|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Metaphysics & ontology
George Berkeley notoriously claimed that his immaterialist
metaphysics was not only consistent with common sense but that it
was also integral to its defense. Roberts argues that understanding
the basic connection between Berkeley's philosophy and common sense
requires that we develop a better understanding of the four
principle components of Berkeley's positive metaphysics: The nature
of being, the divine language thesis, the active/passive
distinction, and the nature of spirits.
Roberts begins by focusing on Berkeley's view of the nature of
being. He elucidates Berkeley's view on Locke and the Cartesians
and by examining Berkeley's views about related concepts such as
unity and simplicity. From there he moves on to Berkeley's
philosophy of language arguing that scrutiny of the famous
"Introduction" to the Principles of Human Knowledge reveals that
Berkeley identified the ideational theory of meaning and
understanding as the root cause of some of the worst of man's
intellectual errors, not "abstract ideas." Abstract ideas are,
rather, the most debilitating symptom of this underlying ailment.
In place of the ideational theory, Berkeley defends a rudimentary
"use theory" of meaning. This understanding of Berkeley's approach
to semantics is then applied to the divine language thesis and is
shown to have important consequences for Berkeley's pragmatic
approach to the ontology of natural objects and for his approach to
our knowledge of, and relation to other minds, including God's.
Turning next to Berkeley's much aligned account of spirits, the
author defends the coherence of Berkeley's view of spirits by way
of providing an interpretation of the active/passive distinction as
marking anormative distinction and by focusing on the role that
divine language plays in letting Berkeley identify the soul with
the will. With these four principles of Berkeley's philosophy in
hand, he then returns to the topic of common sense and offers a
defense of Berkeley's philosophy as built upon and expressive of
the deepest metaphysical commitments of mainstream Christianity.
Roberts' reappraisal of this important figure should appeal to all
historians of philosophy as well as scholars in metaphysics and
philosophy of language.
Questions concerning free will are intertwined with issues in
almost every area of philosophy, from metaphysics to philosophy of
mind to moral philosophy, and are also informed by work in
different areas of science (principally physics, neuroscience and
social psychology). Free will is also a perennial concern of
serious thinkers in theology and in non-western traditions. Because
free will can be approached from so many different perspectives and
has implications for so many debates, a comprehensive survey needs
to encompass an enormous range of approaches. This book is the
first to draw together leading experts on every aspect of free
will, from those who are central to the current philosophical
debates, to non-western perspectives, to scientific contributions
and to those who know the rich history of the subject. Chapter 37
of this book is freely available as a downloadable Open Access PDF
under a Creative Commons Attribution-Non Commercial-No Derivatives
3.0 license.
https://s3-us-west-2.amazonaws.com/tandfbis/rt-files/docs/Open+Access+Chapters/9781138795815_oachapter37.pdf
Our experience of objects (and consequently our theorizing about
them) is very rich. We perceive objects as possessing individuation
conditions. They appear to have boundaries in space and time, for
example, and they appear to move independently of a background of
other objects or a landscape. In Ontology Without Boundaries Jody
Azzouni undertakes an analysis of our concept of object, and shows
what about that notion is truly due to the world and what about it
is a projection onto the world of our senses and thinking. Location
and individuation conditions are our product: there is no echo of
them in the world. Features, the ways that objects seem to be,
aren't projections. Azzouni shows how the resulting austere
metaphysics tames a host of ancient philosophical problems about
constitution ("Ship of Theseus," "Sorities"), as well as
contemporary puzzles about reductionism. In addition, it's shown
that the same sorts of individuation conditions for properties,
which philosophers use to distinguish between various kinds of odd
abstracta-universals, tropes, and so on, are also projections.
Accompanying our notion of an object is a background logic that
makes cogent ontological debate about anything from Platonic
objects to Bigfoot. Contemporary views about this background logic
("quantifier variance") make ontological debate incoherent. Azzouni
shows how a neutral interpretation of quantifiers and quantifier
domains makes sense of both philosophical and pre-philosophical
ontological debates. Azzouni also shows how the same apparatus
makes sense of our speaking about a host of items-Mickey Mouse,
unicorns, Martians-that nearly all of us deny exist. It's allowed
by what Azzouni shows about the background logic of our ontological
debates, as well as the semantics of the language of those debates
that we can disagree over the existence of things, like unicorns,
without that background logic and semantics forcing ontological
commitments onto speakers that they don't have.
