|
Showing 1 - 12 of
12 matches in All Departments
In Life's Values Alan H. Goldman seeks to explain what is of
ultimate value in individual lives. The proposed candidates include
pleasure, happiness, meaning, and well-being. Only the latter is
the all-inclusive category of personal value, and it consists in
the satisfaction of deep rational desires. Since individuals'
rational desires differ, the book cannot dictate what will maximize
your own well-being and what in particular you ought to pursue.
However it can tell you to make your desires rational (that is,
informed and coherent) and it can also explain the nature of these
states that typically enter into well-being: pleasure, happiness,
and meaning being typically partial causes as well as effects of
well-being. All are by-products of satisfying rational desires and
rarely successfully aimed at directly. Pleasure comes in sensory,
intentional, and pure feeling forms, each with an opposite in pain
or distress. Happiness in its primary sense is an emotion, not a
constant state as some philosophers assume, and in secondary senses
a mood (disposition to have an emotion) or temperament (disposition
to be in a mood). Meaning in life is a matter of events in one's
life fitting into intelligible narratives. Events in narratives are
understood teleologically as well as causally, in terms of outcomes
aimed at as well antecedent events. So, in the briefest terms, this
book distinguishes and relates pleasure, happiness, well-being, and
meaning, and relates each to motivation and value.
Alan H. Goldman presents an original and lucid account of the
relationship between philosophy and the novel. In the first part,
on philosophy of novels, he defends theories of literary value and
interpretation. Literary value, the value of literary works as
such, is a species of aesthetic value. Goldman argues that works
have aesthetic value when they simultaneously engage all our mental
capacities: perceptual, cognitive, imaginative, and emotional. This
view contrasts with now prevalent narrower formalist views of
literary value. According to it, cognitive engagement with novels
includes appreciation of their broad themes and the theses these
imply, often moral and hence philosophical theses, which are
therefore part of the novels' literary value. Interpretation
explains elements of works so as to allow readers maximum
appreciation, so as to maximize the literary value of the texts as
written. Once more, Goldman's view contrasts with narrower views of
literary interpretation, especially those which limit it to
uncovering what authors intended. One implication of Goldman's
broader view is the possibility of incompatible but equally
acceptable interpretations, which he explores through a discussion
of rival interpretations of Ernest Hemingway's The Sun Also Rises.
Goldman goes on to test the theory of value by explaining the
immense appeal of good mystery novels in its terms. The second part
of the book, on philosophy in novels, explores themes relating to
moral agency-moral development, motivation, and disintegration-in
Jane Austen's Pride and Prejudice, Mark Twain's Huckleberry Finn,
John Irving's The Cider House Rules, and Joseph Conrad's Nostromo.
By narrating the course of characters' lives, including their inner
lives, over extended periods, these novels allow us to vicariously
experience the characters' moral progressions, positive and
negative, to learn in a more focused way moral truths, as we do
from real life experiences.
Originally published in 1988, this book discusses if moral
knowledge exists, and if so, if it is similar to other forms of
knowledge. This book approaches the issues from both historical and
contemporary perspectives and in order to determine whether there
is a real property of rightness, looks to the ethical theories of
Hobbes, Hume and Kant. This historical analysis leads to a
systematic comparison of three theories of the nature of ethics:
realism, emotivism and coherentism. The nature of coherence is
explained using legal reasoning as a model. Moral reasoning is
compared and contrasted with reasoning both in science and law,
showing how ethics differs from science and empirical disciplines.
Originally published in 1988, this book discusses if moral
knowledge exists, and if so, if it is similar to other forms of
knowledge. This book approaches the issues from both historical and
contemporary perspectives and in order to determine whether there
is a real property of rightness, looks to the ethical theories of
Hobbes, Hume and Kant. This historical analysis leads to a
systematic comparison of three theories of the nature of ethics:
realism, emotivism and coherentism. The nature of coherence is
explained using legal reasoning as a model. Moral reasoning is
compared and contrasted with reasoning both in science and law,
showing how ethics differs from science and empirical disciplines.
