|
Showing 1 - 17 of
17 matches in All Departments
In medicine the understanding and interpretation of the complex
reality of illness currently refers either to an organismic
approach that focuses on the physical or to a 'holistic' approach
that takes into account the patient's human sociocultural
involvement. Yet as the papers of this collection show, the
suffering human person refers ultimately to his/her existential
sphere. Hence, praxis is supplemented by still other perspectives
for valuation and interpretation: ethical, spiritual, and
religious. Can medicine ignore these considerations or push them to
the side as being subjective and arbitrary?
Phenomenology/philosophy-of-life recognizes all of the above
approaches to be essential facets of the Human Condition
(Tymieniecka). This approach holds that all the facets of the Human
Condition have equal objectivity and legitimacy. It completes the
accepted medical outlook and points the way toward a new medical
humanism'.
Mathematics is often considered as a body of knowledge that is
essen tially independent of linguistic formulations, in the sense
that, once the content of this knowledge has been grasped, there
remains only the problem of professional ability, that of clearly
formulating and correctly proving it. However, the question is not
so simple, and P. Weingartner's paper (Language and
Coding-Dependency of Results in Logic and Mathe matics) deals with
some results in logic and mathematics which reveal that certain
notions are in general not invariant with respect to different
choices of language and of coding processes. Five example are
given: 1) The validity of axioms and rules of classical
propositional logic depend on the interpretation of sentential
variables; 2) The language dependency of verisimilitude; 3) The
proof of the weak and strong anti inductivist theorems in Popper's
theory of inductive support is not invariant with respect to
limitative criteria put on classical logic; 4) The
language-dependency of the concept of provability; 5) The language
dependency of the existence of ungrounded and paradoxical sentences
(in the sense of Kripke). The requirements of logical rigour and
consistency are not the only criteria for the acceptance and
appreciation of mathematical proposi tions and theories."
Logic has attained in our century a development incomparably
greater than in any past age of its long history, and this has led
to such an enrichment and proliferation of its aspects, that the
problem of some kind of unified recom prehension of this discipline
seems nowadays unavoidable. This splitting into several subdomains
is the natural consequence of the fact that Logic has intended to
adopt in our century the status of a science. This always implies
that the general optics, under which a certain set of problems used
to be con sidered, breaks into a lot of specialized sectors of
inquiry, each of them being characterized by the introduction of
specific viewpoints and of technical tools of its own. The first
impression, that often accompanies the creation of one of such
specialized branches in a diSCipline, is that one has succeeded in
isolating the 'scientific core' of it, by restricting the somehow
vague and redundant generality of its original 'philosophical'
configuration. But, after a while, it appears that some of the
discarded aspects are indeed important and a new specialized domain
of investigation is created to explore them. By follOwing this
procedure, one finally finds himself confronted with such a variety
of independent fields of research, that one wonders whether the
fact of labelling them under a common denomination be nothing but
the contingent effect of a pure historical tradition."
The two volumes to which this is apreface consist of the
Proceedings of the Second International Conference on History and
Philosophy of Science. The Conference was organized by the Joint
Commission of the International Union of History and Philosophy of
Science (IUHPS) under the auspices of the IUHPS, the Italian
Society for Logic and Philosophy of Science, and the Domus
Galilaeana of Pisa, headed by Professor Vincenzo Cappelletti. Domus
Galilaeana also served as the host institution, with some help from
the University of Pisa. The Conference took place in Pisa, Italy,
on September 4-8, 1978. The editors of these two volumes of the
Proceedings of the Pisa Conference acknowledge with gratitude the
help by the different sponsoring organizations, and in the first
place that by both Divisions of the IUHPS, which made the
Conference possible. A special recognition is due to Professor
Evandro Agazzi, President of the Italian Society for Logic and
Philosophy of Science, who was co opted as an additional member of
the Organizing Committee. This committee was otherwise identical
with the Joint Commission, whose members were initially John
Murdoch, John North, Arpad Szab6, Robert Butts, Jaakko Hintikka,
and Vadim Sadovsky. Later, Erwin Hiebert and Lubos Novy were
appointed as additional members."
