|
Showing 1 - 25 of
25 matches in All Departments
The present volume collects some of the talks given at the Bertrand
Russell Colloquium on Exact Philosophy, attached to the McGill
University Foundations and Philosophy of Science Unit. It also
includes a paper, on Bertrand Russell's method of philosophizing,
read at the memorial symposium held at Sir Gorge Williams
University shortly after the philosopher's death. All the papers
appear here for the first time. Unlike many a philosophy of science
anthology, this one is not center ed on the philosophy of physics.
In fact the papers deal with conceptual and, in particular,
philosophical problems that pop up in almost every one of the
provinces of the vast territory constituted by the foundations,
meth odology and philosophy of science. A couple of border
territories which are in the process of being infiltrated have been
added for good measure. The inclusion of papers in the philosophy
of formal science and in the philosophies of physics and of
biology, in a volume belonging to a series devoted to the
philosophy and methodology of the social and behavioral sciences,
should raise no eyebrows. Because the sciences of man make use of
logic and mathematics, they are interested in questions such as
whether the formal sciences have anything to do with reality
(rather than with our theories about reality) and whether or not
logic has kept up with the practice of mathematicians. These two
problems are tackled in Part II, on the philosophy of formal
science."
This book deals with some of the current issues in the philosophy,
methodology and foundations of physics. Some such problems are: -
Do mathematical formalisms interpret themselves or is it necessary
to adjoin them interpretation assumptions, and if so how are these
as sumptions to be framed? - What are physical theories about:
physical systems or laboratory operations or both or neither? - How
are the basic concepts of a theory to be introduced: by ref erence
to measurements or by explicit definition or axiomatically? - What
is the use ofaxiomatics in physics? - How are the various physical
theories inter-related: like Chinese boxes or in more complex ways?
- What is the role of analogy in the construction and in the inter
pretation of physical theories? In particular, are classical
analogues like those of particle and wave indispensable in quantum
theories? - What is the role of the apparatus in quantum phenomena
and what is the place of measurement theory in quantum mechanics? -
How does a theory face experiment: single-handed or with the help
of further theories? These and several other questions of the kind
are met with by the research physicist, the physics teacher and the
physics student in their everyday work. If dodged they will recur.
And a wrong answer to them may obscure the understanding of what
has been achieved and may even hamper further advancement.
Philosophy, methodology and foundations, like rose bushes, are
enjoyable when cultivated but become ugly and thorny when
neglected."
The purpose of this Introduction is to sketch our approach to the
study of value, morality and action, and to show the place we
assign it in the system of human knowledge. 1. VALUE, MORALITY AND
ACTION: FACT, THEORY, AND METATHEORY We take it that all animals
evaluate some things and some processes, and that some of them
learn the social behavior patterns we call 'moral principles', and
even act according to them at least some of the time. An animal
incapable of evaluating anything would be very short-lived; and a
social animal that did not observe the accepted social behavior
patterns would be punished. These are facts about values, morals
and behavior patterns: they are incorporated into the bodies of
animals or the structure of social groups. We distinguish then the
facts of valuation, morality and action from the study of such
facts. This study can be scientific, philosophic or both. wayan
animal evaluates environmental A zoologist may investigate the or
internal stimuli; a social psychologist may examine the way
children learn, or fail to learn, certain values and norms when
placed in certain environments. And a philosopher may study such
descriptive or explan atory studies, with a view to evaluating
valuations, moral norms, or behavior patterns; he may analyze the
very concepts of value, morals and action, as well as their
cognates; or he may criticize or reconstruct value beliefs, moral
norms and action plans."
The aims of this Introduction are to characterize the philosophy of
science and technology, henceforth PS & T, to locate it on the
map ofiearning, and to propose criteria for evaluating work in this
field. 1. THE CHASM BETWEEN S & T AND THE HUMANITIES It has
become commonplace to note that contemporary culture is split into
two unrelated fields: science and the rest, to deplore this split -
and to do is some truth in the two cultures thesis, and even
nothing about it. There greater truth in the statement that there
are literally thousands of fields of knowledge, each of them
cultivated by specialists who are in most cases indifferent to what
happens in the other fields. But it is equally true that all fields
of knowledge are united, though in some cases by weak links,
forming the system of human knowledge. Because of these links, what
advances, remains stagnant, or declines, is the entire system of S
& T. Throughout this book we shall distinguish the main fields
of scientific and technological knowledge while at the same time
noting the links that unite them.
In this Introduction we shall state the business of both
descriptive and normative epistemology, and shall locate them in
the map oflearning. This must be done because epistemology has been
pronounced dead, and methodology nonexisting; and because, when
acknowledged at all, they are often misplaced. 1. DESCRIPTIVE
EPISTEMOLOGY The following problems are typical of classical
epistemology: (i) What can we know? (ii) How do we know? (iii)
What, if anything, does the subject contribute to his knowledge?
(iv) What is truth? (v) How can we recognize truth? (vi) What is
probable knowledge as opposed to certain knowledge? (vii) Is there
a priori knowledge, and if so of what? (viii) How are knowledge and
action related? (ix) How are knowledge and language related? (x)
What is the status of concepts and propositions? In some guise or
other all of these problems are still with us. To be sure, if
construed as a demand for an inventory of knowledge the first
problem is not a philosophical one any more than the question 'What
is there?'. But it is a genuine philosophical problem if construed
thus: 'What kinds of object are knowable-and which ones are not?'
However, it is doubtful that philosophy can offer a correct answer
to this problem without the help of science and technology. For
example, only these disciplines can tell us whether man can know
not only phenomena (appearances) but also noumena (things in
themselves or self-existing objects).
The word 'materialism' is ambiguous: it designates a moral doc
trine as well as a philosophy and, indeed, an entire world view.
