|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Metaphysics & ontology
Scientific realism is a central, long-standing, and hotly debated
topic in philosophy of science. Debates about scientific realism
concern the very nature and extent of scientific knowledge and
progress. Scientific realists defend a positive epistemic attitude
towards our best theories and models regarding how they represent
the world that is unobservable to our naked senses. Various realist
theses are under sceptical fire from scientific antirealists, e.g.
empiricists and instrumentalists. The different dimensions of the
ensuing debate centrally connect to numerous other topics in
philosophy of science and beyond. The Routledge Handbook of
Scientific Realism is an outstanding reference source - the first
collection of its kind - to the key issues, positions, and
arguments in this important topic. Its thirty-four chapters,
written by a team of international experts, are divided into five
parts: Historical development of the realist stance Classic debate:
core issues and positions Perspectives on contemporary debates The
realism debate in disciplinary context Broader reflections In these
sections, the core issues and debates presented, analysed, and set
into broader historical and disciplinary contexts. The central
issues covered include motivations and arguments for realism;
challenges to realism from underdetermination and history of
science; different variants of realism; the connection of realism
to relativism and perspectivism; and the relationship between
realism, metaphysics, and epistemology. The Routledge Handbook of
Scientific Realism is essential reading for students and
researchers in philosophy of science. It will also be very useful
for anyone interested in the nature and extent of scientific
knowledge.
This is the first comprehensive book-length introduction to the
philosophy of Western music that fully integrates consideration of
popular music and hybrid musical forms, especially song. Its
author, Andrew Kania, begins by asking whether Bob Dylan should
even have been eligible for the Nobel Prize in Literature, given
that he is a musician. This motivates a discussion of music as an
artistic medium, and what philosophy has to contribute to our
thinking about music. Chapters 2-5 investigate the most commonly
defended sources of musical value: its emotional power, its form,
and specifically musical features (such as pitch, rhythm, and
harmony). In chapters 6-9, Kania explores issues arising from
different musical practices, particularly work-performance (with a
focus on classical music), improvisation (with a focus on jazz),
and recording (with a focus on rock and pop). Chapter 10 examines
the intersection of music and morality. The book ends with a
consideration of what, ultimately, music is. Key Features Uses
popular-song examples throughout, but also discusses a range of
musical traditions (notably, rock, pop, classical, and jazz)
Explains both philosophical and musical terms when they are first
introduced Provides publicly accessible Spotify playlists of the
musical examples discussed in the book Each chapter begins with an
overview and ends with questions for testing comprehension and
stimulating further thought, along with suggestions for further
reading
This volume of newly written chapters on the history and
interpretation of Wittgenstein's Tractatus represents a significant
step beyond the polemical debate between broad interpretive
approaches that has recently characterized the field. Some of the
contributors might count their approach as 'new' or 'resolute',
while others are more 'traditional', but all are here concerned
primarily with understanding in detail the structure of argument
that Wittgenstein presents within the Tractatus, rather than with
its final self-renunciation, or with the character of the
understanding that renunciation might leave behind. The volume
makes a strong case that close investigation, both biographical and
textual, into the composition of the Tractatus, and into the
various influences on it, still has much to yield in revealing the
complexity and fertility of Wittgenstein's early thought. Amongst
these influences Kant and Kierkegaard are considered alongside
Wittgenstein's immediate predecessors in the analytic tradition.
The themes explored range across the breadth of Wittgenstein's
book, and include his accounts of ethics and aesthetics, as well as
issues in metaphysics and the philosophy of mind, and aspects of
the logical framework of his account of representation. The
contrast of saying and showing, and Wittgenstein's attitude to the
inexpressible, is of central importance to many of the
contributions. By approaching this concern through the various
first-level issues that give rise to it, rather than from
entrenched schematic positions, the contributors demonstrate the
possibility of a more inclusive, constructive and fruitful mode of
engagement with Wittgenstein's text and with each other.
Accounts of human and animal action have been central to modern
philosophy from Suarez and Hobbes in the sixteenth century to
Wittgenstein and Anscombe in the mid-twentieth century via Locke,
Hume, Kant, and Hegel, among many others. Philosophies of action
have thus greatly influenced the course of both moral philosophy
and the philosophy of mind. This book gathers together specialists
from both the philosophy of action and the history of philosophy
with the aim of re-assessing the wider philosophical impact of
action theory. It thereby explores how different notions of action,
agency, reasons for action, motives, intention, purpose, and
volition have affected modern philosophical understandings of
topics as diverse as those of human nature, mental causation,
responsibility, free will, moral motivation, rationality,
normativity, choice and decision theory, criminal liability,
weakness of will, and moral and social obligation. In so doing, it
reinterprets the history of modern philosophy through the lens of
action theory while also tracing the origins of contemporary
questions in the philosophy of action back across half a
millennium. This book was originally published as a special issue
of Philosophical Explorations.
