|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Metaphysics & ontology
The prolific Margaret Cavendish (1623-1673) published books on
natural philosophy as well as stories, plays, poems, orations,
allegories, and letters. Her mature philosophical system offered a
unique panpsychist theory of Nature as composed of a continuous,
non-atomistic, perceiving, knowing matter. In contrast to the
dominant philosophical thinking of her day, Cavendish argued that
all matter has free will and can choose whether or not to follow
Nature's rules. The Well-Ordered Universe explores the development
of Cavendish's natural philosophy from the atomism of her 1653
poems to the panpsychist materialism of her 1668 Grounds of Natural
Philosophy. Deborah Boyle argues that her natural philosophy, her
medical theories, and her social and political philosophy are all
informed by an underlying concern with order, regularity, and
rule-following. This focus on order reveals interesting connections
among apparently disparate elements of Cavendish's philosophical
program, including her views on gender, on animals and the
environment, and on sickness and health. Focusing on the role of
order in Cavendish's philosophy also helps reveal key differences
between her natural philosophy and her more conservative social and
political philosophy. Cavendish believed that humans' special
desire for public recognition often leads to an unruly ambition,
causing humans to disrupt society in ways not seen in the rest of
Nature. Thus, The Well-Ordered Universe defends Cavendish as a
royalist who endorsed absolute monarchy and a rigid social
hierarchy for maintaining order in human society.
This book has two aims; first, to provide a new account of time's
arrow in light of relativity theory; second, to explain how God,
being eternal, relates to our world, marked as it is by change and
time.In part one, Saudek argues that time is not the expansive
universal 'wave' that is appears to be, but nor are we living in an
unchanging block. Rather, time is real but local: there are
infinitely many arrows of time in the universe, each with their own
fixed past and open future. This model is based on the ontology of
substances which can exist in different states, marked by different
properties. On this basis, a derivation of temporal precedence and
of the asymmetry between the fixed past and the open future is
provided. Time's arrow is thus 'attached' to substances, and is
therefore a local rather than global phenomenon, though by no means
an illusory or merely subjective one. In part two, this model is
then applied to the perennial questions concerning the relationship
between divine eternity and the temporal world: How can my future
choices be free if God already knows what I will do? Can God act if
He is not in time? Through the lens of relativity theory, such
questions are shown to appear in a completely new light. The book
combines insights from theoretical physics with ancient and
contemporary philosophy into a unique synthesis, broaching a wealth
of key issues including the arrow of time, the evolution of the
cosmos, and a physics-based defence of eternalism in philosophical
theology.
The contemporary literature on self-deception was born out of
Jean-Paul Sartre's work on bad faith-lying to oneself. As time has
progressed, the conception of self-deception has moved further and
further away from Sartre's conception of bad faith. In
Self-Deception's Puzzles and Processes: A Return to a Sartrean
View, Jason Kido Lopez argues that this departure is a mistake and
that we should return to thinking about self-deception in a
Sartrean fashion, in which we are self-deceived when we
intentionally use the strategies and methods of interpersonal
deception on ourselves. Since literally tricking ourselves cannot
work-we will always see through our own self-deception, after
all-self-deception merely consists of the attempt to trick
ourselves in this way. Other scholars have rejected this notion of
self-deception historically, dismissing it as paradoxical. Lopez
argues first that it isn't paradoxical, and he further suggests
that moving away from this notion of self-deception has caused the
contemporary literature on the topic to be littered with disparate
and conflicting theories. Indeed, there are a great many ways to
avoid the allegedly paradoxical Sartrean notion of self-deception,
and the resulting plethora of accounts lead to a fragmented picture
of self-deception. If, however, the Sartrean view isn't
paradoxical, then there was no need for the host of contradictory
theories and most researchers on self-deception have missed what
was originally so intriguing about self-deception: that it, like
bad faith, is the process of literally trying to trick oneself into
believing what is false or unwarranted. Self-Deception's Puzzles
and Processes will be of great interest to students and scholars of
epistemology, philosophy of mind, psychology, and continental
philosophy, and to anyone else interested in the problems of
self-deception.