This collection addresses metaphysical issues at the intersection
between philosophy and science. A unique feature is the way in
which it is guided both by history of philosophy, by interaction
between philosophy and science, and by methodological awareness. In
asking how metaphysics is possible in an age of science, the
contributors draw on philosophical tools provided by three great
thinkers who were fully conversant with and actively engaged with
the sciences of their day: Kant, Husserl, and Frege. Part I sets
out frameworks for scientifically informed metaphysics in
accordance with the meta-metaphysics outlined by these three
self-reflective philosophers. Part II explores the domain for
co-existent metaphysics and science. Constraints on ambitious
critical metaphysics are laid down in close consideration of logic,
meta-theory, and specific conditions for science. Part III
exemplifies the role of language and science in contemporary
metaphysics. Quine's pursuit of truth is analysed; Cantor's
absolute infinitude is reconstrued in modal terms; and sense is
made of Weyl's take on the relationship between mathematics and
empirical aspects of physics. With chapters by leading scholars,
Metametaphysics and the Sciences is an in-depth resource for
researchers and advanced students working within metaphysics,
philosophy of science, and the history of philosophy.
The present volume posits the themes of freedom, action, and
motivation as the central principles that drive Spinoza's Ethics
from its first part to its last. It assembles essays by
internationally leading scholars who provide different, sometimes
opposing interpretations of these fundamental themes as they
operate across the five parts of the Ethics and within its manifold
domains. The diversity of issues, approaches, and perspectives
within this volume, along with the chapters' common focus, open up
new ways of understanding not only some of the key concepts and
main objectives in the Ethics but also the threads unifying the
entire work. The sequence of essays in the book broadly follows the
order of the Ethics, providing up-to-date perspectives of Spinoza's
views on freedom, action, and motivation in their ontological,
cognitive, physical, affective, and ethical facets. This enables
readers to engage with a variety of new interpretations of these
key themes of the Ethics and to reconsider their consequences both
for other related issues in the Ethics and for the relevance of the
Ethics to contemporary trends in philosophy of action and
motivation. The essays will contribute to the growing interest in
Spinoza's Ethics and spark further discussion and debate within and
outside the vast body of scholarship on this important work.
Freedom, Action, and Motivation in Spinoza's Ethics will be of
interest to scholars and advanced students working on Spinoza and
early modern philosophy, as well as on philosophy of action and
motivation.
First published in 1973, this is the first book on Paul Tillich in
which a sustained attempt is made to sort out and evaluate the
questions to which Tillich addresses himself in the crucial
philosophical parts of his theological system. It is argued that
despite the apparent simplicity in his interest in the 'question of
being', Tillich in fact conceives of the ontological enterprise in
a number of radically different ways in different contexts. Much of
the author's work is devoted to the careful separation of these
strands in his philosophical thought and to an exploration and
assessment of the assumptions associated with them. This book will
be of interest to readers of Tillich and philosophers who
specialise in ontology and linguistics.
The issue of the other has always been an urgent one, especially
since 1980's, when the political debates over race, gender, class,
culture, ethnicity, and post-colonialism took the central stage.
The Riddling between Oedipus and the Sphinx, Ontology, Hauntology,
and Heterologies of the Grotesque probes the polemic status of the
other and the dubious nature of the subject from a heterodox
perspective of an emblematic grotesque figure, the Sphinx-the
mystical trickster and the guardian of sacred knowledge in Egyptian
culture. In Greek mythology, Oedipus, the epitome of Western logos,
solved the Sphinx's riddle with a single word, "Man." This
evocation for the phantom of a solipsistic subject discloses, in
effect, Oedipus' latent grotesque disparity. The book explores the
encounter of this unlikely pair to inquire the riddling
relationship between the singular subject and the grotesque other
in the context of modern discourses of the subject and postmodern
theories of the other.
