|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present
This collection of eleven new essays contains the latest
developments in analytic feminist philosophy on the topic of
pornography. While honoring early feminist work on the subject, it
aims to go beyond speech act analyses of pornography and to reshape
the philosophical discourse that surrounds pornography. A rich
feminist literature on pornography has emerged since the 1980s,
with Rae Langton's speech act theoretic analysis dominating
specifically Anglo-American feminist philosophy on pornography.
Despite the predominance of this literature, there remain
considerable disagreements and precious little agreement on many
key issues: What is pornography? Does pornography (as Langton
argues) constitute women's subordination and silencing? Does it
objectify women in harmful ways? Is pornography authoritative
enough to enact women's subordination? Is speech act theory the
best way to approach pornography? Given the deep divergences over
these questions, the first goal of this collection is to take stock
of extant debates in order to clarify key feminist conceptual and
political commitments regarding pornography. This volume further
aims to go beyond the prevalent speech-acts approach to
pornography, and to highlight novel issues in feminist
pornography-debates, including the aesthetics of pornography,
trans* identities and racialization in pornography, and putatively
feminist pornography.
Nietzsche, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics explores how
Nietzsche criticizes, adopts, and reformulates Kant's critique of
metaphysics and his transcendental idealism. Thing in itself and
phenomenon, space and time, intuition and thought, the I and
self-consciousness, concepts and judgments, categories and
schemata, teleological judgement: building on established and
recent literature on these topics in both thinkers, this volume
asks whether Nietzsche can - malgr lui - be considered a Kantian of
sorts. Nietzsche's intensive engagement with early Neo-Kantians
(Lange, Liebmann, Fischer, von Helmholtz) and other contemporaries
of his, largely ignored in the Anglophone literature, is also
addressed, raising the question whether Nietzsche's positions on
Kant's theoretical philosophy are best understood as historically
embedded in the often rather loose relation they had to the first
Critique. These and other questions are taken up in Nietzsche, Kant
and the Problem of Metaphysics, which in different ways tackles the
complexities of Nietzsche's relation to Kant's theoretical
philosophy and its reception in nineteenth Century philosophy.
Simone de Beauvoir and Luce Irigaray famously insisted on their
philosophical differences, and this mutual insistence has largely
guided the reception of their thought. What does it mean to return
to Simone de Beauvoir and Luce Irigaray in light of questions and
problems of contemporary feminism, including intersectional and
queer criticisms of their projects? How should we now take up,
amplify, and surpass the horizons opened by their projects? Seeking
answers to these questions, the essays in this volume return to
Beauvoir and Irigaray to find what the two philosophers share. And
as the authors make clear, the richness of Beauvoir and Irigaray's
thought far exceeds the reductive parameters of the Eurocentric,
bourgeois second-wave debates that have constrained interpretation
of their work. The first section of this volume places Beauvoir and
Irigaray in critical dialogue, exploring the place of the material
and the corporeal in Beauvoir's thought and, in doing so, reading
Beauvoir in a framework that goes beyond a theory of gender and the
humanism of phenomenology. The essays in the second section of the
volume take up the challenge of articulating points of dialogue
between the two focal philosophers in logic, ethics, and politics.
Combined, these essays resituate Beauvoir and Irigaray's work both
historically and in light of contemporary demands, breaking new
ground in feminist philosophy.
Ex nihilo nihil fit. Philosophy, especially great philosophy, does
not appear out of the blue. In the current volume, a team of top
scholars-both up-and-coming and established-attempts to trace the
philosophical development of one of the greatest philosophers of
all time. Featuring twenty new essays and an introduction, it is
the first attempt of its kind in English and its appearance
coincides with the recent surge of interest in Spinoza in
Anglo-American philosophy. Spinoza's fame-or notoriety-is due
primarily to his posthumously published magnum opus, the Ethics,
and, to a lesser extent, to the 1670 Theological-Political
Treatise. Few readers take the time to study his early works
carefully. If they do, they are likely to encounter some surprising
claims, which often diverge from, or even utterly contradict, the
doctrines of the Ethics. Consider just a few of these assertions:
that God acts from absolute freedom of will, that God is a whole,
that there are no modes in God, that extension is divisible and
hence cannot be an attribute of God, and that the intellectual and
corporeal substances are modes in relation to God. Yet, though
these claims reveal some tension between the early works and the
Ethics, there is also a clear continuity between them. Spinoza
wrote the Ethics over a long period of time, which spanned most of
his philosophical career. The dates of the early drafts of the
Ethics seem to overlap with the assumed dates of the composition of
the Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect and the Short
Treatise on God, Man, and His Well Being and precede the
publication of Spinoza's 1663 book on Descartes' Principles of
Philosophy. For this reason, a study of Spinoza's early works (and
correspondence) can illuminate the nature of the problems Spinoza
addresses in the Ethics, insofar as the views expressed in the
early works help us reconstruct the development and genealogy of
the Ethics. Indeed, if we keep in mind the common dictum "nothing
comes from nothing "-which Spinoza frequently cites and appeals
to-it is clear that great works like the Ethics do not appear ex
nihilo. In light of the preeminence and majesty of the Ethics, it
is difficult to study the early works without having the Ethics in
sight. Still, we would venture to say that the value of Spinoza's
early works is not at all limited to their being stations on the
road leading to the Ethics. A teleological attitude of such a sort
would celebrate the works of the "mature Spinoza " at the expense
of the early works. However, we have no reason to assume that on
all issues the views of the Ethics are better argued, developed,
and motivated than those of the early works. In other words, we
should keep our minds open to the possibility that on some issues
the early works might contain better analysis and argumentation
than the Ethics.