First handbook on liberal naturalism Superb line up of
international contributors, many of whom are leading names in the
field Covers hot topics such as history of philosophical
naturalism, key figures from Aristotle to Quine and contemporary
issues such as ethical, metaphysical and epistemological naturalism
Rather than see love as a natural form of affection, Love As Human
Freedom sees love as a practice that changes over time through
which new social realities are brought into being. Love brings
about, and helps us to explain, immense social-historical
shifts-from the rise of feminism and the emergence of bourgeois
family life, to the struggles for abortion rights and birth control
and the erosion of a gender-based division of labor. Drawing on
Hegel, Paul A. Kottman argues that love generates and explains
expanded possibilities for freely lived lives. Through keen
interpretations of the best known philosophical and literary
depictions of its topic-including Shakespeare, Plato, Nietzsche,
Ovid, Flaubert, and Tolstoy-his book treats love as a fundamental
way that we humans make sense of temporal change, especially the
inevitability of death and the propagation of life.
This lucid and original book offers a detailed and critical
exposition of German metaphysics and philosophy of logic during the
past century. Julian Roberts sets his argument in the context of
the current debate between "analytical" and "continental"
philosophers. the book centers on the problem of
reflection-exploration of the boundaries of rationality, or (in
analytical terms) of the "limits of thought"-which Roberts claims
lies at the heart of both traditions. Roberts concentrates on the
work of Frege, Wittengenstein, Husserl, the Erlangen School, and
Habermas. In the course of his examination, however, he also
considers philosophers ranging from Russell and Quine to Putnam and
Heidegger. Roberts argues that the technical advances of modern
logic have not, as is sometimes believed by analytical thinkers,
generated uniquely modern problems that can only be dealt with by a
correspondingly modernist philosophy, for the problem of reflection
was already at the heart of Kant's critical project and of his
confrontation with Leibniz. If we recover this earlier debate, says
Roberts, we can develop a more adequate understanding not merely of
its echoes in the twentieth century, but of the role and
contribution of metaphysics and of philosophy in general.
The first collection to address the vexing issue of Nabokov's moral
stances, this book argues that he designed his novels and stories
as open-ended ethical problems for readers to confront. In a dozen
new essays, international Nabokov scholars tackle those problems
directly while addressing such questions as whether Nabokov was a
bad reader, how he defined evil, if he believed in God, and how he
constructed fictional works that led readers to become aware of
their own moral positions. In order to elucidate his engagement
with aesthetics, metaphysics, and ethics, Nabokov and the Question
of Morality explores specific concepts in the volume's four
sections: "Responsible Reading," "Good and Evil," "Agency and
Altruism," and "The Ethics of Representation." By bringing together
fresh insights from leading Nabokovians and emerging scholars, this
book establishes new interdisciplinary contexts for Nabokov studies
and generates lively readings of works from his entire career.
For years now much attention has been given to the phenomenon of
the artificial. Speculation regarding "what is real?" abounds in
the sciences, literature, as well as films and other visual arts.
This work presents the first critical, sustained, philosophical
study on this topic. Nature and the Artificial: Aristotelian
Reflections on the Operative Imperative reveals the inner logic of
the artificial by reflecting it off the metaphysical relationship
between nature and techne as conceived by Aristotle and Thomas
Aquinas. During early modernity, figures such as Descartes and
Bacon transformed this understanding, giving rise to the notion of
the "operative imperative." Nature and techne, for the Aristotelian
tradition and for us, can only be understood in terms of their
dialectical relationship to one another. Aristotle articulates this
relationship with the phrase "techne imitates nature." With the
operative imperative, however, a certain reversal takes place,
whereby techne becomes the paradigm for nature. As Ed Engelmann
demonstrates, the operative imperative, together with the
phenomenon of the artificial it implies, stands to Aristotelian
metaphysics of nature as image is to original. Anyone who believes
that the rise of the artificial in our civilization needs the
intensive study it deserves-as well as those who are seeking
innovative insights into Aristotelian tradition-will want to read
this book.