The two volumes to which this is a preface consist of the
Proceedings of the Second International Conference on History and
Philosophy of Science. The Conference was organized by the Joint
Commission of the International Union of History and Philosophy of
Science (IUHPS) of the IUHPS, the Italian Society for Logic and
under the auspices Philosophy of Science, and the Domus Galilaeana
of Pisa, headed by Professor Vincenzo Cappelletti. Domus GaIilaeana
also served as the host institution, with some help from the
University of Pisa. The Conference took place in Pisa, Italy, on
September 4-8, 1978. The editors of these two volumes of the
Proceedings of the Pisa Conference acknowledge with gratitude the
help by the different sponsoring organizations, and in the first
place that by both, Divisions of the IUHPS, which made the
Conference possible.' A special recognition is due to Professor
Evandro Agazzi, President of the Italian Society for Logic and
Philosophy of Science, who was co opted as an additional member of
the Organizing Committee. This committee was otherwise identical
with the Joint Commission, whose members were initially John
Murdoch, John North, Arpad Szab6, Robert Butts, Jaakko Hintikka,
and Vadim Sadovsky. Later, Erwin Hiebert and Lubos Novy were
appointed as additional members."
Probability has become one of the most characteristic con cepts of
modern culture, and a 'probabilistic way of thinking' may be said
to have penetrated almost every sector of our in tellectual life.
However it would be difficult to determine an explicit list of
'positive' features, to be proposed as identifica tion marks of
this way of thinking. One would rather say that it is characterized
by certain 'negative' features, i. e. by certain at titudes which
appear to be the negation of well established tra ditional
assumptions, conceptual frameworks, world outlooks and the like. It
is because of this opposition to tradition that the probabilistic
approach is perceived as expressing a 'modern' in tellectual style.
As an example one could mention the widespread diffidence in
philosophy with respect to self -contained systems claiming to
express apodictic truths, instead of which much weaker pretensions
are preferred, that express 'probable' interpretations of reality,
of history, of man (the hermeneutic trend). An ana logous example
is represented by the interest devoted to the study of different
patterns of 'argumentation', dealing wiht reasonings which rely not
so much on the truth of the premisses and stringent formal logic
links, but on a display of contextual conditions (depending on the
audience, and on accepted stan dards, judgements, and values),
which render the premisses and the conclusions more 'probable' (the
new rhetoric)."
The topic to which this book is devoted is reductionism, and not
reduction. The difference in the adoption of these two
denominations is not, contrary to what might appear at first sight,
just a matter of preference between a more abstract (reductionism)
or a more concrete (reduction) terminology for indicating the same
sUbject matter. In fact, the difference is that between a
philosophical doctrine (or, perhaps, simply a philosophical tenet
or claim) and a scientific procedure. Of course, this does not mean
that these two fields are separated; they are only distinct, and
this already means that they are also likely to be interrelated.
However it is useful to consider them separately, if at least to
better understand how and why they are interconnected. Just to give
a first example of difference, we can remark that a philosophical
doctrine is something which makes a claim and, as such, invites
controversy and should, in a way, be challenged. A scientific
procedure, on the other hand, is something which concretely exists,
and as such must be first of all described, interpreted,
understood, defined precisely and analyzed critically; this work
may well lead to uncovering limitations of this procedure, or of
certain ways of conceiving or defining it, but it does not lead to
really challenging it.
Observability and Scientific Realism It is commonly thought that
the birth of modern natural science was made possible by an
intellectual shift from a mainly abstract and specuJative
conception of the world to a carefully elaborated image based on
observations. There is some grain of truth in this claim, but this
grain depends very much on what one takes observation to be. In the
philosophy of science of our century, observation has been
practically equated with sense perception. This is understandable
if we think of the attitude of radical empiricism that inspired
Ernst Mach and the philosophers of the Vienna Circle, who
powerfully influenced our century's philosophy of science. However,
this was not the atti tude of the f ounders of modern science:
Galileo, f or example, expressed in a f amous passage of the
Assayer the conviction that perceptual features of the world are
merely subjective, and are produced in the 'anima!' by the motion
and impacts of unobservable particles that are endowed uniquely
with mathematically expressible properties, and which are therefore
the real features of the world. Moreover, on other occasions, when
defending the Copernican theory, he explicitly remarked that in
admitting that the Sun is static and the Earth turns on its own
axis, 'reason must do violence to the sense' , and that it is
thanks to this violence that one can know the tme constitution of
the universe.
The topic to which this book is devoted is reductionism, and not
reduction. The difference in the adoption of these two
denominations is not, contrary to what might appear at first sight,
just a matter of preference between a more abstract (reductionism)
or a more concrete (reduction) terminology for indicating the same
sUbject matter. In fact, the difference is that between a
philosophical doctrine (or, perhaps, simply a philosophical tenet
or claim) and a scientific procedure. Of course, this does not mean
that these two fields are separated; they are only distinct, and
this already means that they are also likely to be interrelated.