Colin Wilson revitalised existentialism with a completely new
approach to the philosophy. The six volumes of his 'Outsider'
series created an existentialism that is not paralysed by its own
nihilism. This book, first published in 1966, is a clear summary of
the ideas of the 'Outsider' cycle, and also develops them to a new
stage. Wilson's 'new existentialism' sees philosophy as an
intellectual adventure that aims at a real command and control of
human existence, and this book is its clearest exponent.
Plato's "Phaedo", Hegel's "Phenomenology of Spirit" and Heidegger's
"Being and Time" are three of the most profound meditations on
variations of the ideas that to practice philosophy is to practice
how to die. This study traces how these variations are connected
with each other and with the reflections of this idea to be found
in the works of other ancient and modern philosophers - including
Neitzsche, Husserl, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty and levinas. The book
also shows how this philosophical thanatology motivates or is
motivated by experiences documented in psychoanalysis and in the
anthropology of Western and Oriental religions and myths.
In George Berkeley's two most important works, the Principles of
Human Knowledge and Three Dialogues Bewtween Hylas and Philonous,
he argued that there is no such thing as matter: only minds and
ideas exist, and physical things are nothing but collections of
ideas. In defense of this idealism, he advanced a battery of
challenging arguments purporting to show that the very notion of
matter is self-contradictory or meaningless, and that even if it
were possible for matter to exist, we could not know that it does;
and he then put forward an alternative world-view that purported to
refute both skepticism and atheism.
Using the tools of contemporary analytic philosophy, Georges Dicker
here examines both the destructive and the constructive sides of
Berkeley's thought, against the background of the mainstream views
that he rejected. Dicker's accessible and text-based analysis of
Berkeley's arguments shows that the Priniciples and the Dialogues
dovetail and complement each other in a seamless way, rather than
being self-contained. Dicker's book avoids the incompleteness that
results from studying just one of his two main works; instead, he
treats the whole as a visionary response to the issues of modern
philosophy- such as primary and secondary qualities, external-world
skepticism, the substance-property relation, the causal roles of
human agents and of God. In addition to relating Berkeley's work to
his contemporaries, Dicker discusses work by today's top Berkeley
scholars, and uses notions and distinctions forged by recent and
contemporary analytic philosophers of perception. Berkeley's
Idealism both advances Berkeley scholarship and serves as a useful
guide for teachers and students.
The English philosopher Herbert Spencer (1820 - 1903) was a
colossus of the Victorian age. His works ranked alongside those of
Darwin and Marx in the development of disciplines as wide ranging
as sociology, anthropology, political theory, philosophy and
psychology. In this acclaimed study of Spencer, the first for over
thirty years and now available in paperback, Mark Francis provides
an authoritative and meticulously researched intellectual biography
of this remarkable man that dispels the plethora of misinformation
surrounding Spencer and shines new light on the broader cultural
history of the nineteenth century. In this major study of Spencer,
the first for over thirty years, Mark Francis provides an
authoritative and meticulously researched intellectual biography of
this remarkable man. Using archival material and contemporary
printed sources, Francis creates a fascinating portrait of a human
being whose philosophical and scientific system was a unique
attempt to explain modern life in all its biological, psychological
and sociological forms. Herbert Spencer and the Invention of Modern
Life fills what is perhaps the last big biographical gap in
Victorian history. An exceptional work of scholarship it not only
dispels the plethora of misinformation surrounding Spencer but
shines new light on the broader cultural history of the nineteenth
century. Elegantly written, provocative and rich in insight it will
be required reading for all students of the period.