Focusing on the works of Thomas Reid, Dugald Stewart, Sir William
Hamilton, Thomas Brown and James Frederick Ferrier, this book
offers a definitive account of an important philosophical movement,
and represents a ground-breaking contribution to scholarship in the
area. Essential reading for philosophers or anyone with an interest
in the history of philosophical thought.
What does it signify when a Shakespearean character forgets
something or when Hamlet determines to 'wipe away all trivial fond
records'? How might forgetting be an act to be performed, or be
linked to forgiveness, such as when in The Winter's Tale Cleomenes
encourages Leontes to 'forget your evil. / With them, forgive
yourself'? And what do we as readers and audiences forget of
Shakespeare's works and of the performances we watch? This is the
first book devoted to a broad consideration of how Shakespeare
explores the concept of forgetting and how forgetting functions in
performance. A wide-ranging study of how Shakespeare dramatizes
forgetting, it offers close readings of Shakespeare's plays,
considering what Shakespeare forgot and what we forget about
Shakespeare. The book touches on an equally broad range of
forgetting theory from antiquity through to the present day, of
forgetting in recent novels and films, and of creative ways of
making sense of how our world constructs the cultural meaning of
and anxiety about forgetting. Drawing on dozens of productions
across the history of Shakespeare on stage and film, the book
explores Shakespeare's dramaturgy, from characters who forget what
they were about to say, to characters who leave the stage never to
return, from real forgetting to performed forgetting, from the mad
to the powerful, from playgoers to Shakespeare himself.
Hellenistic philosophy concerns the thought of the Epicureans,
Stoics, and Skeptics, the most influential philosophical groups in
the era between the death of Alexander the Great (323 BCE) and the
defeat of the last Greek stronghold in the ancient world (31 BCE).
The Routledge Handbook of Hellenistic Philosophy provides
accessible yet rigorous introductions to the theories of knowledge,
ethics, and physics belonging to each of the three schools,
explores the fascinating ways in which interschool rivalries shaped
the philosophies of the era, and offers unique insight into the
relevance of Hellenistic views to issues today, such as
environmental ethics, consumerism, and bioethics. Eleven countries
are represented among the Handbook's 35 authors, whose chapters
were written specifically for this volume and are organized
thematically into six sections: The people, history, and methods of
Epicureanism, Stoicism, and Skepticism. Earlier philosophical
influences on Hellenistic thought, such as Aristotle, Socrates, and
Presocratics. The soul, perception, and knowledge. God, fate, and
the primary principles of nature and the universe. Ethics,
political theory, society, and community. Hellenistic philosophy's
relevance to contemporary life. Spanning from the ancient past to
the present, this Handbook aims to show that Hellenistic philosophy
has much to offer all thinking people of the twenty-first century.
In this fascinating and timely book, Maren Behrensen facilitates a
conversation between philosophy and the 'practitioners' of
identity. What makes a person the same person over time? This
question has been studied throughout the history of philosophy. Yet
philosophers have never fully engaged with the 'practitioners' of
identity, namely technology developers, lawyers, politicians,
sociologists and applied ethicists. The book offers an answer to
the metaphysical question of personal identity and tries to show
how this question is of immediate relevance to the various
practices of identity management - particularly in the fields of
administration, counter-terrorism activities, and gender
reassignment. Behrensen argues that identity documents and other
markers of identity (such as biometric samples) are not merely
representations of, but actually help constitute, personal
identity. The metaphysical fact of personal identity lies in these
supposedly 'external' features. The book goes on to focus on issues
relating to 'trust' and 'security', terms central to the ethics of
new technologies and in work on new identity management
technologies.
This handbook is a thorough and state of the art overview of a
central and fast-growing topic in philosophy including up-to-date
topics throughout making it the ideal reference source for both
students and scholars. This is the only handbook to pull together a
thoroughly comprehensive overview of the topic of philosophy of
agency. This handbook will help the field of study organise itself:
it will be a rallying point for any student and researcher
interested in the subject. All chapters are specially commissioned,
written by an international team of renowned contributors and not
previously published.
