|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present
Relativism has dominated many intellectual circles, past and
present, but the twentieth century saw it banished to the fringes
of mainstream analytic philosophy. Of late, however, it is making
something of a comeback within that loosely configured tradition, a
comeback that attempts to capitalize on some important ideas in
foundational semantics. Relativism and Monadic Truth aims not
merely to combat analytic relativism but also to combat the
foundational ideas in semantics that led to its revival. Doing so
requires a proper understanding of the significance of possible
worlds semantics, an examination of the relation between truth and
the flow of time, an account of putatively relevant data from
attitude and speech act reporting, and a careful treatment of
various operators. Throughout, Herman Cappelen and John Hawthorne
contrast relativism with a view according to which the contents of
thought and talk are propositions that instantiate the fundamental
monadic properties of truth simpliciter and falsity simpliciter.
Such propositions, they argue, are the semantic values of sentences
(relative to context), the objects of illocutionary acts, and,
unsurprisingly, the objects of propositional attitudes.
In Phenomenology and Lacan on Schizophrenia, Alphonse De Waelhens
provides a clear summary of Lacan's theory of schizophrenia, as
Lacan derived it from his commentary of Freud's study of the
Memoirs of Schreber. De Waelhens also shows how Lacan's
understanding of the schizophrenic as having a defective relation
to language can also explain four other characteristics of
schizophrenic behavior: the fragmented body image; lack of
realistic evaluation of the world; so-called bisexuality; and
confusion of birth and death. Third, De Waelhens gives a Hegelian
interpretation of the pre-Oedipal experience of the child. He makes
use of Freud's study on his grand-child using a bobbin and later
the words fort-da (away-here), to demonstrate that a transitional
object allows the child to take distance from its attachment to the
mother so that it can start to separate itself from the mother.
Taking distance is, according to De Waelhens, introducing the
Hegelian negative, which is the birth of the subject. Fourth, De
Waelhens gives a dialectic reading of the history of German and
French psychiatry. He shows the epistemological contradictions in
the work of some of the great nineteenth century psychiatrists
relying too exclusively on a biological model of schizophrenia.In
his contribution to this volume, Wilfried Ver Eecke draws several
lessons from evaluating the literature on schizophrenia. He argues
that epistemologically neither a biological nor a psychological
method of reasoning can capture all the factors that can play a
role in the creation of schizophrenia. He relies heavily, but not
exclusively, on the Finnish studies of Tienari, Myrhman, and
Wahlberg and their colleagues to provide statistical evidence that
non-biological factors also play an important role in causing
schizophrenia. He relies heavily, but again not exclusively, on the
study by Karon and VandenBos to demonstrate statistically the
efficiency of psychodynamically inspired therapy of
schizophrenics.Ver Eecke also addresses an apparent inconsistency
in De Waelhens' presentation of Lacan's theory of schizophrenia.
Where De Waelhens seemed to argue at one time that the mother
figure was the crucial figure to explain schizophrenia (leading to
a defective relation to the body) and at another time that it was
the role of the father which was crucial (leading to a defective
relation to language and the symbolic), there Ver Eecke argues that
the defective function of each influences the function of the
other. He then draws a conclusion for the therapy of
schizophrenics: to be helpful a therapist will have to address both
deficiencies. The problem for treating schizophrenics is that
correcting an unconscious deficiency to the body-a deficiency in
the imaginary-requires a totally different kind of intervention
than an attempt to correct a symbolic deficiency-a deficiency in
the paternal function. A correction of the imaginary requires a
kind of maternal mirroring; a correction of the symbolic requires
making a distinction or a prohibition stick. One further difficulty
arises. Psychotherapy uses language in its treatment. However,
language in schizophrenics is deficient. We can therefore expect
that language will be inefficient. This is so unless the therapist
uses language, first, to make a repair at the imaginary level and
only thereafter makes an attempt to make a correction in the
symbolic. In analyzing successful therapeutic techniques reported
by several therapists Ver Eecke discovers that all of them first
try to repair the imaginary before they attempt to make corrections
to the symbolic.
The English philosopher Herbert Spencer (1820 - 1903) was a
colossus of the Victorian age. His works ranked alongside those of
Darwin and Marx in the development of disciplines as wide ranging
as sociology, anthropology, political theory, philosophy and
psychology. In this acclaimed study of Spencer, the first for over
thirty years and now available in paperback, Mark Francis provides
an authoritative and meticulously researched intellectual biography
of this remarkable man that dispels the plethora of misinformation
surrounding Spencer and shines new light on the broader cultural
history of the nineteenth century. In this major study of Spencer,
the first for over thirty years, Mark Francis provides an
authoritative and meticulously researched intellectual biography of
this remarkable man. Using archival material and contemporary
printed sources, Francis creates a fascinating portrait of a human
being whose philosophical and scientific system was a unique
attempt to explain modern life in all its biological, psychological
and sociological forms. Herbert Spencer and the Invention of Modern
Life fills what is perhaps the last big biographical gap in
Victorian history. An exceptional work of scholarship it not only
dispels the plethora of misinformation surrounding Spencer but
shines new light on the broader cultural history of the nineteenth
century. Elegantly written, provocative and rich in insight it will
be required reading for all students of the period.
