|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Metaphysics & ontology
This volume takes up Heidegger's idea of a phenomenological
chronology in an attempt to pose the question of the possibility of
a phenomenological language that would be given over to the
temporality of being and the finitude of existence. The book
combines a discussion of approaches to language in the
philosophical tradition with readings of Husserl on temporality and
the early and late texts of Heidegger's on logic, truth and the
nature of language. As well as Heidegger's deconstruction of logic
and metaphysics Dastur's work is also informed by Derrida's
deconstruction of the metaphysics of presence and Nietzschean
genealogy. Appealing a much to Humboldt's philosophy of language as
to Holderin's poetic thought, the book illuminates the eminently
dialectical structure of speech and its essential connection with
mortality.
This book offers a new and original hypothesis on the origin of
modal ontology, whose roots can be traced back to the mathematical
debate about incommensurable magnitudes, which forms the implicit
background for Plato's later dialogues and culminates in the
definition of being as dynamis in the Sophist. Incommensurable
magnitudes - also called dynameis by Theaetetus - are presented as
the solution to the problem of non-being and serve as the
cornerstone for a philosophy of difference and becoming. This shift
also marks the passage to another form of rationality - one not of
the measure, but of the mediation. The book argues that the
ontology and the rationality which arise out of the discovery of
incommensurable constitutes a thread that runs through the entire
history of philosophy, one that leads to Kantian transcendentalism
and to the philosophies derived from it, such as Hegelianism and
philosophical hermeneutics. Readers discover an insightful exchange
with some of the most important issues in philosophy, newly
reconsidered from the point of view of an ontology of the
incommensurable. These issues include the infinite, the continuum,
existence, and difference. This text appeals to students and
researchers in the fields of ancient philosophy, German idealism,
philosophical hermeneutics and the history of mathematics.
This text by a well-known author provides an approachable
introduction to the six great arguments for the existence of God.
Requiring no specialist knowledge of philosophy, an important
feature of The Question of God is the inclusion of a wealth of
primary sources drawn from both classic and contemporary texts.
With its combination of critical analysis and extensive extracts,
this book will be particularly attractive to students and teachers
of philosophy, religious studies and theology, at school or
university level, who are looking for a text that offers a detailed
and authoritative account of these famous arguments - The
Ontological Argument (Sources: Anselm, Haight, Descartes, Kant,
Findlay, Malcolm, Hick), The Cosmological Argument (Sources:
Aquinas, Taylor, Hume, Kant), The Argument from Design (Sources:
Paley, Hume, Darwin, Dawkins, Ward), The Argument from Miracles
(Sources: Hume, Hambourger, Coleman, Flew, Swinburne, Diamond), The
Moral Argument (Sources: Plato, Lewis, Kant, Rachels, Martin,
Nielsen), and The Pragmatic Argument (Sources: Pascal, Gracely,
Stich, Penelhum, James, Moore).
Things are particulars and their qualities are universals, but do
universals have an existence distinct from the particular things
describable by those terms? And what must be their nature if they
do? This book provides a careful and assured survey of the central
issues of debate surrounding universals, in particular those issues
that have been a crucial part of the emergence of contemporary
analytic ontology. The book begins with a taxonomy of extreme
nominalist, moderate nominalist, and realist positions on
properties, and outlines the way each handles the phenomena of
predication, resemblance, and abstract reference. The debate about
properties and philosophical naturalism is also examined. Different
forms of extreme nominalism, moderate nominalism, and minimalist
realism are critiqued. Later chapters defend a traditional realist
view of universals and examine the objections to realism from
various infinite regresses, the difficulties in stating identity
conditions for properties, and problems with realist accounts of
knowledge of abstract objects. In addition, the debate between
Platonists and Aristotelians is examined alongside a discussion of
the relationship between properties and an adequate theory of
existence. The book's final chapter explores the problem of
individuating particulars. The book makes accessible a difficult
topic without blunting the sophistication of argument required by a
more advanced readership.
