|
Showing 1 - 8 of
8 matches in All Departments
This collection deals with utopias in the Greek and Roman worlds.
Plato is the first and foremost name that comes to mind and,
accordingly, 3 chapters (J. Annas; D. El Murr; A. Hazistavrou) are
devoted to his various approaches to utopia in the Republic,
Timaeus and Laws. But this volume's central vocation and
originality comes from our taking on that theme in many other
philosophical authors and literary genres. The philosophers include
Aristotle (Ch. Horn) but also Cynics (S. Husson), Stoics (G.
Reydams-Schils) and Cicero (S. McConnell). Other literary genres
include comedic works from Aristophanes up to Lucian (G. Sissa; S.
Kidd; N.I. Kuin) and history from Herodotus up to Diodorus Siculus
(T. Lockwood; C. Atack; I. Sulimani). A last comparative chapter is
devoted to utopias in Ancient China (D. Engels).
While the field of classics has informed and influenced the early
developments of the field of psychology, these two disciplines
presently enjoy fewer fruitful cross-fertilizations than one would
expect. This book shows how the study of classics can help
psychologists anchor their scientific findings in a historical,
literary and philosophical framework, while insights of
contemporary psychology offer new hermeneutic methods and
explanations to classicists. This book is the first to date to
offer a wide-ranging overview of the possibilities of marrying
contemporary trends in psychology and classical studies. Advocating
a critical dialogue between both disciplines, it offers novel
reflections on psychotherapy, ancient philosophy, social
psychology, literature and its theory, historiography,
psychoanalysis, tragedy, the philosophy of mind, linguistics and
reception. With twenty contributions by specialists in different
fields, it promotes the combination of classical and psychological
perspectives, and demonstrates the methods and rewards of such an
endeavour through concrete case studies. This pioneering book is
thus intended for all readers who seek inspiration for their
readings, research, or therapeutic practice.
Proclus' "On the Existence of Evils" is not a commentary, but helps
to compensate for the dearth of Neoplatonist ethical commentaries.
The central question addressed in the work is: how can there be
evil in a providential world? Neoplatonists agree that it cannot be
caused by higher and worthier beings. Plotinus had said that evil
is matter, which, unlike Aristotle, he collapsed into mere
privation or lack, thus reducing its reality. He also protected
higher causes from responsibility by saying that evil may result
from a combination of goods. Proclus objects: evil is real, and not
a privation. Rather, it is a parasite feeding off good. Parasites
have no proper cause, and higher beings are thus vindicated as
being the causes only of the good off which evil feeds.
In this treatise Proclus discusses ten problems on providence and
fate, foreknowledge of the future, human responsibility, evil and
punishment (or seemingly absence of punishment), social and
individual responsibility for evil, and the unequal fate of
different animals. These problems, he admits, had been discussed a
thousand times in and outside philosophical schools. Yet, as he put
it: we too have to discuss them, not because we imagine that the
philosophers before us have said anything valuable, but because our
soul desires 'to speak and hear about these problems and wants to
turn to itself and to discuss as it were with itself and is not
willing to take arguments about these issues only from authorities
outside'. Proclus exhorts his readers: we are to use his treatise
as an opportunity to investigate these problems for ourselves 'in
the secret recess of our soul' and 'exercise ourselves in the
solutions of problems'. In fact, it makes no difference whether
what we discuss has been said before by philosophers, so long as we
express what corresponds to our own views. This exhortation may be
the best presentation of the translation of this wonderful treatise
from late antiquity.
While the field of classics has informed and influenced the early
developments of the field of psychology, these two disciplines
presently enjoy fewer fruitful cross-fertilizations than one would
expect. This book shows how the study of classics can help
psychologists anchor their scientific findings in a historical,
literary and philosophical framework, while insights of
contemporary psychology offer new hermeneutic methods and
explanations to classicists. This book is the first to date to
offer a wide-ranging overview of the possibilities of marrying
contemporary trends in psychology and classical studies. Advocating
a critical dialogue between both disciplines, it offers novel
reflections on psychotherapy, ancient philosophy, social
psychology, literature and its theory, historiography,
psychoanalysis, tragedy, the philosophy of mind, linguistics and
reception. With twenty contributions by specialists in different
fields, it promotes the combination of classical and psychological
perspectives, and demonstrates the methods and rewards of such an
endeavour through concrete case studies. This pioneering book is
thus intended for all readers who seek inspiration for their
readings, research, or therapeutic practice.
'The universe is, as it were, one machine, wherein the celestial
spheres are analogous to the interlocking wheels and the particular
beings are like the things moved by the wheels, and all events are
determined by an inescapable necessity. To speak of free choice or
self determination is only an illusion we human beings cherish.'
Thus writes Theodore the engineer to his old friend Proclus, one of
the last major Classical philosophers. Proclus' reply is one of the
most remarkable discussions on fate, providence and free choice in
Late Antiquity. It continues a long debate that had started with
the first polemics of the Platonists against the Stoic doctrine of
determinism. How can there be a place for free choice and moral
responsibility in a world governed by an unalterable fate? Proclus
discusses ten problems on providence and fate, foreknowledge of the
future, human responsibility, evil and punishment (or seemingly
absence of punishment), social and individual responsibility for
evil, and the unequal fate of different animals. Until now, despite
its great interest, Proclus' treatise has not received the
attention it deserves, probably because its text is not very
accessible to the modern reader. It has survived only in a Latin
medieval translation and in some extensive Byzantine Greek
extracts. This first English translation, based on a
retro-conversion that works out what the original Greek must have
been, brings the arguments he formulates again to the fore.
Proclus' On the Existence of Evils is not a commentary, but helps
to compensate for the dearth of Neoplatonist ethical commentaries.
The central question addressed in the work is: how can there be
evil in a providential world? Neoplatonists agree that it cannot be
caused by higher and worthier beings. Plotinus had said that evil
is matter, which, unlike Aristotle, he collapsed into mere
privation or lack, thus reducing its reality. He also protected
higher causes from responsibility by saying that evil may result
from a combination of goods. Proclus objects: evil is real, and not
a privation. Rather, it is a parasite feeding off good. Parasites
have no proper cause, and higher beings are thus vindicated as
being the causes only of the good off which evil feeds.
|
|