|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present > Western philosophy, c 1600 to c 1800
Why should anybody take an interest in philosophy? Is it just
another detailed study like metallurgy? Or is it similar to
history, literature and even religion: a study meant to do some
personal good and influence our lives? "Engaging and accessible,
this vigorous swansong exemplifies many of Midgley's virtues, and
revisits many of her favourite themes." - The Tablet In her last
published work, Mary Midgley addresses provocative questions,
interrogating the various forms of our current intellectual
anxieties and confusions and how we might deal with them. In doing
so, she provides a robust, yet not uncritical, defence of
philosophy and the life of the mind. This defence is expertly
placed in the context of contemporary debates about science,
religion, and philosophy. It asks whether, in light of rampant
scientific and technological developments, we still need philosophy
to help us think about the big questions of meaning, knowledge, and
value.
This book proposes a new and systematic interpretation of the
mental nature, function and structure, and importance of the
imagination in Book 1, 'Of the Understanding', of Hume's Treatise
of Human Nature. The proposed interpretation has deeply revisionary
implications for Hume's philosophy of mind and for his naturalism,
epistemology, and stance to scepticism. The book remedies a
surprising blindspot in Hume scholarship and contributes to the
current, lively philosophical debate on imagination. Hume's
philosophy, if rightly understood, gives suggestions about how to
treat imagination as a mental natural kind, its cognitive
complexity and variety of functions notwithstanding. Hume's
imagination is a faculty of inference and the source of a
distinctive kind of idea, which complements our sensible
representations of objects. Our cognitive nature, if restricted to
the representation of objects and of their relations, would leave
ordinary and philosophical cognition seriously underdetermined and
expose us to scepticism. Only the non-representational, inferential
faculty of the imagination can put in place and vindicate ideas
like causation, body, and self, which support our cognitive
practices. The book reconstructs how Hume's naturalist
inferentialism about the imagination develops this fundamental
insight. Its five parts deal with the dualism of representation and
inference; the explanation of generality and modality; the
production of causal ideas; the production of spatial and temporal
content, and the distinction of an external world of bodies and an
internal one of selves; and the replacement of the understanding
with imagination in the analysis of cognition and in epistemology.
Designed as a textbook for use in courses on natural theology and
used by Immanuel Kant as the basis for his Lectures on The
Philosophical Doctrine of Religion, Johan August Eberhard's
Preparation for Natural Theology (1781) is now available in English
for the first time. With a strong focus on the various intellectual
debates and historically significant texts in late renaissance and
early modern theology, Preparation for Natural Theology influenced
the way Kant thought about practical cognition as well as moral and
religious concepts. Access to Eberhard's complete text makes it
possible to distinguish where in the lectures Kant is making
changes to what Eberhard has written and where he is articulating
his own ideas. Identifying new unexplored lines of research, this
translation provides a deeper understanding of Kant's explicitly
religious doctrines and his central moral writings, such as the
Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals and the Critique of
Practical Reason. Accompanied by Kant's previously untranslated
handwritten notes on Eberhard's text as well as the Danzig
transcripts of Kant's course on rational theology, Preparation for
Natural Theology features a dual English-German / German-English
glossary, a concordance and an introduction situating the book in
relation to 18th-century theology and philosophy. This is a
significant contribution to twenty-first century Kantian studies.
In this interdisciplinary work, Stacy J. Lettman explores real and
imagined violence as depicted in Caribbean and Jamaican text and
music, how that violence repeats itself in both art and in the
actions of the state, and what that means for Caribbean cultural
identity. Jamaica is known for having one of the highest per capita
murder rates in the world, a fact that Lettman links to remnants of
the plantation era-namely the economic dispossession and structural
violence that still haunt the island. Lettman contends that the
impact of colonial violence is so embedded in the language of
Jamaican literature and music that violence has become a separate
language itself, one that paradoxically can offer cultural modes of
resistance. Lettman codifies Paul Gilroy's concept of the "slave
sublime" as a remix of Kantian philosophy through a Caribbean lens
to take a broad view of Jamaica, the Caribbean, and their political
and literary history that challenges Eurocentric ideas of slavery,
Blackness, and resistance. Living at the intersection of
philosophy, literary and musical analysis, and postcolonial theory,
this book sheds new light on the lingering ghosts of the plantation
and slavery in the Caribbean.
