|
Showing 1 - 8 of
8 matches in All Departments
With the growth of interest in later Greek philosophy, the
importance of Plotinus (AD 205-270) as a seminal influence on later
thinkers, both pagan and Christian, is being increasingly
recognized. The Enneads have been readily available for some time,
both in Greek and in English translation, and there is no shortage
of scholarly writing on the Enneads in general, and on particular
aspects of Plotinus' thought. However, apart from Michael
Atkinson's translation and commentary on Ennead V.1 (Clarendon
Press, 1985), there has been no major commentary in English on any
single treatise. Plotinus' Greek is notoriously obscure, and mere
translation often sheds little light. Barrie Fleet's translation
and commentary on Ennead III.6 elucidates the text of a major
treatise in which Plotinus uses the concept of impassivity to shed
light on three questions of importance to Platonists: the nature of
change in the human soul; its analogue in the Sensible World; and
the nature of Matter. Dr Fleet shows how texts of Plato and
Aristotle, and Hellenistic commentaries on them, were central to
the seminars held in Rome under the leadership of Plotinus. This
treatise is the outcome of one such seminar. All Greek quotations
in the commentary are translated into English, and all Greek terms
are either translated or transliterated, making this edition fully
accessible to readers with or without Greek.
SPECIAL PROMOTIONAL OFFER Parmenides Publishing is excited to
announce this, the first volume in their new series; The Enneads Of
Plotinus With Philosophical Commentaries. To celebrate this special
occasion, we are offering a 25% Discount on all orders of Ennead
IV.8 via the Gazelle website. This offer is valid for two months
following publication. Plotinus was much exercised by Plato's
doctrines of the soul. In this treatise, at chapter 1 line 27, he
talks of the divine Plato, who has said in many places in his works
many noble things about the soul and its arrival here, so that we
can hope for some clarity from him. So what does the philosopher
say? It is clear that he does not always speak with sufficient
consistency for us to make out his intentions with any ease. The
issue in this treatise is one that has puzzled students of Plato
from ancient to modern times -- and is indeed a popular topic for
undergraduate essays even today: Why should the philosopher, who
has ascended through a long and painful process of dialectic to
assimilation to the divine, ever descend back into the
body?Plotinus himself is said by Porphyry to have attained such a
state of other-worldly transcendence on at least four occasions
during his lifetime, so this was a very real and personal issue for
him. In this treatise we see him grappling with it.
In "Categories" chapters 7 and 8 Aristotle considers his third and
fourth categories - those of Relative and Quality. Critics of
Aristotle had suggested for each of the non-substance categories
that they could really be reduced to relatives, so it is important
how the category of Relative is defined. Arisotle offers two
definitons, and the second, stricter, one is often cited by his
defenders in order to rule out objections. The second definition of
relative involves the idea of something changing its relationship
through a change undergone by its correlate, not by itself. There
were disagreements as to whether this was genuine change, and
Plotinus discussed whether relatives exist only in the mind,
without being real. The terms used by Aristotle for such
relationships was 'being disposed relatively to something', a term
later borrowed by the Stoics for their fourth category, and perhaps
originating in Plato's Academy. In his discussion of Quality,
Aristotle reports a debate on whether justice admits of degrees, or
whether only the possession of justice does so. Simplicius reports
the further development of this controversy in terms of whether
justice admits a range or latitude (platos). This debate helped to
inspire the medieval idea of latitude of forms, which goes back
much further than is commonly recognised - at least to Plato and
Aristotle.
Chapters 5 and 6 of Aristotle's "Categories" describe his first two
categories, Substance and Quantity. It is usually taken that
Plotinus attacked Aristotle's "Categories", but that Porphyry and
Iamblichus restored it to the curriculum once and for all.
Nonetheless, the introduction to this text stresses how much of the
defence of Aristotle Porphyry was able to draw out of Plotinus'
critical discussion. Simplicius' commentary is our most
comprehensive account of the debate on the validity of Aristotle's
"Categories". One subject discussed by Simplicius in these chapters
is where the differentia of a species (eg the rationality of
humans) fits into the scheme of categories. Another is why
Aristotle elevates the category of Quantity to second place, above
the category of Quality. Further, de Haas shows how Simplicius
distinguishes different kinds of universal order to solve some of
the problems.
Book two of Aristotle's "Physics" is thought by some to be the most
interesting and representative book in the whole of his corpus. It
explains his conception of nature, of physics as opposed to
mathematics, of causation and explanation, of chance and of purpose
in nature. Simplicius, writing in the 6th century AD, is the most
comprehensive of all the commentators. He reports interpretations
of Aristotle from the preceding 800 years by Eudemus, Posidonius,
Porphyry and Syranius. His accounts of the various definitions of
nature and of chance are highly useful, are as his analyses of
Aristotle's technical terms, per accidens and privation. He often
carries out the project, which Aristotle himself proposed but never
undertook, of putting Aristotle's scientific explanations into
syllogistic form.
Book 2 of the "Physics" is arguably the best introduction to
Aristotle's ideas, as well as being the most interesting and
representative book in the whole of his corpus. It defines nature
and distinguishes natural science from mathematics. It introduces
the seminal idea of four causes, or four modes of explanation. It
defines chance, but rejects a theory of chance and natural
selection in favour of purpose in nature. Simplicius, writing in
the sixth century AD, adds his own considerable contribution to
this work. Seeing Aristotle's God as a Creator, he discusses how
nature relates to soul, adds Stoic and Neoplatonist causes to
Aristotle's list of four, and questions the likeness of cause to
effect. He discusses missing a great evil or a great good by a
hairsbreadth and considers whether animals act from reason or
natural instinct. He also preserves a Posidonian discussion of
mathematical astronomy.
Chapters 5 and 6 of Aristotle's Categories describe his first two
categories, Substance and Quantity. It is usually taken that
Plotinus attacked Aristotle's Categories, but that Porphyry and
Iamblichus restored it to the curriculum once and for all.
Nonetheless, the introduction to this text stresses how much of the
defence of Aristotle Porphyry was able to draw out of Plotinus'
critical discussion. Simplicius' commentary is our most
comprehensive account of the debate on the validity of Aristotle's
Categories. One subject discussed by Simplicius in these chapters
is where the differentia of a species (eg the rationality of
humans) fits into the scheme of categories. Another is why
Aristotle elevates the category of Quantity to second place, above
the category of Quality. Further, de Haas shows how Simplicius
distinguishes different kinds of universal order to solve some of
the problems.
In "Categories" chapters 7 and 8 Aristotle considers his third and
fourth categories - those of Relative and Quality. Critics of
Aristotle had suggested for each of the non-substance categories
that they could really be reduced to relatives, so it is important
how the category of Relative is defined. Aristotle offers two
definitions, and the second, stricter, one is often cited by his
defenders in order to rule out objections. The second definition of
relative involves the idea of something changing its relationship
through a change undergone by its correlate, not by itself. There
were disagreements as to whether this was genuine change, and
Plotinus discussed whether relatives exist only in the mind,
without being real. The terms used by Aristotle for such
relationships was 'being disposed relatively to something', a term
later borrowed by the Stoics for their fourth category, and perhaps
originating in Plato's Academy. In his discussion of Quality,
Aristotle reports a debate on whether justice admits of degrees, or
whether only the possession of justice does so. Simplicius reports
the further development of this controversy in terms of whether
justice admits a range or latitude (platos). This debate helped to
inspire the medieval idea of latitude of forms, which goes back
much further than is commonly recognised - at least to Plato and
Aristotle.
|
|