One of America's most celebrated poets, Emily Dickinson was
virtually unpublished in her lifetime. When a slim volume of her
poems emerged on the American scene in 1890, her work created
shockwaves that have not subsided yet. Famously precise and sparse,
Emily Dickinson's poetry is often described as philosophical, both
because her poetry grapples with philosophical topics like death,
spirituality, and the darkening operations of the mind, and because
she approaches those topics in a characteristically philosophical
manner: analyzing and extrapolating from close observation,
exploring alternatives, and connecting thoughts into cumulative
demonstrations. But unlike Lucretius or Pope, she cannot be accused
of producing versified treatises. Many of her poems are unsettling
in their lack of conclusion; their disparate insights often stand
in conflict; and her logic turns crucially on imagery,
juxtaposition, assonance, slant rhyme, and punctuation. The six
chapters of this volume collectively argue that Dickinson is an
epistemically ambitious poet, who explores fundamental questions by
advancing arguments that are designed to convince. Dickinson
exemplifies abstract ideas in tangible form and habituates readers
into productive trains of thought-she doesn't just make
philosophical claims, but demonstrates how poetry can make a
distinct contribution to philosophy. All essays in this volume,
drawn from both philosophers and literary theorists, serve as a
counterpoint to recent critical work, which has emphasized
Dickinson's anguished uncertainty, her nonconventional style, and
the unsettled status of her manuscripts. On the view that emerges
here, knowing is like cleaning, mending, and lacemakingL a form of
hard, ongoing work, but one for which poetry is a powerful, perhaps
indispensable, tool.
Friedrich Nietzsche has always been recognized as an original
thinker, one who stands apart from and outside the philosophical
schools and tendencies of his time. This is the way he continually
presented himself. Many readers have accepted this
self-interpretation at face value. Yet there is another side to
Nietzsche's thinking which shows not only an awareness of
contemporary writers, but an engagement with their ideas which is
often both intense and sustained. The intention of this study is to
explore this side in detail, by surveying various themes in his
philosophical thinking with such links in mind. It is important to
avoid one misunderstanding though: this book is not designed to
show that Nietzsche derived his ideas from various other thinkers.
In that sense, it is not necessarily about sources or even about
influences. Rather, it shows that his independence and originality
developed in dialogue with other thinkers. Those qualities are no
less real for that reason; in fact the author believes that they
can be appreciated all the more by being placed in the context of
his relations to other philosophers.
The "Nations" are the "seventy nations": a metaphor which, in the
Talmudic idiom, designates the whole of humanity surrounding
Israel. In this major collection of essays, Levinas considers
Judaism's uncertain relationship to European culture since the
Enlightenment, problems of distance and integration. It also
includes essays on Franz Rosenzweig and Moses Mendelssohn, and a
discussion of central importance to Jewish philosophy in the
context of general philosophy. This work brings to the fore the
vital encounter between philosophy and Judaism, a hallmark of
Levinas's thought.
Cheryl Misak presents the first collective study of the development
of philosophy in North America, from the 18th century to the end of
the 20th century. Twenty-six leading experts examine distinctive
features of American philosophy, trace notable themes, and consider
the legacy and influence of notable figures. This will be the first
reference point for future work on the subject, and a fascinating
resource for anyone interested in modern philosophy or American
intellectual history.
Conversations with My Dog by Hannah Gold is a tale for those who
love to seek new adventures and the promise of following their
dreams, or nose, into the unknown. In a fast-paced world, driven by
material achievement and the fear of loss; clarity can seem hard to
find. Sometimes answers can come from the most surprising sources.
When the author found herself confronted with challenges, she
discovered, to her surprise, that wisdom came not from a
philosophical master or spiritual guide, but her puppy named Monty.
On the road with him, she learns to stop and ask him questions. He
answers her through demonstrating the values of simplicity, fun and
love of exploration. This description of the conversations that
developed between them is a tale about rediscovering direction in
life. It gives a light-hearted, gently thought-provoking account of
the bigger journey of working out how to live. The search for the
way ahead is the metaphor that illustrates the eternal bond of
loyalty between a dog and its humanand makes this tale transcend
normal conversation. 'Even when we are in small bodies, we have big
spirits.' Writes Hannah Gold, relaying the replies of her wise
four-legged friend, to her questions about life. 'The very young
always know why they are here. Because they haven't forgotten.
Sometimes life muddles things up with too many thoughts. But the
heart is ageless.' Hannah's illustrations were created from
sketches she made of Monty on their travels. These drawings provide
a visual tapestry, depicting their journey together to inspire
readers in finding their own path. Conversations with My Dog is an
ideal companion for people considering significant change or
embarking on a new direction, however uncertain, or even just
searching for a little extra companionship and inspiration.