We humans are collectively driven by a powerful - yet not fully
explained - instinct to understand. We would like to see everything
established, proven, laid bare. The more important an issue, the
more we desire to see it clarified, stripped of all secrets, all
shades of gray. What could be more important than to understand the
Universe and ourselves as a part of it? To find a window onto our
origin and our destiny? This book examines how far our modern
cosmological theories - with their sometimes audacious models, such
as inflation, cyclic histories, quantum creation, parallel
universes - can take us towards answering these questions. Can such
theories lead us to ultimate truths, leaving nothing unexplained?
Last, but not least, Heller addresses the thorny problem of why and
whether we should expect to find theories with all-encompassing
explicative power.
Bernard Bolzano (1781-1850) is increasingly recognized as one of
the greatest nineteenth-century philosophers. A philosopher and
mathematician of rare talent, he made ground-breaking contributions
to logic, the foundations and philosophy of mathematics,
metaphysics, and the philosophy of religion. Many of the larger
features of later analytic philosophy (but also many of the
details) first appear in his work: for example, the separation of
logic from psychology, his sophisticated understanding of
mathematical proof, his definition of logical consequence, his work
on the semantics of natural kind terms, or his anticipations of
Cantor's set theory, to name but a few. To his contemporaries,
however, he was best known as an intelligent and determined
advocate for reform of Church and State. Based in large part on a
carefully argued utilitarian practical philosophy, he developed a
program for the non-violent reform of the authoritarian
institutions of the Hapsburg Empire, a program which he himself
helped to set in motion through his teaching and other activities.
Rarely has a philosopher had such a great impact on the political
culture of his homeland. Persecuted in his lifetime by secular and
ecclesiastical authorities, long ignored or misunderstood by
philosophers, Bolzano's reputation has nevertheless steadily
increased over the past century and a half. Much discussed and
respected in Central Europe for over a century, he is finally
beginning to receive the recognition he deserves in the
English-speaking world. This book provides a comprehensive and
detailed critical introduction to Bolzano, covering both his life
and works.
Part I of this book presents a theory of modal metaphysics in the
possible-worlds tradition. `Worlds' themselves are understood as
structured sets of properties; this `Ersatzist' view is defended
against its most vigorous competitors, Meinongianism and David
Lewis' theory of existent concrete worlds. Related issues of
essentialism and linguistic reference are explored. Part II takes
up the question of lexical meaning in the context of possible-world
semantics. There are skeptical analyses of analyticity and the
notion of a logical constant; and an `infinite polysemy' thesis is
defended. The book will be of particular interest to
metaphysicians, possible-world semanticists, philosophers of
language, and linguists concerned with lexical semantics.
This book discusses various aspects of God's causal activity.
Traditional theology has long held that God acts in the world and
interrupts the normal course of events by performing special acts.
Although the tradition is unified in affirming that God does
create, conserve, and act, there is much disagreement about the
details of divine activity. The chapters in this book fruitfully
explore these disagreements about divine causation. The chapters
are divided into two sections. The first explores historical views
of divine causal activity from the Pre-Socratics to Hume. The
second section addresses a variety of contemporary issues related
to God's causal activity. These chapters include defenses of the
possibility of special acts of God, proposals of models of divine
causation, and analyses of divine conservation. Philosophical
Essays on Divine Causation will be of interest to researchers and
graduate students working in philosophy of religion, philosophical
theology, and metaphysics.
This book offers new ways of thinking about and assessing the
impact of virtual reality on its users. It argues that we must go
beyond traditional psychological concepts of VR "presence" to
better understand the many varieties of virtual experiences. The
author provides compelling evidence that VR simulations are capable
of producing "virtually real" experiences in people. He also
provides a framework for understanding when and how simulations
induce virtually real experiences. From these insights, the book
shows that virtually real experiences are responsible for several
unaddressed ethical issues in VR research and design. Experimental
philosophers, moral psychologists, and institutional review boards
must become sensitive to the ethical issues involved between
designing "realistic" virtual dilemmas, for good data collection,
and avoiding virtually real trauma. Ethicists and game designers
must do more to ensure that their simulations don't inculcate
harmful character traits. Virtually real experiences, the author
claims, can make virtual relationships meaningful, productive, and
conducive to welfare but they can also be used to systematically
mislead and manipulate users about the nature of their experiences.
