|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present
Before he had even conceived of the Decline and fall of the Roman
Empire there was another Edward Gibbon, a young expatriate living
in Switzerland and writing in French. In the Essai, a work of
remarkable erudition and energy completed by the age of twenty-one,
Gibbon reflects on the present state of knowledge in
post-Renaissance Europe - what he calls litterature. The first
publication of the Essai since 1761, this critical edition sets
Gibbon's work in its intellectual context. A detailed introduction
examines the biographical, cultural and historical background to
this text: the young writer's perception of European intellectual
life as he observed it from Lausanne, his relation to the
Encyclopedie and the French academies, the fate of erudition, and
the modern organization of learning in books. An extensive
commentary completes this edition, providing invaluable annotation
of each chapter, including the important but little-known sections
on religion that were replaced by Gibbon in the final text. As
current debates revisit the meaning of Enlightenment, readers will
find in this edition of Gibbon's Essai a new approach to the
intellectual networks and tensions that lie at its heart.
Eighteenth-century Epicureanism is often viewed as radical,
anti-religious and politically dangerous. But to what extent does
this simplify the ancient philosophy and underestimate its
significance in Enlightenment writing? Through a pan-European
analysis of Enlightenment centres from Scotland to Russia via the
Netherlands, France and Germany, contributors argue that elements
of classical Epicureanism were appropriated by radical and
conservative writers alike. They move beyond literature and
political theory to examine the application of Epicurean ideas in
domains as diverse as physics, natural law, and the philosophy of
language, drawing on the work of both major figures (Diderot,
Helvetius, Smith and Hume) and of lesser-known but equally
influential thinkers (Johann Jacob Schmauss and Dmitrii Anichkov).
This unique collaboration, bringing together historians,
philosophers, political scientists and literary scholars, provides
rich and varied insights into the different strategic uses of
Epicureanism in the eighteenth century.
This edition includes the letters exchanged between Charles S.
Peirce and the Open Court Publishing Company between 1890 and 1913.
Open Court published more of Peirce's philosophical writings than
any other publisher during his lifetime, and played a critical role
in what little recognition and financial income he received during
these difficult, yet philosophically rich, years. This
correspondence is the basis for much of what is known surrounding
Peirce's publications in The Monist and The Open Court-two of the
publishers most popular forums for philosophical, scientific, and
religious thought-and is therefore referenced heavily in Peirce
editions dealing partly or wholly with his later work, including
The Essential Peirce series and Writings of Charles S. Peirce. The
edition provides for the first time a complete text of this
oft-cited correspondence, with textual apparatus, contextual
annotation, and careful replications of existential graphs and
other complex illustrations. By so doing, this edition sheds
critical light not only on Peirce and Open Court, but also on the
context, relationships, and concepts that influenced the
development of Progressive Era intellectual history and philosophy.
This book reflects the most recent research devoted to a
systematized perspective and a critical (re)construction of
previous theoretical attempts of explaining, justifying and
continuing Kuhn's ingenious hypothesis in arts. Hofstadter, Clignet
and Habermas revealed to be the most engaged scholars in solving
this aesthetic "puzzled-problem". In this context, the structural
similarities between science and arts are attentively evaluated,
thus satisfying an older concern attributed to the historical
Kuhn-Kubler dispute, extensively commented along the pages of this
book. How can we track the matter of rationality and truth in art
and aesthetics, inspired by scientific perspectives? Are artistic
styles similar to scientific paradigms? Are we entitled to pursue
paradigms and masterpieces as rational models in science,
respectively in arts? On what possible grounds can we borrow from
science notions such as progress and predictability, in the study
of the evolution of art and its aesthetic backgrounds? Are the
historical dynamics of science and art affected by political
factors in the same manner? This book will be of interest to
philosophers, but also to historians of science and historians of
art alike in the reassessment it provides of recent debates on
reshaping the art world using Kuhn's "paradigm shift".
The book explores Peirce's non standard thoughts on a synthetic
continuum, topological logics, existential graphs, and relational
semiotics, offering full mathematical developments on these areas.
More precisely, the following new advances are offered: (1) two
extensions of Peirce's existential graphs, to intuitionistic logics
(a new symbol for implication), and other non-classical logics (new
actions on nonplanar surfaces); (2) a complete formalization of
Peirce's continuum, capturing all Peirce's original demands
(genericity, supermultitudeness, reflexivity, modality), thanks to
an inverse ordinally iterated sheaf of real lines; (3) an array of
subformalizations and proofs of Peirce's pragmaticist maxim,
through methods in category theory, HoTT techniques, and modal
logics. The book will be relevant to Peirce scholars,
mathematicians, and philosophers alike, thanks to thorough
assessments of Peirce's mathematical heritage, compact surveys of
the literature, and new perspectives offered through formal and
modern mathematizations of the topics studied.
Most human action has a technical dimension. This book examines
four components of this technical dimension. First, in all actions,
various individual, organizational or institutional agents combine
actional capabilities with tools, institutions, infrastructure and
other elements by means of which they act. Second, the deployment
of capabilities and means is permeated by ethical aspirations and
hesitancies. Third, all domains of action are affected by these
ethical dilemmas. Fourth, the dimensions of the technicity of
action are typical of human life in general, and not just a
regional or culturally specific phenomenon. In this study, an
interdisciplinary approach is adopted to encompass the broad
anthropological scope of this study and combine this bigger picture
with detailed attention to the socio-historical particularities of
action as it plays out in different contexts. Hermeneutics (the
philosophical inquiry into the human phenomena of meaning,
understanding and interpretation) and social science (as the study
of all human affairs) are the two main disciplinary orientations of
this book. This study clarifies the technical dimension of the
entire spectrum of human action ranging from daily routine to the
extreme of violent protest.