Thomas C. Vinci aims to reveal and assess the structure of Kant's
argument in the Critique of Pure Reason called the "Transcendental
Deduction of the Categories." At the end of the first part of the
Deduction in the B-edition Kant states that his purpose is
achieved: to show that all intuitions in general are subject to the
categories. On the standard reading, this means that all of our
mental representations, including those originating in
sense-experience, are structured by conceptualization. But this
reading encounters an exegetical problem: Kant states in the second
part of the Deduction that a major part of what remains to be shown
is that empirical intuitions are subject to the categories. How can
this be if it has already been shown that intuitions in general are
subject to the categories? Vinci calls this the Triviality Problem,
and he argues that solving it requires denying the standard
reading. In its place he proposes that intuitions in general and
empirical intuitions constitute disjoint classes and that, while
all intuitions for Kant are unified, there are two kinds of
unification: logical unification vs. aesthetic unification. Only
the former is due to the categories. A second major theme of the
book is that Kant's Idealism comes in two versions-for laws of
nature and for objects of empirical intuition-and that
demonstrating these versions is the ultimate goal of the Deduction
of the Categories and the similarly structured Deduction of the
Concepts of Space, respectively. Vinci shows that the Deductions
have the argument structure of an inference to the best explanation
for correlated domains of explananda, each arrived at by
independent applications of Kantian epistemic and geometrical
methods.
Frank Jackson champions the cause of conceptual analysis as central
to philosophical inquiry. In recent years conceptual analysis has
been undervalued and, Jackson suggests, widely misunderstood; he
argues that there is nothing especially mysterious about it and a
whole range of important questions cannot be productively addressed
without it. He anchors his argument in discussion of specific
philosophical issues, starting with the metaphysical doctrine of
physicalism and moving on, via free will, meaning, personal
identity, motion and change, to the philosophy of colour and to
ethics. The significance of different kinds of supervenience
theses, Kripke and Putnam's work in the philosophy of modality and
language, and the role of intuitions about possible cases receive
detailed attention. Jackson concludes with a defence of a version
of analytical descriptivism in ethics. In this way the book not
only offers a methodological programme for philosophy, but also
throws fascinating new light on some much-debated problems and
their interrelations. puffs which may be quoted (please do not edit
without consulting OUP editor): 'This is an outstanding book. It
covers a vast amount of philosophy in a very short space, advances
a number of original and striking positions, and manages to be both
clear and concise in its expositions of other views and forceful in
its criticisms of them. The book offers something new for those
interested in the various individual problems it
discusses-conceptual analysis, the mind-body relation, secondary
qualities, modality, and ethical realism. But unifying these
individual discussions is an ambitious structure which amounts to
an outline of a complete metaphysical system, and an outline of an
epistemology for this metaphysics. It is hard to think of a central
area of analytic philosophy which will not be touched by Jackson's
conclusions.' Tim Crane, Reader in Philosophy, University College
London 'The writing is clear, straightforward, and down to
earth-the usual virtues one expects from Jackson . . . what he has
to say is innovative and valuable . . . the book deals with a large
number of apparently diverse philosophical issues, but it is also
an elegantly unified work. What gives it unity is the
metaphilosophical framework that Jackson works out with great care
and persuasiveness. This is the first serious and sustained work on
the methodology of metaphysics in recent memory. What he says about
the role of conceptual analysis in metaphysics is an important and
timely contribution. . . . It is refreshing and heartening to see a
first-class analytic philosopher doing some serious
metaphilosophical work . . . I think that the book will be greeted
as an important event in philosophical publishing.' Jaegwon Kim,
Professor of Philosophy, Brown University
Meaning (significance) and nature are this book's principal topics.
They seem an odd couple, like raisins and numbers, though they
elide when meanings of a global sort-ideologies and religions, for
example-promote ontologies that subordinate nature. Setting one
against the other makes reality contentious. It signifies workmates
and a coal face to miners, gluons to physicists, prayer and
redemption to priests. Are there many realities, or many
perspectives on one? The answer I prefer is the comprehensive
naturalism anticipated by Aristotle and Spinoza: "natura naturans,
natura naturata." Nature naturing is an array of mutually
conditioning material processes in spacetime. Each structure or
event-storm clouds forming, nature natured-is self-differentiating,
self-stabilizing, and sometimes self-disassembling; each alters or
transforms a pre-existing state of affairs. This surmise
anticipated discoveries and analyses to which neither thinker had
access, though physics and biology confirm their hypothesis beyond
reasonable doubt. Hence the question this book considers: Is
reality divided:nature vrs. lived experience? Or is experience,
with all its meanings and values, the complex expression of natural
processes?
|
|