On Heidegger's Being and Time is an outstanding exploration of
Heidegger's most important work by two major philosophers. Simon
Critchley argues that we must see Being and Time as a
radicalization of Husserl's phenomenology, particularly his
theories of intentionality, categorial intuition, and the
phenomenological concept of the a priori. This leads to a
reappraisal and defense of Heidegger's conception of phenomenology.
In contrast, Reiner Schurmann urges us to read Heidegger
'backward', arguing that his later work is the key to unravelling
Being and Time. Through a close reading of Being and Time Schurmann
demonstrates that this work is ultimately aporetic because the
notion of Being elaborated in his later work is already at play
within it. This is the first time that Schurmann's renowned
lectures on Heidegger have been published. The book concludes with
Critchley's reinterpretation of the importance of authenticity in
Being and Time. Arguing for what he calls an 'originary
inauthenticity', Critchley proposes a relational understanding of
the key concepts of the second part of Being and Time: death,
conscience and temporality.
In recent decades, the analysis of causal relations has become a
topic of central importance in analytic philosophy. More recently,
dispositional properties have also become objects of intense study.
Both of these phenomena appear to be intimately related to
counterfactual conditionals and other modal phenomena such as
objective chance, but little work has been done to directly relate
them. Dispositions and Causes contains ten essays by scholars
working in both metaphysics and in philosophy of science, examining
the relation between dispositional and causal concepts.
Particular issues discussed include the possibility of reducing
dispositions to causes, and vice versa; the possibility of a
nominalist theory of causal powers; the attempt to reduce all
metaphysical necessity to dispositional properties; the
relationship between dispositions, causes, and laws of nature; the
role of causal capacities in explaining the success of scientific
inquiry; the grounding of dispositions and causes in objective
chances; and the type of causal power required for free agency.
The introductory chapter contains a detailed overview of recent
work in the area, providing a helpful entry to the literature for
non-specialists.
The importance of Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason in the
history of philosophy is matched only by its difficulty. In
particular, readers are often frustrated by how difficult it is to
extract Kant's arguments from his dense prose. This book
reconstructs, using the tools of propositional logic, the central
arguments of the Critique. In all, the book reconstructs thirty-six
of Kant's arguments spanning the Transcendental Aesthetic,
Transcendental Analytic, and Transcendental Dialectic. For each
argument, they begin with a quote from Kant's text followed by a
synopsis that explains the argument informally. Finally, each
synopsis is followed by a formal reconstruction of the argument.
The synopses offer examples, metaphors, historical background, and
objections/responses to aid the reader in appreciating Kant's
arguments. Even though many readers who approach Kant for the first
time have a good philosophical vocabulary, few will understand
Kant's unique lexicon. In addition to formally reconstructing
Kant's arguments, the book also includes a glossary that defines
the technical terms that Kant uses in his arguments. Finally, since
this book is directed largely at students, Bryan Hall enlisted two
of his own students to ensure that the book is maximally student
friendly. In contrast to most pedagogical philosophical literature,
the content of this book has been tailored by students for
students.
First published in 1962, Bodily Sensations argues that bodily
sensations are nothing but impressions that physical happenings are
taking place in the body, impressions that may correspond or fail
to correspond to physical reality. In the case of such sensations
as pains, these impressions are accompanied by certain attitudes to
the impressions. He argues, that is to say that bodily sensations
are a sub-species of sense-impression, standing to perception of
our own bodily state (or in some cases to touch) as visual
impressions stand to the sense of sight. He examines, and tries to
refute, all plausible alternative accounts of the nature of bodily
sensations. He prefaces his argument by an account of tactual and
bodily perception. Here he argues that, with the exception of heat
and cold, the qualities discerned by these senses are all reducible
to spatial and temporal properties of material objects. Combined
with his own conclusions on bodily sensations, this allows him to
draw up a short and exhaustive list of the so-called "secondary"
qualities of physical objects. This book will be of interest to
students of philosophy.
First published in 1927, The Nature of Deity forms a sequel to
Personality and Reality. The premise of this book is the conclusion
of the prequel: that there exists a Supreme Self or Deity. In
pursuing this argument, the author uses logic and broad facts that
prove the existence of a Supreme Self. This book will be of
interest to students of philosophy, religion, literature and
science.