Superficially, Wittgenstein and Heidegger seem worlds apart: they
worked in different philosophical traditions, seemed mostly
ignorant of one another's work, and Wittgenstein's terse aphorisms
in plain language could not be farther stylistically from
Heidegger's difficult prose. Nevertheless, Wittgenstein's
Philosophical Investigations and Heidegger's Being and Time share a
number of striking parallels. In particular, this book shows that
both authors manifest a similar concern with authenticity. David
Egan develops this position in three stages. Part One explores the
emphasis both philosophers place on the everyday, and how this
emphasis brings with it a methodological focus on recovering what
we already know rather than advancing novel theses. Part Two argues
that the dynamic of authenticity and inauthenticity in Being and
Time finds homologies in Philosophical Investigations. Here Egan
particularly articulates and defends a conception of authenticity
in Wittgenstein that emphasizes the responsiveness and reciprocity
of play. Part Three considers how both philosophers' conceptions of
authenticity apply reflexively to their own work: each is concerned
not only with the question of what it means to exist authentically
but also with the question of what it means to do philosophy
authentically. For both authors, the problematic of authenticity is
intimately linked to the question of philosophical method.
Soren Kierkegaard's Christian existentialism provides a unique
framework for thinking about the problem of religious pluralism.
This problem arises from the fact that there are lots of different
religions in the world and each of them teaches different things.
Accordingly, it is difficult to know which one, if any, ought to be
believed in as actually being true. Fehir defends his view of
Kierkegaard's understanding of faith and uses it to deal with
common philosophical problems related to pluralism. In the course
of advancing this argument, Kierkegaardian Reflections of the
Problem of Pluralism also engages in interreligious dialogue by
comparing Kierkegaard's views with representatives from Buddhism,
Judaism, and Taoism.
This volume is composed of extended versions of selected papers
presented at an international conference held in June 2011 at Opole
University-the seventh in a series of annual American and European
Values conferences organized by the Institute of Philosophy, Opole
University, Poland. The papers were written independently with no
prior guidelines other than the obvious need to address some aspect
of George Herbert Mead's work. While rooted in careful study of
Mead's original writings and transcribed lectures and the
historical context in which that work was carried out, these papers
have brought that work to bear on contemporary issues in
metaphysics, epistemology, cognitive science, and social and
political philosophy. There is good reason to classify Mead as one
of the original classical American pragmatists (along with Charles
Peirce, William James, and John Dewey) and consequently as a major
figure in American philosophy. Nevertheless his thought has been
marginalized for the most part, at least in academic philosophy. It
is our intention to help recuperate Mead's reputation among a
broader audience by providing a small corpus of significant
contemporary scholarship on some key aspects of his thought.
The seventeenth century witnesses the demise of two core doctrines
in the theory of perception: naive realism about color, sound, and
other sensible qualities and the empirical theory, drawn from
Alhacen and Roger Bacon, which underwrote it. This created a
problem for seventeenth century philosophers: how is that we use
qualities such as color, feel, and sound to locate objects in the
world, even though these qualities are not real? Ejecting such
sensible qualities from the mind-independent world at once makes
for a cleaner ontology, since bodies can now be understood in
purely geometrical terms, and spawns a variety of fascinating
complications for the philosophy of perception. If sensible
qualities are not part of the mind-independent world, just what are
they, and what role, if any, do they play in our cognitive economy?
We seemingly have to use color to visually experience objects. Do
we do so by inferring size, shape, and motion from color? Or is it
a purely automatic operation, accomplished by divine decree? This
volume traces the debate over perceptual experience in early modern
France, covering such figures as Antoine Arnauld, Robert Desgabets,
and Pierre-Sylvain Regis alongside their better-known countrymen
Rene Descartes and Nicolas Malebranche.
Can we prove the necessity of our best physical theories by
rational means, without appeal to experience? This book recounts a
few ingenious attempts to derive physical theories by reason only,
beginning with Descartes' geometric construction of the world, and
finishing with recent derivations of quantum mechanics from natural
axioms. Deductions based on theological, metaphysical, or
transcendental arguments are worth remembering for the ways they
motivated and structured physical theory, even though we would now
criticize their excessive confidence in the power of the mind.
Other deductions more modestly relied on criteria for the
comprehensibility of nature, including forms of measurability,
causality, homogeneity, and correspondence. The central thesis of
this book is that such criteria, when properly applied to idealized
systems, effectively determine some of our most important theories
as well as the mathematical character of the laws of physics. The
relevant arguments are not purely rational, because only experience
can tell us to which extent nature is comprehensible in a given
way. Nor do they block the possibility of ever more varied forms of
comprehensibility. They nonetheless suggest the inevitability of
much of our theoretical physics.
This book investigates a number of central problems in the
philosophy of Charles Peirce grouped around the realism of his
semiotics: the issue of how sign systems are developed and used in
the investigation of reality. Thus, it deals with the precise
character of Peirce's realism; with Peirce's special notion of
propositions as signs which, at the same time, denote and describe
the same object. It deals with diagrams as signs which depict more
or less abstract states-of-affairs, facilitating reasoning about
them; with assertions as public claims about the truth of
propositions. It deals with iconicity in logic, the issue of
self-control in reasoning, dependences between phenomena in their
realist descriptions. A number of chapters deal with applied
semiotics: with biosemiotic sign use among pre-human organisms: the
multimedia combination of pictorial and linguistic information in
human semiotic genres like cartoons, posters, poetry, monuments.
All in all, the book makes a strong case for the actual relevance
of Peirce's realist semiotics.
|
|