This volume critically engages with the work of the acclaimed
Australian sociologist John Carroll. It makes the argument for a
metaphysical sociology, which Carroll has proposed should focus on
the questions of fundamental existence that confront all humans:
'Where do I come from?', 'What should I do with my life?' and 'What
happens to me when I die?'. These questions of meaning, in the
secular modern West, have become difficult to answer. As
contemporary individuals increasingly draw on their inner
resources, or 'ontological qualities', to pursue quests for
meaning, the key challenge for a metaphysical sociology concerns
the cultural resources available to people and the manner in which
they are cultivated. Through wide-ranging discussions which
include, film, romantic love, terrorism and video games,
Metaphysical Sociology takes up this challenge. The contributors
include emerging and established sociologists, a philosopher, a
renowned actor and a musician. As such, this collection will appeal
to scholars of social theory and sociology, and to the general
reader with interests in morality, art, culture and the fundamental
questions of human existence.
This volume presents a commentary on Aristotle's Metaphysics Book
12 by pseudo-Alexander in a new translation accompanied by
explanatory notes, introduction and indexes. Fred D. Miller, Jr.
argues that the author of the commentary is in fact not Alexander
of Aphrodisias, Aristotle's distant successor in early 3rd century
CE Athens and his leading defender and interpreter, but Michael of
Ephesus from Constantinople as late as the 12th century CE. Robert
Browning had earlier made the case that Michael was enlisted by
Princess Anna Comnena in a project to restore and complete the
ancient Greek commentaries on Aristotle, including those of
Alexander; he did so by incorporating available ancient
commentaries into commentaries of his own. Metaphysics Book 12
posits a god as the supreme cause of motion in the cosmic system
Aristotle had elaborated elsewhere as having the earth at the
centre. The fixed stars are whirled around it on an outer sphere,
the sun, moon and recognised planets on interior spheres, but with
counteracting spheres to make the motions of each independent of
the motions of others and of the fixed stars, thus yielding a total
of 55 spheres. Motion is transmitted from a divine unmoved mover
through divine moved movers which move the celestial spheres, and
on to the perishable realms. Chapters 1 to 5 describe the
principles and causes of the perishable substances nearer the
centre of the universe, while Chapters 6 to 10 seek to prove the
existence and attributes of the celestial substances beyond.
Kathrin Koslicki offers an analysis of ordinary material objects,
those material objects to which we take ourselves to be committed
in ordinary, scientifically informed discourse. She focuses
particularly on the question of how the parts of such objects are
related to the wholes which they compose.
Many philosophers today find themselves in the grip of an
exceedingly deflationary conception of what it means to be an
object. According to this conception, any plurality of objects, no
matter how disparate or gerrymandered, itself composes an object,
even if the objects in question fail to exhibit interesting
similarities, internal unity, cohesion, or causal interaction
amongst each other.
This commitment to initially counterintuitive objects follows from
the belief that no principled set of criteria is available by means
of which to distinguish intuitively gerrymandered objects from
commonsensical ones; the project of this book is to persuade the
reader that systematic principles can be found by means of which
composition can be restricted, and hence that we need not embrace
this deflationary approach to the question of what it means to be
an object.
To this end, a more full-blooded neo-Aristotelian account of
parthood and composition is developed according to which objects
are structured wholes: it is integral to the existence and identity
of an object, on this conception, that its parts exhibit a certain
manner of arrangement. This structure-based conception of parthood
and composition is explored in detail, along with some of its
historical precursors as well as some of its contemporary
competitors.
Brian Loar (1939-2014) was an eminent and highly respected
philosopher of mind and language. He was at the forefront of
several different field-defining debates between the 1970s and the
2000s-from his earliest work on reducing semantics to psychology,
through debates about reference, functionalism, externalism, and
the nature of intentionality, to his most enduringly influential
work on the explanatory gap between consciousness and neurons. Loar
is widely credited with having developed the most comprehensive
functionalist account of certain aspects of the mind, and his
'phenomenal content strategy' is arguably one of the most
significant developments on the ancient mind/body problem. This
volume of essays honours the entirety of Loar's wide-ranging
philosophical career. It features sixteen original essays from
influential figures in the fields of philosophy of language and
philosophy of mind, including those who worked with and were taught
by Loar. The essays are divided into three thematic sections
covering Loar's work in philosophy of language, especially the
relations between semantics and psychology (1970s-80s), on content
in the philosophy of mind (1980s-90s), and on the metaphysics of
intentionality and consciousness (1990s and beyond). Taken
together, this book is a fitting tribute to one of the leading
minds of the latter-20th century, and a timely reflection on Loar's
enduring influence on the philosophy of mind and language.