However it is useful to consider them separately, if at least to
better understand how and why they are interconnected. Just to give
a first example of difference, we can remark that a philosophical
doctrine is something which makes a claim and, as such, invites
controversy and should, in a way, be challenged. A scientific
procedure, on the other hand, is something which concretely exists,
and as such must be first of all described, interpreted,
understood, defined precisely and analyzed critically; this work
may well lead to uncovering limitations of this procedure, or of
certain ways of conceiving or defining it, but it does not lead to
really challenging it.
In medicine the understanding and interpretation of the complex
reality of illness currently refers either to an organismic
approach that focuses on the physical or to a 'holistic' approach
that takes into account the patient's human sociocultural
involvement. Yet as the papers of this collection show, the
suffering human person refers ultimately to his/her existential
sphere. Hence, praxis is supplemented by still other perspectives
for valuation and interpretation: ethical, spiritual, and
religious. Can medicine ignore these considerations or push them to
the side as being subjective and arbitrary?
Phenomenology/philosophy-of-life recognizes all of the above
approaches to be essential facets of the Human Condition
(Tymieniecka). This approach holds that all the facets of the Human
Condition have equal objectivity and legitimacy. It completes the
accepted medical outlook and points the way toward a new medical
humanism'.
It has often been noted that a kind of double dynamics char-
terizes the development of science. On the one hand the progress in
every discipline appears as the consequence of an increasing
specialization, implying the restriction of the inquiry to very
partial fields or aspects of a given domain. On the other hand, an
opposite (but one might better say a complementary) trend points
towards the construction of theoretical frameworks of great ge-
rality, the aim of which seems to correspond not so much to the
need of providing "explanations" for the details accumulated
through partial investigation, as to the desire of attaining an -
rizon of global comprehension of the whole field. This intell- tual
dialectics is perceivable in every discipline, from mathe- tics, to
physics, to biology, to history, to economics, to sociology, and it
is not difficult to recognize there the presence of the two main
attitudes according to which human beings try to make
"intelligible" the world surrounding them (including themselves),
attitudes which are sometimes called analysis and synthesis. They
correspond respectively to the spontaneous inclination which pushes
us to try to understand things by seeing "how they are made", in
the sense of "looking into them" and breaking them into their
constitutive parts, or rather to encompass things in a global
picture, where they are accounted for as occupying a place, or
playing a role, which are understandable from the point of view of
the whole.
Mathematics is often considered as a body of knowledge that is
essen tially independent of linguistic formulations, in the sense
that, once the content of this knowledge has been grasped, there
remains only the problem of professional ability, that of clearly
formulating and correctly proving it. However, the question is not
so simple, and P. Weingartner's paper (Language and
Coding-Dependency of Results in Logic and Mathe matics) deals with
some results in logic and mathematics which reveal that certain
notions are in general not invariant with respect to different
choices of language and of coding processes. Five example are
given: 1) The validity of axioms and rules of classical
propositional logic depend on the interpretation of sentential
variables; 2) The language dependency of verisimilitude; 3) The
proof of the weak and strong anti inductivist theorems in Popper's
theory of inductive support is not invariant with respect to
limitative criteria put on classical logic; 4) The
language-dependency of the concept of provability; 5) The language
dependency of the existence of ungrounded and paradoxical sentences
(in the sense of Kripke). The requirements of logical rigour and
consistency are not the only criteria for the acceptance and
appreciation of mathematical proposi tions and theories.
Logic has attained in our century a development incomparably
greater than in any past age of its long history, and this has led
to such an enrichment and proliferation of its aspects, that the
problem of some kind of unified recom prehension of this discipline
seems nowadays unavoidable. This splitting into several subdomains
is the natural consequence of the fact that Logic has intended to
adopt in our century the status of a science. This always implies
that the general optics, under which a certain set of problems used
to be con sidered, breaks into a lot of specialized sectors of
inquiry, each of them being characterized by the introduction of
specific viewpoints and of technical tools of its own. The first
impression, that often accompanies the creation of one of such
specialized branches in a diSCipline, is that one has succeeded in
isolating the 'scientific core' of it, by restricting the somehow
vague and redundant generality of its original 'philosophical'
configuration. But, after a while, it appears that some of the
discarded aspects are indeed important and a new specialized domain
of investigation is created to explore them. By follOwing this
procedure, one finally finds himself confronted with such a variety
of independent fields of research, that one wonders whether the
fact of labelling them under a common denomination be nothing but
the contingent effect of a pure historical tradition."
Probability has become one of the most characteristic con cepts of
modern culture, and a 'probabilistic way of thinking' may be said
to have penetrated almost every sector of our in tellectual life.