Contents: Matilal, B K, Ontological Problems in Nyaya, Buddhism and Jainism: A Comparitive Analysis, Journal of Indian Philosophy 5 [1977] Potter, Karl H, Vedantaparibhasa as Systematic Reconstruction, SS Rama Rao Pappu ed. Perspectives on Vedanta, Essays in Honor of Professor T Raju [Leiden: E J Brill, 1988] Chakrabarti, Kisor, The Nyaya-Vaisesika Theory of Universals, Journal of Indian Philosophy 3 [1975] Siderits, Mark, More Things in Heaven and Earth, Journal of Indian Philosophy, 10 [1982] Gillon, Brendon S, Negative Facts and Knowledge of Negative Facts, P. Bilimoria and J N Mohanty eds., Relativism, Suffering and Beyond [Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1997] Kapstein, Matthew, Mercological Considerations in Vasubandhu's Proof of Idealism,(Vijnaptimatratasiddhi) Idealstic Studies 18 [1988] Matilal, B K, Causality in the Nyaya-Vaisesika School, Philosophy East and West 44 [1975] Potter, Karl H, An Ontology of Concrete Connectors, Journal of Philosophy 58 [1961] Garfield, Jay L, Dependent Arising and the Emptiness of Emptiness: Why Did Nagarjuna Start with Causation?, Philosophy East and West 44 [1994] Potter, Karl H, Freedom and Determinism from an Indian Perspective, Philosophy East and West 17 [1967] Duerlinger, James, Reductionist and Nonreductionist Theories of Persons in Indian Buddhist Philosophy, Journal of Indian Philosophy 21 [1993] Bastow, David, Self-Construction in Buddhism, Ratio 28 [1986] Siderits, Mark, Buddhist Reductionism, Philosophy East and West 47 [1997] Taber, John, The Mimamsa Theory of Self Recognition, Philosophy East and West 40 [1990] Chakrabarti, Arindam, I Touch What I Saw, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 [1992] Shukla, Pandit Badrinath, Dehatmavada or the Body as Soul: Exploration of a Possibility Within Nyaya Thought, Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 5 [1988] Larson, Gerald James, An Eccentric Ghost in the Machine: Formal and Quantitative Aspects of the Samkhya-Yoga Dualism, Philosophy East and West 33 [1983] Schweizer, Paul, Mind/Consciousness Dualism in Sankhya-Yoga Philosophy, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 [1993] Deutsch, Eliot, The Self in Advaita Vedanta, International Philosophical Quarterly 6 [1966] Bhattacharyya, K C, The Concept of the Absolute and its Alternative Forms, Philosophical Studies 2 [Calcutta: Progressive Publishers, 1958]
This book provides a framework that encompasses both physics and
cognitive science - integrating them into a 'theory of everything'
to establish a basis for both our scientific and humanistic
endeavours. It explores the implications of brain laterality for
understanding the emergence of mind and its relation to the
physical world - arguing that the analytic vs. holistic cognitive
differences of the left and right human cerebral hemispheres are
key to understanding not only human self-consciousness and
language, but also sociocultural phenomena ranging from the
emergence of the scientific method and axes of political
orientation to the direction of development of conceptions of God
and the fundamental differences between polarizing philosophical
traditions. In a further step, the book draws on the Darwinian
principle that our cognitive apparatus is shaped by the environment
in which it evolved to argue that human bilaterality mirrors the
fundamental hylomorphic relation between formal organization and
material components that constitutes physical nature itself. The
logical division between holistic and analytic categories thereby
offers a principled basis for a metaphilosophy.
First published in 2000. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor &
Francis, an informa company.
First published in 2000. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor &
Francis, an informa company.
First published in 2000. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor &
Francis, an informa company.
"Routledge Philosophy Guidebooks" introduce students to the classic
works of philosophy. Each guidebook considers a major philosopher
and a key area of their philosophy by focusing upon an important
text - situating the philosopher and work in a historical context,
considering the text in question and assessing the philosopher's
contribution to contemporary thought.;Leibniz is a major figure in
western philosophy and, with Descartes and Spinoza, one of the most
influential philosophers of the Rationalist School. The
"Monadology" is his most famous work and one of the most important
works of modern philosophy. This text introduces and assesses:
Leibniz's life and the background to the "Monadology"; the ideas
and text of the "Monadology"; and Leibniz's continuing importance
to philosophy.
Series Information: Studies in Philosophy
At the origin of this volume, a simple question: what to make of
that surprisingly monotonous series of statements produced by our
societies and our philosophers that all converge in one theme - the
importance of difference?