According to two-dimensional semantics, the meaning of an
expression involves two different "dimensions": one dimension
involves reference and truth-conditions of a familiar sort, while
the other dimension involves the way that reference and
truth-conditions depend on the external world (for example,
reference and truth-conditions might be held to depend on which
individuals and substances are present in the world, or on which
linguistic conventions are in place). A number of different
two-dimensional frameworks have been developed, and these have been
applied to a number of fundamental problems in philosophy: the
nature of communication, the relation between the necessary and the
a priori, the role of context in assertion, Frege's distinction
between sense and reference, the contents of thought, and the
mind-body problem. Manuel Garcia-Carpintero and Josep Macia present
a selection of new essays by an outstanding international team,
shedding fresh light both on foundational issues regarding _
two-dimensional semantics and on its specific applications. The
volume will be the starting-point for future work on this approach
to issues in philosophy of language, _ epistemology, and
metaphysics. _
Suffering is a central component of our lives. We suffer pain. We
fall ill. We fail and are failed. Our loved ones die. It is a
commonplace to think that suffering is, always and everywhere, bad.
But might suffering also be good? If so, in what ways might
suffering have positive, as well as negative, value? This important
volume examines these questions and is the first comprehensive
examination of suffering from a philosophical perspective. An
outstanding roster of international contributors explore the nature
of suffering, pain, and valence, as well as the value of suffering
and the relationships between suffering, morality, and rationality.
Philosophy of Suffering: Metaphysics, Value, and Normativity is
essential reading for students and researchers in philosophy of
mind, philosophy of psychology, cognitive and behavioral psychology
as well as those in health and medicine researching conceptual
issues regarding suffering and pain.
This volume draws on the significance of the work of Marilyn
Strathern in respect of its potential to queer anthropological
analysis and to foster the reimagining of the object of
anthropology. The authors examine the ways in which Strathern's
varied analytics facilitate the construction of alternative forms
of anthropological thinking, and greater understanding of how
knowledge practices of queer objects, subjects and relations
operate and take effect. Queering Knowledge offers an innovative
collection of writing, bringing about queer and anthropological
syntheses through Strathern's oeuvre. It will be relevant to
scholars from anthropology as well as a number of other
disciplines, including gender, sexuality and queer studies. *Winner
of the 2020 Ruth Benedict Prize for Outstanding Edited Volume*
Arguments that ordinary inanimate objects such as tables and
chairs, sticks and stones, simply do not exist have become
increasingly common and increasingly prominent. Some are based on
demands for parsimony or for a non-arbitrary answer to the special
composition question; others arise from prohibitions against causal
redundancy, ontological vagueness, or co-location; and others still
come from worries that a common sense ontology would be a rival to
a scientific one. Until now, little has been done to address these
arguments in a unified and systematic way. Ordinary Objects is
designed to fill this gap, demonstrating that the mistakes behind
all of these superficially diverse eliminativist arguments may be
traced to a common source. It aims to develop an ontology of
ordinary objects subject to no such problems, providing perhaps the
first sustained defense of a common sense ontology in two
generations. The work done along the way addresses a number of
major issues in philosophy of language and metaphysics,
contributing to debates about analyticity, identity conditions,
co-location and the grounding problem, vagueness,
overdetermination, parsimony, and ontological commitment. In the
end, the most important result of addressing these eliminativist
arguments is not merely avoiding their conclusions; examining their
failings also gives us reason to suspect that many apparent
disputes in ontology are pseudo-debates. For it brings into
question widely-held assumptions about which uses of metaphysical
principles are appropriate, which metaphysical demands are
answerable, and how we should go about addressing such fundamental