However it would be difficult to determine an explicit list of
'positive' features, to be proposed as identifica tion marks of
this way of thinking. One would rather say that it is characterized
by certain 'negative' features, i. e. by certain at titudes which
appear to be the negation of well established tra ditional
assumptions, conceptual frameworks, world outlooks and the like. It
is because of this opposition to tradition that the probabilistic
approach is perceived as expressing a 'modern' in tellectual style.
As an example one could mention the widespread diffidence in
philosophy with respect to self -contained systems claiming to
express apodictic truths, instead of which much weaker pretensions
are preferred, that express 'probable' interpretations of reality,
of history, of man (the hermeneutic trend). An ana logous example
is represented by the interest devoted to the study of different
patterns of 'argumentation', dealing wiht reasonings which rely not
so much on the truth of the premisses and stringent formal logic
links, but on a display of contextual conditions (depending on the
audience, and on accepted stan dards, judgements, and values),
which render the premisses and the conclusions more 'probable' (the
new rhetoric)."
The two volumes to which this is a preface consist of the
Proceedings of the Second International Conference on History and
Philosophy of Science. The Conference was organized by the Joint
Commission of the International Union of History and Philosophy of
Science (IUHPS) of the IUHPS, the Italian Society for Logic and
under the auspices Philosophy of Science, and the Domus Galilaeana
of Pisa, headed by Professor Vincenzo Cappelletti. Domus GaIilaeana
also served as the host institution, with some help from the
University of Pisa. The Conference took place in Pisa, Italy, on
September 4-8, 1978. The editors of these two volumes of the
Proceedings of the Pisa Conference acknowledge with gratitude the
help by the different sponsoring organizations, and in the first
place that by both, Divisions of the IUHPS, which made the
Conference possible.' A special recognition is due to Professor
Evandro Agazzi, President of the Italian Society for Logic and
Philosophy of Science, who was co opted as an additional member of
the Organizing Committee. This committee was otherwise identical
with the Joint Commission, whose members were initially John
Murdoch, John North, Arpad Szab6, Robert Butts, Jaakko Hintikka,
and Vadim Sadovsky. Later, Erwin Hiebert and Lubos Novy were
appointed as additional members."
The two volumes to which this is apreface consist of the
Proceedings of the Second International Conference on History and
Philosophy of Science. The Conference was organized by the Joint
Commission of the International Union of History and Philosophy of
Science (IUHPS) under the auspices of the IUHPS, the Italian
Society for Logic and Philosophy of Science, and the Domus
Galilaeana of Pisa, headed by Professor Vincenzo Cappelletti. Domus
Galilaeana also served as the host institution, with some help from
the University of Pisa. The Conference took place in Pisa, Italy,
on September 4-8, 1978. The editors of these two volumes of the
Proceedings of the Pisa Conference acknowledge with gratitude the
help by the different sponsoring organizations, and in the first
place that by both Divisions of the IUHPS, which made the
Conference possible. A special recognition is due to Professor
Evandro Agazzi, President of the Italian Society for Logic and
Philosophy of Science, who was co opted as an additional member of
the Organizing Committee. This committee was otherwise identical
with the Joint Commission, whose members were initially John
Murdoch, John North, Arpad Szab6, Robert Butts, Jaakko Hintikka,
and Vadim Sadovsky. Later, Erwin Hiebert and Lubos Novy were
appointed as additional members."
Observability and Scientific Realism It is commonly thought that
the birth of modern natural science was made possible by an
intellectual shift from a mainly abstract and specuJative
conception of the world to a carefully elaborated image based on
observations. There is some grain of truth in this claim, but this
grain depends very much on what one takes observation to be. In the
philosophy of science of our century, observation has been
practically equated with sense perception. This is understandable
if we think of the attitude of radical empiricism that inspired
Ernst Mach and the philosophers of the Vienna Circle, who
powerfully influenced our century's philosophy of science. However,
this was not the atti tude of the f ounders of modern science:
Galileo, f or example, expressed in a f amous passage of the
Assayer the conviction that perceptual features of the world are
merely subjective, and are produced in the 'anima!' by the motion
and impacts of unobservable particles that are endowed uniquely
with mathematically expressible properties, and which are therefore
the real features of the world. Moreover, on other occasions, when
defending the Copernican theory, he explicitly remarked that in
admitting that the Sun is static and the Earth turns on its own
axis, 'reason must do violence to the sense' , and that it is
thanks to this violence that one can know the tme constitution of
the universe.
|
|