The Ethics of Virtual and Augmented Reality will appeal to
philosophers working in applied ethics, philosophy of technology,
and aesthetics, as well as researchers and students interested in
game studies and game design.
This volume advances discussion between critics and defenders of
the force-content distinction and opens up new ways of thinking
about force and speech acts in relation to the unity problem. The
force-content dichotomy has shaped the philosophy of language and
mind since the time of Frege and Russell. Isn't it obvious that,
for example, the clauses of a conditional are not asserted and must
therefore be propositions and propositions the forceless contents
of forceful acts? But, others have recently asked in response, how
can a proposition be a truth value bearer if it is not unified
through the forceful act of a subject that takes a position
regarding how things are? Can we not instead think of propositions
as being inherently forceful, but of force as being cancelled in
certain contexts? And what do assertoric, but also directive and
interrogative force indicators mean? Force, Content and the Unity
of the Proposition will be of interest to researchers working in
philosophy of language, philosophical logic, philosophy of mind and
linguistics.
This book is the first detailed and focused defense of
necessitarianism. The author's original account of necessitarianism
encourages a reexamination of commonly held metaphysical positions
as well as important issues in other, related areas of philosophy.
Necessitarianism is the view that absolutely nothing about the
world could have been otherwise in any way, whatsoever. Most
philosophers believe that necessitarianism is just plain false and
presume that some things could have been otherwise than what they
are. In this book, the author argues that necessitarianism is true
and the view that some things in the world are contingent-what the
author terms contingentarianism-is false. The author assesses
various theories of contingency, including the possible worlds
theory, combinatorialism, and dispositionalism, and argues that no
theory can successfully explain why an entity is such as it is
rather than not. She then lays out a case for necessitarianism and
provides responses to various objections. The book concludes with
an explanation of the ways in which necessitarianism is relevant to
issues in ethics, philosophy of mind, and social philosophy. A Case
for Necessitarianism will be of interest to scholars and advanced
students working in metaphysics, logic, and philosophy of science.
This book argues for the explanatory autonomy of the biological
sciences. It does so by showing that scientific explanations in the
biological sciences cannot be reduced to explanations in the
fundamental sciences such as physics and chemistry and by
demonstrating that biological explanations are advanced by models
rather than laws of nature. To maintain the explanatory autonomy of
the biological sciences, the author argues against explanatory
reductionism and shows that explanation in the biological sciences
can be achieved without reduction. Then, he demonstrates that the
biological sciences do not have laws of nature. Instead of laws, he
suggests that biological models usually do the explanatory work. To
understand how a biological model can explain phenomena in the
world, the author proposes an inferential account of model
explanation. The basic idea of this account is that, for a model to
be explanatory, it must answer two kinds of questions:
counterfactual-dependence questions that concern the model itself
and hypothetical questions that concern the relationship between
the model and its target system. The reason a biological model can
answer these two kinds of questions is due to the fact that a model
is a structure, and the holistic relationship between the model and
its target warrants the hypothetical inference from the model to
its target and thus helps to answer the second kind of question.
The Explanatory Autonomy of the Biological Sciences will be of
interest to researchers and advanced students working in philosophy
of science, philosophy of biology and metaphysics.
The book surveys the key metaphysical contributions of the
Cambridge Platonist, Henry More (1614-1687). It deals with such
interwoven topics as: the natures of body and spirit, and the
question of whether or not there is a sharp ontological division
between them; the nature of spatial extension in relation to each;
the composition and governance of the physical world, including
More's theories of Hyle, atoms, vacuum, and the Spirit of Nature;
and the life of the human soul, including its pre-existence. It
approaches these topics and the systematic connections between them
both historically and analytically, and seeks to do justice to the
ways in which More's system developed and changed-sometimes quite
dramatically-over the course of his long career. It also explores
More's intellectual relations with both his own inspirations
(Plotinus, Origen, Ficino, Descartes, etc.) and with those who
responded, whether positively or negatively, to his work (Leibniz,
Locke, Boyle, Newton, etc.).
|
|