questions as "What exists?". As a result, the work of Ordinary
Objects promises to provide not only the route to a reflective
understanding of our unreflective common-sense view, but also a
better understanding of the proper methods and limits of
metaphysics. "Ordinary Objects is well worth reading because it
sheds new light on how to preserve the credibility of familiar
things."-Marianne Djuth, The Review of Metaphysics "In Ordinary
Objects , Amie Thomasson mounts a spirited and vigorous defense of
the reality of ordinary objects."-Terry Horgan, Times Literary
Supplement "Ordinary Objects is a fine book.... [Thomasson] writes
insightfully and persuasively, and she has a realistic view of what
metaphysical arguments can and cannot demonstrate... she approaches
metaphysical theorizing more systematically than many other recent
writers, drawing attention to the ways in which questionable
assumptions in one area of philosophy are undergirding seemingly
powerful arguments in another. Everyone working in metaphysics
should make time for this volume."-R. W. Fischer, Metaphilosophy
"In Ordinary Objects , Thomasson pursues an integrated conception
of ontology and metaontology. In ontology, she defends the
existence of shoes, ships, and other ordinary objects. In
metaontology, she defends a deflationary view of ontological
inquiry, designed to suck the air out of arguments against ordinary
objects. The result is an elegant and insightful defense of a
common sense worldview."-Jonathan Schaffer, Philosophical Books
"Amie Thomasson has written a lovely book which is certain to
irritate many professional metaphysicians. But it is not just
irritating: it is challenging...This book would be good
supplementary text for upper-level metaphysics classes or seminars
in which the sorts of arguments to which Thomasson replies are also
read."-Alan Sidelle, The Philosophical Quarterly
The book is intended as a reader-friendly introduction to issues in
the philosophy of mind, including mental-physical causal
interaction, computational models of thought, the relation minds
bear to brains, and assorted -isms: behaviorism, dualism,
eliminativism, emergentism, functionalism, materialism, neutral
monism, and panpsychism. The Fourth Edition reintroduces a chapter
on Donald Davidson and a discussion of 'Non-Cartesian Dualism',
along with a wholly new chapter on emergence and panpsychism. A
concluding chapter draws together material in earlier chapters and
offers what the author regards as a plausible account of the mind's
place in nature. Suggested readings at the conclusion of each
chapter have been updated, with a focus on accessible,
non-technical material. Key Features of the Fourth Edition Includes
a new chapter, 'Emergence and Panpsychism' (Chapter 13), reflecting
growing interest in these areas Reintroduces and updates a chapter
on Donald Davidson, 'Radical Interpretation' (Chapter 8), which was
excised from the previous edition Updates 'Descartes' Legacy'
(Chapter 3) to include a discussion of E. J. Lowe's arresting
'Non-Cartesian Dualism', also removed from the previous edition
Includes a highly revised final chapter, which draws together much
of the previous material and sketches a plausible account of the
mind's place in nature Updated 'Suggested Reading' lists at the end
of each chapter
A Philosophy of Sacred Nature introduces Robert Corrington's
philosophical thought, "ecstatic naturalism," which seeks to
recognize nature's self-transforming potential. Ecstatic naturalism
is a philosophical-theological perspective, deeply seated in a
semiotic cosmology and psychosemiosis, and it radically and
profoundly probes into the mystery of nature's perennial
self-fissuring of nature natured and nature naturing. Edited by
Leon Niemoczynski and Nam T. Nguyen, this collection aims to allow
readers to see what can be done with ecstatic naturalism, and what
directions, interpretations, and creative uses that doing can take.
A thorough exploration of the prospects of ecstatic naturalism,
this book will appeal to scholars of Continental philosophy,
religious naturalism, and American pragmatism.
In his book, philosopher and law professor Ken Levy explains why he
agrees with most people, but not with most other philosophers,
about free will and responsibility. Most people believe that we
have both - that is, that our choices, decisions, and actions are
neither determined nor undetermined but rather fully
self-determined. By contrast, most philosophers understand just how
difficult it is to defend this "metaphysical libertarian" position.