Do the reasons we have for acting as we do derive from our concerns
and desires, or are there objective values in the world that we are
rationally required to pursue and protect? Alan Goldman argues for
the internalist or subjectivist view of practical reasons on the
grounds that it is simpler, more unified, and more comprehensible
than the rival objectivist position. He provides a naturalistic
account of practical rationality in terms of coherence within sets
of desires or motivational states, and between motivations,
intentions, and actions. Coherence is defined as the avoidance of
self-defeat, the defeat of one's own deepest concerns. The demand
for coherence underlies both practical and theoretical reason and
derives from the natural aims of belief and action. In clarifying
which desires create reasons, drawing on the literature of
cognitive psychology, Goldman offers conceptual analyses of
desires, emotions, and attitudes. Reasons are seen to derive
ultimately from our deepest occurrent concerns. These concerns
require no reasons themselves but provide reasons for many more
superficial desires.
In defense of this theory, Goldman argues that rational agents need
not be morally motivated or concerned for their narrow
self-interest. Objective values would demand such concern. They
would be independent of our desires but would provide reasons for
us to pursue and protect them. They would require rational agents
to be motivated by them. But, Goldman argues, we are not motivated
in that way, and it makes no sense to demand that our informed and
coherent desires be generally other than they are. We need not
appeal to such objective values in order to explain how our lives
can be good and meaningful.
Reasons from Within will appeal to anyone interested in the nature
of values and reasons, particularly students of philosophy,
psychology, and decision theory.
Alan H. Goldman presents an original and lucid account of the
relationship between philosophy and the novel. In the first part,
on philosophy of novels, he defends theories of literary value and
interpretation. Literary value, the value of literary works as
such, is a species of aesthetic value. Goldman argues that works
have aesthetic value when they simultaneously engage all our mental
capacities: perceptual, cognitive, imaginative, and emotional. This
view contrasts with now prevalent narrower formalist views of
literary value. According to it, cognitive engagement with novels
includes appreciation of their broad themes and the theses these
imply, often moral and hence philosophical theses, which are
therefore part of the novels' literary value. Interpretation
explains elements of works so as to allow readers maximum
appreciation, so as to maximize the literary value of the texts as
written. Once more, Goldman's view contrasts with narrower views of
literary interpretation, especially those which limit it to
uncovering what authors intended. One implication of Goldman's
broader view is the possibility of incompatible but equally
acceptable interpretations, which he explores through a discussion
of rival interpretations of Ernest Hemingway's The Sun Also Rises.
Goldman goes on to test the theory of value by explaining the
immense appeal of good mystery novels in its terms. The second part
of the book, on philosophy in novels, explores themes relating to
moral agency-moral development, motivation, and disintegration-in
Jane Austen's Pride and Prejudice, Mark Twain's Huckleberry Finn,
John Irving's The Cider House Rules, and Joseph Conrad's Nostromo.
By narrating the course of characters' lives, including their inner
lives, over extended periods, these novels allow us to vicariously
experience the characters' moral progressions, positive and
negative, to learn in a more focused way moral truths, as we do
from real life experiences.
In Life's Values Alan H. Goldman seeks to explain what is of
ultimate value in individual lives. The proposed candidates include
pleasure, happiness, meaning, and well-being. Only the latter is
the all-inclusive category of personal value, and it consists in
the satisfaction of deep rational desires. Since individuals'
rational desires differ, the book cannot dictate what will maximize
your own well-being and what in particular you ought to pursue.
However it can tell you to make your desires rational (that is,
informed and coherent) and it can also explain the nature of these
states that typically enter into well-being: pleasure, happiness,
and meaning being typically partial causes as well as effects of
well-being. All are by-products of satisfying rational desires and
rarely successfully aimed at directly. Pleasure comes in sensory,
intentional, and pure feeling forms, each with an opposite in pain
or distress. Happiness in its primary sense is an emotion, not a
constant state as some philosophers assume, and in secondary senses
a mood (disposition to have an emotion) or temperament (disposition
to be in a mood). Meaning in life is a matter of events in one's
life fitting into intelligible narratives. Events in narratives are
understood teleologically as well as causally, in terms of outcomes
aimed at as well antecedent events. So, in the briefest terms, this
book distinguishes and relates pleasure, happiness, well-being, and
meaning, and relates each to motivation and value.