Modal realism says that non-actual possible worlds and individuals
are as real as the actual world and individuals. Takashi Yagisawa
defends modal realism of a variety different from David Lewis's
theory. The notion of reality is left primitive and sharply
distinguished from that of existence, which is proposed as a
relation between a thing and a domain. Worlds are postulated as
modal indices for truth on a par with times, which are temporal
indices for truth. Ordinary individual objects are conceived as
being extended in spatial, temporal, and modal dimensions, and
their transworld identity is explicated by the closest-continuer
theory. Impossible worlds and individuals are postulated and used
to provide accounts of propositions, belief sentences, and
fictional discourse.
Gauge theories have provided our most successful representations of
the fundamental forces of nature. How, though, do such
representations work? Interpretations of gauge theory aim to answer
this question. Through understanding how a gauge theory's
representations work, we are able to say what kind of world our
gauge theories reveal to us.
A gauge theory's representations are mathematical structures.
These may be transformed among themselves while certain features
remain the same. Do the representations related by such a gauge
transformation merely offer alternative ways of representing the
very same situation? If so, then gauge symmetry is a purely formal
property since it reflects no corresponding symmetry in
nature.
Gauging What's Real describes the representations provided by
gauge theories in both classical and quantum physics. Richard
Healey defends the thesis that gauge transformations are purely
formal symmetries of almost all the classes of representations
provided by each of our theories of fundamental forces. He argues
that evidence for classical gauge theories of forces (other than
gravity) gives us reason to believe that loops rather than points
are the locations of fundamental properties. In addition to
exploring the prospects of extending this conclusion to the quantum
gauge theories of the Standard Model of elementary particle
physics, Healey assesses the difficulties faced by attempts to base
such ontological conclusions on the success of these theories.
Critical Theory is an interdisciplinary framework of analysis that
was founded by a group of intellectuals working at the Institute
for Social Research in Frankfurt am Main, Germany. While the
Institute itself was established in 1923, the program of 'critical
theory' was not formalized until 1937 when Max Horkheimer, the
Director of the Institute at that time, dubbed it as such in his
essay, "Traditional and Critical Theory." The Institute is
frequently referred to simply as 'The Frankfurt School'. Its
significance cannot be underestimated. To this day there have been
three generations of Frankfurt School academics, but 'critical
theory' refers to something broader than just the work of the
Institute for Social Research. Critical theory now indicates a
theoretical approach that is studied all over the world. However,
the main interests and goals of the founding Institute still remain
integral. Foremost among these interests is the primary focus on
the individual human being as the locus for social change. Over the
years many debates have ensued as to how the individual can achieve
social change. While these debates took Critical Theory in diverse
directions, Soren Kierkegaard, a nineteenth century Danish
religious thinker who emphasizes the individual's self-imposed
obligation to society at large, played a major role. Nevertheless,
Kierkegaard's impact on the development of Critical Theory has
received scant study. I aim to fill this scholarly lacuna. My
intention is to expose the complexity not only of Kierkegaard but
of the Frankfurt School and their cohort. Kierkegaard's
relationship to Critical Theory suffered from the misappropriation
of his works by philosophers and theologians associated with
National Socialism. This caused the Critical Theorists to view the
content of Kierkegaard's philosophy itself as fascistic.
Ultimately, I will highlight the ways in which Kierkegaard has been
redeemed for a multiculture activist ethics today, working
vigorously in spirit with the fundamental aims of the Frankfurt
School.
The American University Publications In From its inception
Philosophy has continued the direction stated in the sub-title of
the initial volume that of probing new directions in philosophy. As
the series has developed these probings of new directions have
taken the two fold direction of exploring the relationships between
the disparate traditions of twentieth century philosophy and with
developing new insights into the foundations of some enduring
philosophic problems. This present volume continues both of these
directions. The interaction between twentieth-century Anglo-Saxon
and Continental philosophy which was an implicit theme of our first
and third volumes and the explicit subject of our second volume is
here continued in a series of studies on major figures and topics
in each tradition. In the context of these interpretative studies,
Professor Durfee returns again and again to the question of the
relationships between the will and the reason, and explores the
conflicting goals of creativity and objectivity in formulating a
philosophic position. In so doing he raises the issue as his title
suggests - of the foundations of philosophy itself. He seriously
challenges the belief common to both pheomenology and analytic
philosophy that philosophizing can be a presuppositionless
activity, objectively persued independent of the personal (and,
perhaps, arbitrary) commitments of the philosopher. This issue,
critical as it is to all forms of philosophy, is surely a worthy
one for a series such as ours."