So they tend to opt for two other theories: "responsibility
skepticism" (which denies the very possibility of free will and
responsibility) and "compatibilism" (which reduces free will and
responsibility to properties that are compatible with determinism).
In opposition to both of these theories, Levy explains how free
will and responsibility are indeed metaphysically possible. But he
also cautions against the dogma that metaphysical libertarianism is
actually true, a widespread belief that continues to cause serious
social, political, and legal harms. Levy's book presents a crisp,
tight, historically informed discussion, with fresh clarity,
insight, and originality. It will become one of the definitive
resources for students, academics, and general readers in this
critical intersection among metaphysics, ethics, and criminal law.
Key features: Presents a unique, qualified defense of "metaphysical
libertarianism," the idea that our choices, decisions, and actions
can be fully self-determined. Written clearly, accessibly, and with
minimal jargon - rare for a book on the very difficult issues of
free will and responsibility. Seamlessly connects philosophical,
legal, psychological, and political issues. Will be provocative and
insightful for professional philosophers, students, and
non-philosophers.
In this book, an international team of scholars from leading
American, British and Continental European universities, led by
Richard Swinburne, Eleonore Stump, William Wainwright and Linda
Zagzebski, presents original ideas about three currently discussed
topics in the philosophy of religion: religious epistemology, the
philosophy of God's action in the world, including the problem of
evil and Divine Providence, and the philosophical challenge of
religious diversity. The book contains echoes of all four main
strands of the late 20th century philosophy of religion: Richard
Swinburne's philosophical theology, Alvin Plantinga's reformed
epistemology, John Hick's theory of religious pluralism, and the
philosophy of religion inspired by the work of the later
Wittgenstein. One of the distinguishing features of this volume is
that it mirrors a new trend towards philosophical cooperation
across the so-called continental/analytic divide.
How does the ontological turn in anthropology redefine what modern,
Western ontology is in practice, and offer the beginnings of a new
ontological pluralism? On a planet that is increasingly becoming a
single, metaphysically homogeneous world, anthropology remains one
of the few disciplines that recognizes that being has been thought
with very different concepts and can still be rendered in terms
quite different than those placed on it today. Yet despite its
critical acuity, even the most philosophically oriented
anthropology often remains segregated from philosophical
discussions aimed at rethinking such terms. What would come of an
anthropology more fully committed to being a source of (post-)
philosophical concepts? What would happen to philosophy if it began
to think with and through these concepts? How, finally, does
comparison condition these two projects ? This book addresses these
questions from a variety of perspectives, all of which nonetheless
hold in common the view that "philosophy" has been displaced and
altered by the modes of thought of other collectives. An
international group of authors, including Eduardo Viveiros de
Castro, Marilyn Strathern, Philippe Descola, and Bruno Latour,
explore how the new anthropology/philosophy conjuncture opens new
horizons of critique.
Metaphysical Themes in Thomas Aquinas III is Msgr. John Wippel's
third volume dedicated to the metaphysical thought of Thomas
Aquinas. After an introduction, this volume of collected essays
begins with Wippel's interpretation of the discovery of the subject
of metaphysics by a special kind of judgment ("separation"). In
subsequent chapters, Wippel turns to the relationship between faith
and reason, exploring what are known as the preambles of faith.
This is followed by two chapters on the important contributions by
Cornelio Fabro on Aquinas's distinction between essence and esse
and on participation. The volume continues with articles on
Aquinas's view of creation as a preamble of faith, Aquinas's
much-disputed defense of unicity of substantial form in creatures,
his account of the separated soul's natural knowledge, and
Aquinas's understanding of evil in his De Malo 1. The volume
concludes with an article comparing Bonaventure, Aquinas, and
Godfrey of Fontaines on the metaphysical composition of angelic
beings. Most of these issues were disputed during Aquinas's time by
some of his contemporaries, and the proper understanding of each
continues to be debated by various students of his thought today.
Wippel's purpose, therefore, is to help clarify our understanding
of Aquinas's thought on each of these topics, a task that requires
the careful analysis of primary sources and of secondary literature
and attention to the relative chronology of his writing.
|
|