To clarify the meaning of the difference at stake here, we have
tried to rephrase it in terms of the two major and mutually
competing paradigms provided by the history of phenomenology only
to find both of them equally unable to accommodate this difference
without violence. Neither the ethical nor the ontological approach
can account for a subject that insists on playing a part of its own
rather than following the script provided for it by either Being or
the Good. What appears to be, from a Heideggerian or Levinasian
perspective, an unwillingness to open up to what offers to deliver
us from the condition of subjectivity is analysed in these pages as
a structure in its own right. Far from being the wilful,
indifferent and irresponsive being its critics have portrayed it to
be, the so-called 'postmodern' subject is essentially finite, not
even able to assume the transcendence to which it owes its
singularity. This inability is not a lack - it points instead to a
certain unthought shared by both Heidegger and Levinas which sets
the terms for a discussion no longer our own. Instead of blaming
Heidegger for underdeveloping 'being-with', we should rather stress
that his account of mineness may be, in the light of contemporary
philosophy, what stands most in need of revision. And, instead of
hailing Levinas as the critic whose stress on the alterity of the
Other corrects Heidegger's existential solipsism, the problems into
which Levinas runs in defining that alterity call for a different
diagnosis and a corresponding change in the course that
phenomenology has taken since. Instead of preoccupying itself with
the invisible, we should focus on the structures of visibility that
protect us from its terror.
The result? An account of difference that is neither ontological
nor ethical, but 'me-ontological', and that can help us understand
some of the problems our societies have come to face (racism,
sexism, multiculturalism, pluralism). And, in the wake of this, an
unexpected defence of what is at stake in postmodernism and in the
question it has refused to take lightly: who are we? Finally, an
homage to Arendt and Lyotard who, if read through each other's
lenses, give an exact articulation to the question with which our
age struggles: how to think the 'human condition' once one realizes
that there is an 'inhuman' side to it which, instead of being its
mere negation, turns out to be that without which it would come to
lose its humanity?"
Generally, categories are understood to express the most general
features of reality. Yet, since categories have this special
status, obtaining a correct list of them is difficult. This
question is addressed by examining how Thomas Aquinas establishes
the list of categories through a technique of identifying diversity
in how predicates are per se related to their subjects. A
sophisticated critique by Duns Scotus of this position is also
examined, a rejection which is fundamentally grounded in the idea
that no real distinction can be made from a logical one. It is
argued Aquinas's approach can be rehabilitated in that real
distinctions are possible when specifically considering per se
modes of predication. This discussion between Aquinas and Scotus
bears fruit in a contemporary context insofar as it bears upon,
strengthens, and seeks to correct E. J. Lowe's four-category
ontology view regarding the identity and relation of the
categories.
This book critically examines the case for and against the belief
in personal survival of bodily death. It discusses key
philosophical questions. How could a discarnate individual be
identified as a person who was once alive? What is the relationship
between minds and their brains? Is a 'next world' conceivable? The
book also examines classic arguments for the immortality of the
soul, and focuses on types of prima facie evidence of survival:
near-death experiences, apparitions, mediumistic communications,
and ostensible reincarnation cases.
Gustav Bergmann (1906-1987) was, arguably, one of the greatest
ontologists of the twentieth century. In 2006 and 2007, after a
period of relative neglect, international conferences devoted
solely to Bergmann's work were held at the University of Iowa in
the USA, Universite de Provence in France, and Universita degli
Studi di Roma Tre in Italy. The fifteen papers collected in this
volume were presented at the third of these conferences, in Rome,
and are here divided into three sections: "Categories of a
realistic ontology," "World, mind, and relations," "Metaphysics of
space and time.""
The Conceptual Roots of Mathematics is a comprehensive study of the foundation of mathematics. J.R. Lucas, one of the most distinguished Oxford scholars, covers a vast amount of ground in the philosophy of mathematics, showing us that it is actually at the heart of the study of epistemology and metaphysics. eBook available with sample pages: EB:0203028422
The question raised in this book is why Spinoza's work which comes
so close to the modern view of natural science is not prominent in
the social sciences. The answer suggested is that this is due to
the lingering influence of the Cartesian differentiation between
the domain of science, dealing with material bodies in space and
time, and the realm of thought to which the mind belongs. Spinoza's
rejection of this mind/body dualism was based on his conviction
that the human mind was an essential part of the 'forces' which
maintain human existence. Since this view fits so well the
evolutionary view of life, the book suggests that after Darwin,
when this dualism became untenable, it was replaced by a nature
versus culture dichotomy. The book examines whether the history of
the philosophy of science supports this explanation. The author
believes that answering this question is important because of the
rising influence of cultural relativism which endangers the very
survival of modern science and political stability.