In this interdisciplinary work, Stacy J. Lettman explores real and
imagined violence as depicted in Caribbean and Jamaican text and
music, how that violence repeats itself in both art and in the
actions of the state, and what that means for Caribbean cultural
identity. Jamaica is known for having one of the highest per capita
murder rates in the world, a fact that Lettman links to remnants of
the plantation era-namely the economic dispossession and structural
violence that still haunt the island. Lettman contends that the
impact of colonial violence is so embedded in the language of
Jamaican literature and music that violence has become a separate
language itself, one that paradoxically can offer cultural modes of
resistance. Lettman codifies Paul Gilroy's concept of the "slave
sublime" as a remix of Kantian philosophy through a Caribbean lens
to take a broad view of Jamaica, the Caribbean, and their political
and literary history that challenges Eurocentric ideas of slavery,
Blackness, and resistance. Living at the intersection of
philosophy, literary and musical analysis, and postcolonial theory,
this book sheds new light on the lingering ghosts of the plantation
and slavery in the Caribbean.
This book offers new critical perspectives on the relationship
between the notions of speculation, logic and reality in Hegel's
thought as basis for his philosophical account of nature, history,
spirit and human experience. The systematic functions of logic and
pure thought are explored in their concrete forms and processual
progression from subjective spirit to philosophy of right, society,
the notion of habit, the idea of work, art, religion and science.
Engaging the relation between the Logic and its realisations, this
book shows the internal tension that inhabits Hegel's philosophy at
the intersection of logical (conceptual) speculation and concrete
(interpretative) analysis. The investigation of this tension allows
for a hermeneutical approach that demystifies the common view of
Hegel's idealism as a form of abstract thought, while allowing for
a new assessment of the importance of speculation for a concrete
understanding of the world.
First published in 1752, Excerpt from the Doctrine of Reason
[Auszug aus der Vernunftlehre] was written as a textbook and widely
adopted by many 18th-century German instructors, but most notably
by Immanuel Kant. For forty years Kant used the Excerpts as the
basis of his lectures on logic making extensive notes on his copy
of the text. More than a text on formal logic, Excerpt from the
Doctrine of Reason covers epistemology and the elements of thought
and language Meier believed made human understanding possible.
Working across the two dominant intellectual forces in modern
philosophy, the rationalist and the empiricist traditions, Meier's
work was also instrumental to the introduction of English
philosophy into Germany; he was among the first German philosophers
to study John Locke's philosophy in depth. This complete English
translation of Meier's influential textbook is introduced by
Riccardo Pozzo and enhanced by a glossary and a concordance
correlating Meier's arguments to Kant's logic lectures, the related
Reflexionen and the Jasche Logic of 1800 - the text considered of
fundamental importance to Kant's philosophy. For scholars of Kant,
Locke and the German Enlightenment, this valuable translation and
its accompanying material presents the richest source of
information available on Meier and his 18th-century work.
In this book, Marek Sullivan challenges a widespread consensus
linking secularization to rationalization, and argues for a more
sensual genealogy of secularity connected to affect, race and
power. While existing works of secular intellectual history,
especially Charles Taylor's A Secular Age (2007), tend to rely on
rationalistic conceptions of Enlightenment thought, Sullivan offers
an alternative perspective on key thinkers such as Descartes,
Montesquieu and Diderot, asserting that these figures sought to
reinstate emotion against the rationalistic tendencies of the past.
From Descartes's last work Les Passions de l'Ame (1649) to Baron
d'Holbach's System of Nature (1770), the French Enlightenment
demonstrated an acute understanding of the limits of reason, with
crucial implications for our current 'postsecular' and
'postliberal' moment. Sullivan also emphasizes the importance of
Western constructions of Oriental religions for the history of the
secular, identifying a distinctively secular-yet impassioned-form
of Orientalism that emerged in the 18th century. Mahomet's racial
profile in Voltaire's Le Fanatisme, ou Mahomet (1741), for example,
functioned as a polemic device calibrated for emotional impact, in
line with Enlightenment efforts to generate an affective body of
anti-Catholic propaganda that simultaneously shored up people's
sense of national belonging. By exposing the Enlightenment as a
nationalistic and affective movement that resorted to racist,
Orientalist and emotional tropes from the outset, Sullivan
ultimately undermines modern nationalist appeals to the
Enlightenment as a mark of European distinction.
For philosophers of German idealism and early German romanticism,
the imagination is central to issues ranging from hermeneutics to
transcendental logic and from ethics to aesthetics. This volume of
new essays brings together, for the first time, comprehensive and
critical reflections on the significances of the imagination during
this period, with essays on Kant and the imagination, the
imagination in post-Kantian German idealism, and the imagination in
early German romanticism. The essays explore the many and varied
uses of the imagination and discuss whether they form a coherent or
shared notion or whether they embody points of philosophical
divergence within these traditions. They shed new light on one of
the most important and enigmatic aspects of human nature, as
understood in the context of a profoundly influential era of
western thought.
|
|