Do the reasons we have for acting as we do derive from our concerns
and desires, or are there objective values in the world that we are
rationally required to pursue and protect? Alan Goldman argues for
the internalist or subjectivist view of practical reasons on the
grounds that it is simpler, more unified, and more comprehensible
than the rival objectivist position. He provides a naturalistic
account of practical rationality in terms of coherence within sets
of desires or motivational states, and between motivations,
intentions, and actions. Coherence is defined as the avoidance of
self-defeat, the defeat of one's own deepest concerns. The demand
for coherence underlies both practical and theoretical reason and
derives from the natural aims of belief and action. In clarifying
which desires create reasons, drawing on the literature of
cognitive psychology, Goldman offers conceptual analyses of
desires, emotions, and attitudes. Reasons are seen to derive
ultimately from our deepest occurrent concerns. These concerns
require no reasons themselves but provide reasons for many more
superficial desires.
In defense of this theory, Goldman argues that rational agents need
not be morally motivated or concerned for their narrow
self-interest. Objective values would demand such concern. They
would be independent of our desires but would provide reasons for
us to pursue and protect them. They would require rational agents
to be motivated by them. But, Goldman argues, we are not motivated
in that way, and it makes no sense to demand that our informed and
coherent desires be generally other than they are. We need not
appeal to such objective values in order to explain how our lives
can be good and meaningful.
Reasons from Within will appeal to anyone interested in the nature
of values and reasons, particularly students of philosophy,
psychology, and decision theory.
Rules proliferate; some are kept with a bureaucratic stringency
bordering on the absurd, while others are manipulated and ignored
in ways that injure our sense of justice. Under what conditions
should we make exceptions to rules, and when should they be
followed despite particular circumstances? The two dominant models
in the literature on rules are the particularist account and that
which sees the application of rules as normative. Taking a position
that falls between these two extremes, Alan Goldman provides a
systematic framework to clarify when we need to follow rules in our
moral, legal and prudential decisions, and when we ought not to do
so. The book distinguishes among various types of rules; it
illuminates concepts such as integrity, self-interest and
self-deception; and finally, it provides an account of ordinary
moral reasoning without rules. This book will be of great interest
to advanced students and professionals working in philosophy, law,
decision theory and the social sciences.
Rules proliferate; some are kept with a bureaucratic stringency bordering on the absurd, while others are manipulated and ignored in ways that injure our sense of justice. Under what conditions should we make exceptions to rules, and when should they be followed despite particular circumstances? The two dominant models in the current literature on rules are the particularist account and that which sees the application of rules as normative. Taking a position that falls between these two extremes, Alan Goldman is the first to provide a systematic framework to clarify when we need to follow rules in our moral, legal, and prudential decisions, and when we ought not to do so.
Through careful consideration of the mutually plausible yet
conflicting arguments on both sides of the issue, Alan Goldman
attempts to derive a morally consistent position on the justice (or
injustice) of reverse discrimination. From a philosophical
framework that appeals to a contractual model of ethics, he
develops principles of rights, compensation, and equal opportunity.
He then applies these principles to the issue at hand, bringing his
conclusions to bear on an evaluation of Affirmative Action programs
as they tend to work in practice. Originally published in 1979. The
Princeton Legacy Library uses the latest print-on-demand technology
to again make available previously out-of-print books from the
distinguished backlist of Princeton University Press. These
editions preserve the original texts of these important books while
presenting them in durable paperback and hardcover editions. The
goal of the Princeton Legacy Library is to vastly increase access
to the rich scholarly heritage found in the thousands of books
published by Princeton University Press since its founding in 1905.
Through careful consideration of the mutually plausible yet
conflicting arguments on both sides of the issue, Alan Goldman
attempts to derive a morally consistent position on the justice (or
injustice) of reverse discrimination. From a philosophical
framework that appeals to a contractual model of ethics, he
develops principles of rights, compensation, and equal opportunity.
He then applies these principles to the issue at hand, bringing his
conclusions to bear on an evaluation of Affirmative Action programs
as they tend to work in practice. Originally published in 1979. The
Princeton Legacy Library uses the latest print-on-demand technology
to again make available previously out-of-print books from the
distinguished backlist of Princeton University Press. These
editions preserve the original texts of these important books while
presenting them in durable paperback and hardcover editions. The
goal of the Princeton Legacy Library is to vastly increase access
to the rich scholarly heritage found in the thousands of books
published by Princeton University Press since its founding in 1905.
|
|