses the
issue of the relation between belief and faith, the issue of what
Soren Kierkegaard called the subjectivity of faith, and the issue
of the relation between religious belief and religious experience.
After the introductory chapter the book continues with a chapter in
which features and forms of belief allowed by the general concept
of belief are presented. Several of these forms and features are
related to the features of religious belief examined in succeeding
chapters. The book's final chapter examines God-relationships in
the Christian tradition that de-emphasize belief and are not
defined by belief.
This book provides a coherent and systematic analysis of Miguel de
Unamuno's notion of religious faith and the reasoning he offers in
defense of it. Unamuno developed a non-cognitivist Christian
conception of religious faith, defending it as being something
which we are all naturally lead to, given our (alleged) most basic
and natural inclination to seek an endless existence. Illuminating
the philosophical relevance this conception still has to
contemporary philosophy of religion, Oya draws connections with
current non-cognitivist notions of religious faith in general, and
with contemporary religious fictionalist positions more
particularly. The book includes a biographical introduction to
Miguel de Unamuno, as well as lucid and clear analyses of his
notions of the 'tragic feeling of life', his epistemological
paradigm, and his naturally founded religious fictionalism.
Revealing links to current debates, Oya shows how the works of
Unamuno are still relevant and enriching today
Robinson Crusoe recognizes it is foolish to leave for the open
seas; nevertheless, he boards the ship. William Wordsworth of The
Prelude sees the immense poetic task ahead of him, but instead of
beginning work, he procrastinates by going for a walk. Centering on
this sort of intentionally irrational action, originally defined as
" akrasia" by the ancient Greeks and "weakness of will" in early
Christian thought, Against Better Judgment argues that the
phenomenon takes on renewed importance in the long eighteenth
century.In treating human minds and bodies as systems and machines,
Enlightenment philosophers did not account for actions that may be
undermotivated, contradictory, or self-betraying. A number of
authors, from Daniel Defoe and Samuel Johnson to Jane Austen and
John Keats, however, took up the phenomenon in inventive ways.
Thomas Manganaro traces how English novelists, essayists, and poets
of the period sought to represent akrasia in ways philosophy
cannot, leading them to develop techniques and ideas distinctive to
literary writing, including new uses of irony, interpretation, and
contradiction. In attempting to give shape to the ways people
knowingly and freely fail themselves, these authors produced a new
linguistic toolkit that distinguishes literature's epistemological
advantages when it comes to writing about people.
For generations, early Franciscan thought has been widely regarded
as unoriginal: a mere attempt to systematize the longstanding
intellectual tradition of Augustine in the face of the rising
popularity of Aristotle. This volume brings together leading
scholars in the field to undertake a major study of the sources and
context of the so-called Summa Halensis (1236-45), which was
collaboratively authored by the founding members of the Franciscan
school at Paris, above all, Alexander of Hales, and John of La
Rochelle, in an effort to lay down the Franciscan intellectual
tradition or the first time. The contributions will highlight that
this tradition, far from unoriginal, laid the groundwork for later
Franciscan thought, which is often regarded as formative for modern
thought. Furthermore, the volume shows the role this Summa played
in the development of the burgeoning field of systematic theology,
which has its origins in the young university of Paris. This is a
crucial and groundbreaking study for those with interests in the
history of western thought and theology specifically.
This book is a study in a new form of religious naturalism called
"Deep Pantheism," which has roots in American Transcendentalism,
but also in phenomenology and Asian thought. It argues that the
great divide within nature is that between nature naturing and
nature natured, the former term defined as "Nature creating itself
out of itself alone," while the latter term defined as "The
innumerable orders of the World." Explorations are made of the
connections among the unconscious of nature, the archetypes, and
the various layers of the human psyche. The Selving process is
analyzed using the work of C.G.Jung and Otto Rank. Evolution and
involution are compared as they relate to the Encompassing, and the
priority of art over most forms of religion is argued for.
The volume focuses on the relation between Cusanus and Aristotle or
the Aristotelian tradition. In recent years the attention on this
topic has partially increased, but overall the scholarship results
are still partial or provisional. The book thus aims at verifying
more systematically how Aristotle and Aristotelianism have been
received by Cusanus, in both their philosophical and theological
implications, and how he approached the Aristotelian thought. In
order to answer these questions, the papers are structured
according to the traditional Aristotelian sciences and their
reflection on Cusanus' thought. This allows to achieve some aspects
of interest and originality: 1) the book provides a general, but
systematic analysis of Aristotle's reception in Cusanus' thought,
with some coherent results. 2) Also, it explores how a philosopher
and theologian traditionally regarded as Neoplatonist approached
Aristotle and his tradition (including Thomas Aquinas), what he
accepted of it, what he rejected, and what he tried to overcome. 3)
Finally, the volume verifies the attitude of a relevant Christian
philosopher and theologian of the Humanistic age towards Aristotle.
|
|