Paul Guyer is acknowledged as one of the world's foremost Kant
specialists, and he collects here some of his most celebrated
essays from the past decade and a half. The governing theme of the
volume is the role of systematicity in Kant's theoretical and
practical philosophy. Featuring two brand-new papers and an
introduction to orient the reader, Kant's System of Nature and
Freedom will be an essential purchase for anyone working on the
history of philosophy and related areas of ethics, philosophy of
science, and metaphysics.
This book offers a fresh and up-to-date account of the ethical
thought of one of the twentieth century's greatest theologians:
Karl Barth. In it, the author seeks to recover Barth's ethics from
some widespread misunderstandings, and also presents a picture of
it as a whole. Drawing on recently published sources, Dr Biggar
construes the ethics of the Church Dogmatics as it might have been
had Barth lived to complete it. However, The Hastening that Waits
is more than apology and description. For it recommends to
contemporary Christian ethics the theological rigour with which
Barth expounds the good life in terms of the living presence of
God-in-Christ to his creatures; his conception of right human
action as that which is able to hasten in the service of humanity
precisely by waiting prayerfully upon God; and his discriminate
openness to moral wisdom outside the Christian church. Among
particular topics treated are: the concept of human freedom and of
created moral order; moral norms and their relation to individual
vocation; the relative ethical roles of the Bible, the Church,
philosophy, and empirical science; moral character and its
formation; and the problem of war.
Now in a new edition, this volume updates Davidson's exceptional
Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (1984), which set out his
enormously influential philosophy of language. The original volume
remains a central point of reference, and a focus of controversy,
with its impact extending into linguistic theory, philosophy of
mind, and epistemology. Addressing a central question--what it is
for words to mean what they do--and featuring a previously
uncollected, additional essay, this work will appeal to a wide
audience of philosophers, linguists, and psychologists.
Frank Jackson champions the cause of conceptual analysis as central
to philosophical inquiry. In recent years conceptual analysis has
been undervalued and, Jackson suggests, widely misunderstood; he
argues that there is nothing especially mysterious about it and a
whole range of important questions cannot be productively addressed
without it. He anchors his argument in discussion of specific
philosophical issues, starting with the metaphysical doctrine of
physicalism and moving on, via free will, meaning, personal
identity, motion and change, to the philosophy of colour and to
ethics. The significance of different kinds of supervenience
theses, Kripke and Putnam's work in the philosophy of modality and
language, and the role of intuitions about possible cases receive
detailed attention. Jackson concludes with a defence of a version
of analytical descriptivism in ethics. In this way the book not
only offers a methodological programme for philosophy, but also
throws fascinating new light on some much-debated problems and
their interrelations. puffs which may be quoted (please do not edit
without consulting OUP editor): 'This is an outstanding book. It
covers a vast amount of philosophy in a very short space, advances
a number of original and striking positions, and manages to be both
clear and concise in its expositions of other views and forceful in
its criticisms of them. The book offers something new for those
interested in the various individual problems it
discusses-conceptual analysis, the mind-body relation, secondary
qualities, modality, and ethical realism. But unifying these
individual discussions is an ambitious structure which amounts to
an outline of a complete metaphysical system, and an outline of an
epistemology for this metaphysics. It is hard to think of a central
area of analytic philosophy which will not be touched by Jackson's
conclusions.' Tim Crane, Reader in Philosophy, University College
London 'The writing is clear, straightforward, and down to
earth-the usual virtues one expects from Jackson . . . what he has
to say is innovative and valuable . . . the book deals with a large
number of apparently diverse philosophical issues, but it is also
an elegantly unified work. What gives it unity is the
metaphilosophical framework that Jackson works out with great care
and persuasiveness. This is the first serious and sustained work on
the methodology of metaphysics in recent memory. What he says about
the role of conceptual analysis in metaphysics is an important and
timely contribution. . . . It is refreshing and heartening to see a
first-class analytic philosopher doing some serious
metaphilosophical work . . . I think that the book will be greeted
as an important event in philosophical publishing.' Jaegwon Kim,
Professor of Philosophy, Brown University
Meaning (significance) and nature are this book's principal topics.
They seem an odd couple, like raisins and numbers, though they
elide when meanings of a global sort-ideologies and religions, for
example-promote ontologies that subordinate nature. Setting one
against the other makes reality contentious. It signifies workmates
and a coal face to miners, gluons to physicists, prayer and
redemption to priests. Are there many realities, or many
perspectives on one? The answer I prefer is the comprehensive
naturalism anticipated by Aristotle and Spinoza: "natura naturans,
natura naturata." Nature naturing is an array of mutually
conditioning material processes in spacetime. Each structure or
event-storm clouds forming, nature natured-is self-differentiating,
self-stabilizing, and sometimes self-disassembling; each alters or
transforms a pre-existing state of affairs. This surmise
anticipated discoveries and analyses to which neither thinker had
access, though physics and biology confirm their hypothesis beyond
reasonable doubt. Hence the question this book considers: Is
reality divided:nature vrs. lived experience? Or is experience,
with all its meanings and values, the complex expression of natural
processes?
|
You may like...
Anniversary
Scottish Fiddle Orchestra
CD
R276
Discovery Miles 2 760
|