First Published in 1999. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor &
Francis, an informa company.
Nietzsche's critique of the modern subject is often presented as a
radical break with modern philosophy and associated with the
so-called 'death of the subject' in 20th century philosophy. But
Nietzsche claimed to be a 'psychologist' who was trying to open up
the path for 'new versions and sophistications of the soul
hypothesis.' Although there is no doubt that Nietzsche gave
expression to a fundamental crisis of the modern conception of
subjectivity (both from a theoretical and from a
practical-existential perspective), it is open to debate whether he
wanted to abandon the very idea of subjectivity or only to pose the
problem of subjectivity in new terms. The volume includes 26
articles by top Nietzsche scholars. The chapters in Part I,
"Tradition and Context", deal with the relationship between
Nietzsche's views on subjectivity and modern philosophy, as well as
with the late 19th century context in which his thought emerged;
Part II, "The Crisis of the Subject", examines the impact of
Nietzsche's critique of the subject on 20th century philosophy,
from Freud to Heidegger to Dennett, but also in such authors as
Deleuze, Foucault, Derrida, or Luhmann; Part III, "Current Debates
- From Embodiment and Consciousness to Agency", shows that the way
in which Nietzsche engaged with such themes as the self, agency,
consciousness, embodiment and self-knowledge makes his thought
highly relevant for philosophy today, especially for philosophy of
mind and ethics.
Personal Agency consists of two parts. In Part II, a radically
libertarian theory of action is defended which combines aspects of
agent causalism and volitionism. This theory accords to volitions
the status of basic mental actions, maintaining that these are
spontaneous exercises of the will--a 'two-way' power which rational
agents can freely exercise in the light of reason. Lowe contends
that substances, not events, are the causal source of all change in
the world--with rational, free agents like ourselves having a
special place in the causal order as unmoved movers, or initiators
of new causal chains. And he defends a thoroughgoing externalism
regarding reasons for action, holding these to be mind-independent
worldly entities rather than the beliefs and desires of agents.
Part I prepares the ground for this theory by undermining the
threat presented to it by physicalism. It does this by challenging
the causal closure argument for physicalism in all of its forms and
by showing that a dualistic philosophy of mind--one which holds
that human mental states and their subjects cannot be identified
with bodily states and human bodies respectively--is both
metaphysically coherent and entirely consistent with known
empirical facts.
"For a long time now, religion in the West has been polarized
between a democratic kind of faith meant for simple believers, and
divine mysteries so high that hardly anyone can claim to know much
about them. The vital connecting link between them, that of
metaphysical religion, is all but lost..." (From the Introduction.)
There are many books that seek to answer the fundamental questions
of life: Who am I? Does life have a purpose? How should I live? Dr
Bolton's book brings to these universal questions an extraordinary
degree of metaphysical insight. It contains in highly condensed
form a veritable library of traditional wisdom, offering a
systematic reconstruction of our understanding of the soul and its
relation to archetypal reality. Its starting-point is the fact that
increasing numbers of people seem to lack spiritual and material
power over their own lives. Modern man feels like a victim. But
true power, real freedom, is closer than we think. Our mistake lies
in accepting a false view of the self, and neglecting the
metaphysical dimension that gives access to eternity. Dr Bolton's
book offers a crash-course in liberation. It can liberate us,
specifically, from a common sense idea of reality which is
profoundly false, and which holds us in unconscious slavery to time
and appearances. The book defends the capacity of the human mind to
obtain objective insight, despite the obfuscations of
postmodernism, and represents a bold development of the Platonist
tradition associated with St Augustine, Plotinus, and Proclus.
"This book is like a diamond: a diamond placed not in a necklace,
but at the business end of a drill. It is up to us to use the drill
to penetrate reality. Writing the book was a great achievement.
Reading it invites us to make the achievement our own." - Stratford
Caldecott (G.K. Chesterton Institute for Faith & Culture)
|
You may like...
Mud fun
Paul George
Paperback
R180
R127
Discovery Miles 1 270
|