The Philosophy of Science Fiction: Henri Bergson and the
Fabulations of Philip K. Dick explores the deep affinity between
two seemingly quite different thinkers, in their attempts to
address the need for salvation in (and from) an era of accelerated
mechanization, in which humans' capacity for destroying or
subjugating the living has attained a planetary scale. The
philosopher and the science fiction writer come together to meet
the contradictory imperatives of a realist outlook-a task which,
arguably, philosophy and science fiction could only ever adequately
undertake in collaboration. Their respective approaches meet in a
focus on the ambiguous status of fictionalizing, or fabulation, as
simultaneously one of mechanization's most devastating tools, and
the possibility of its undoing. When they are read together, the
complexities and paradoxes thrown up by this ambiguity, with which
both Bergson and Dick struggle on their own, open up new ways to
navigate ideas of mechanism and mysticism, immanence and
transcendence, and the possibility and meaning of salvation. The
result is at once an original reading of both thinkers, a new
critical theory of the socio-cultural, political and ethical
function of fictionalizing, and a case study in the strange
affinity, at times the uncanny similarity, between philosophy and
science fiction.
The coursebook presents Plato and Aristotle as the two most
significant and groundbreaking thinkers of European thought from
the era of classical Greek philosophy. The author provides
prefatory orientation in the labyrinth of their complex thought and
sketches their metaphysics, problems of knowledge and ethics. He
departs from the fact that both thinkers are similar in striving to
overcome problems of their period by localizing the human being
into a hierarchical order of beings, which obliges in questions of
the possibility of knowledge as well as of the right conduct.
This title was first published in 2001. Idealism, Metaphysics and
Community examines the place of idealism in contemporary
philosophy, and its relation to problems of metaphysics, political
thought, and the study of the history of philosophy. Following an
extensive introduction by the editor, and drawing on the work of
the Canadian idealist, Leslie Armour, the book is divided into
three main parts: Part 1 focuses on F.H.Bradley; Part 2 examines
metaphysical issues and idealism, such as the realism/anti-realism
debate, the relation of classical and idealist metaphysics,
rational psychology, time and eternity, and the divine; Part 3
draws on idealism to address contemporary concerns in ethical
theory, political philosophy, social philosophy and culture and the
history of philosophy. Presenting new insights into the work of
classical and contemporary authors, this book provides a better
understanding of classical idealism and addresses important areas
of contemporary philosophical, social and political concern.
Originally published in 1973. This final collection of thought by
founder of the New School for Social Research in New York, Horace
M. Kallen, touches on topics from language to death and from
freedom to value. The author's treatise explores his understanding
of logic and existence.
This book, based on ethnographic research in Romania, traces the
ontological red lines that form a world in which xenophobic
landscapes are possible. The last couple hundred years in Romania's
history have been marked by change of political regimes, but this
manuscript pays equal attention to an important continuity in
Romania's ontological world: its understanding of the landscape,
and the relationship between Romanian people and their land. From
political discourses to children's books, to literature, and
explanations found for everyday events, the book follows the ways
in which the landscape of Romania has been understood as a sentient
being imbued with willpower and ability to act on the world. The
sentience specific to Romania's landscape is characterized by
xenophobia-a fear and distrust of ethno-religious others-that has
been historically interpreted by Romanians as manifesting through
acts of violence enacted by the landscape towards various groups of
humans understood as dangerous to the country's unity. The novelty
of this book lies in the fact that it is an in-depth analysis of an
ontological world in which sentient landscapes are de-romanticized
and presented in their uncomfortable complexity. The concept of
sentient xenophobic mountains can add a great deal to the current
literature on the ontological turn and ontological multiplicities,
by questioning binaries like colonized/colonizer,
indigenous/colonial, sentient landscape/industrial superpower.
Romania's history makes it a good case study for this exercise, as
the country has been at the margins of empires, both desired
because of its natural resources and rejected because of the
perceived inferiority of its people, both racialized and racist,
both neoliberal and imagining absolute sovereignty.
Antonia Lolordo presents an original interpretation of John Locke's
conception of moral agency-one that has implications both for his
metaphysics and for the foundations of his political theory. Locke
denies that species boundaries exist independently of human
convention, holds that the human mind may be either an immaterial
substance or a material one to which God has superadded the power
of thought, and insists that animals possess the ability to
perceive, will, and even reason-indeed, in some cases to reason
better than humans. Thus, he eliminates any sharp distinction
between humans and the rest of the animal kingdom. However, in his
ethical and political work Locke assumes that there is a sharp
distinction between moral agents and other beings. He thus needs to
be able to delineate the set of moral agents precisely, without
relying on the sort of metaphysical and physical facts his
predecessors appealed to. Lolordo argues that for Locke, to be a
moral agent is simply to be free, rational, and a person.
Interpreting the Lockean metaphysics of moral agency in this way
helps us to understand both Locke's over-arching philosophical
project and the details of his accounts of liberty, personhood, and
rationality.
|
|