Moral materialism is identical with hedonism, or the doctrine that
humans should pursue only their own pleasure. Philosophical ma
terialismis the view that the real worId is composed exclusively of
material things. The two doctrines are logically independent:
hedonism is consistent with immaterialism, and materialism is
compatible with high minded morals. We shall be concerned ex
c1usively with philosophical materialism. And we shall not confuse
it with realism, or the epistemological doctrine that knowIedge, or
at any rate scientific knowledge, attempts to represent reality.
Philosophical materialism is not a recent fad and it is not a solid
block: it is as old as philosophy and it has gone through six quite
different stages. The first was ancient materialism, centered
around Greek and Indian atomism. The second was the revival of the
first during the 17th century. The third was 18th century ma
terialism, partly derived from one side of Descartes' ambiguous
legacy. The fourth was the mid-19th century "scientific" material
ism, which flourished mainly in Germany and England, and was tied
to the upsurge of chemistry and biology. The fifth was dialec tical
and historical materialism, which accompanied the consolida tion of
the socialist ideology. And the sixth or current stage, evolved
mainly by Australian and American philosophers, is aca demic and
nonpartisan but otherwise very heterogeneous. Ancient materialism
was thoroughly mechanistic."
The aims of this Introduction are to characterize the philosophy of
science and technology, henceforth PS & T, to locate it on the
map ofiearning, and to propose criteria for evaluating work in this
field. 1. THE CHASM BETWEEN S & T AND THE HUMANITIES It has
become commonplace to note that contemporary culture is split into
two unrelated fields: science and the rest, to deplore this split -
and to do is some truth in the two cultures thesis, and even
nothing about it. There greater truth in the statement that there
are literally thousands of fields of knowledge, each of them
cultivated by specialists who are in most cases indifferent to what
happens in the other fields. But it is equally true that all fields
of knowledge are united, though in some cases by weak links,
forming the system of human knowledge. Because of these links, what
advances, remains stagnant, or declines, is the entire system of S
& T. Throughout this book we shall distinguish the main fields
of scientific and technological knowledge while at the same time
noting the links that unite them.
The purpose of this Introduction is to sketch our approach to the
study of value, morality and action, and to show the place we
assign it in the systemof human knowledge. 1. VALUE, MORALITY AND
ACTION: FACT, THEORY, AND METATHEORY We take it that all animals
evaluate some things and some processes, and that some of them
learn the social behavior patterns we call 'moral principles', and
even act according to them at least some of the time. An animal
incapable of evaluating anything would be very short-lived; and a
social animal that did not observe the accepted social behavior
patterns would be punished. These are facts about values, morals
and behavior patterns: they are incorporated into the bodies of
animals or the structure ofsocialgroups. We distinguish theq the
facts of valuation, morality and action from the study of such
facts.This study can be scientific, philosophic or both. A
zoologist may investigate the wayan animal evaluates environmental
or internal stimuli; a social psychologist may examine the way
children learn, or fail to learn, certain values and norms when
placed in certain environments. And a philosopher may study such
descriptive or explan atory studies, with a view to evaluating
valuations, moral norms, or behavior patterns; he may analyze the
very concepts of value, morals and action, as well as their
cognates; or he may criticize or reconstruct value beliefs, moral
norms and action plans."
This volume is a logical sequel of Volume I, The Search for System:
indeed, it concerns the ways theoretical systems are put to work
and subjected to test. Yet it can be read independently by anyone
familiar with some factual theories, referring back to Volume I
when necessary. Special Symbols AS;B the set A is included in the
set B AvB the union of the sets A and B AnB the common part of the
sets A and B aEB the individual a is in (or belongs to) the set A
Card (A) cardinality (numerosity) of the set A AxB Cartesian
product of the sets A and B en(A) consequence(s) of the set A of
assumptions equals by definition =dt definition Dt* some x (or
there is at least one x such that) (3 x) e empirical datum e*
translation of e into a semiempirical, semitheoreticallanguage h
hypothesis m(r) measured value of the degree r m(;) average (or
mean) value of a set of measured values of ,; P-jT T presupposes P
p, q arbitrary (unspecified) propositions (statements) P(x) x has
the property P (or x is a P) {xl P(x)} set of the x such that every
x is a P pVq p and/or q (inclusive disjunction) p &q p and q
(conjunction) p-+q if p, then q (conditional or implication) p if
and only if q (biconditional or equivalence) p-q sum over i 2:; t
theorem, testable consequence
The Tum of the Tide During centuries physicists were supposed to be
studying the physical world. Since the turn of the century this
assumption has often been challenged as naive: it was proclaimed
that physics is not about the external world but about observers
and their manipUlations: that it is meaningless to talk of anything
else than observation devices and opera tions: that the laws of
physics concern our knowledge rather than the external world. This
view of the nature of physical science has old roots in philo sophy
but it was independently reinvented by a number of philosophi cally
inclined physicists, notably ERNST MACH. These scientists were
disgusted with the school philosophies and they were alarmed by the
increasing number of physical concepts which they regarded as meta
physical or beyond experimental control, such as those of absolute
motion, ether, electromagnetic field, and molecule. Reasonably
enough, they wished to keep physics testable. To accomplish this
goal they adopted the safe method, namely to banish every idea that
could not be closely tied to observation. In this way they
certainly avoided the risks of untestable speculation but they also
failed to enjoy the benefits of theoretical invention. Furthermore
they instituted unawares a new meta physics that was to dominate
the philosophy of physics for half a century: the metaphysics
according to which the world is made of sense experience."
This is a collection of technical papers in the foundations and the
philoso It takes both "foundations" phy of physics with emphasis on
the former. and "philosophy" in their narrow technical senses but
it construes "physics" lato sensu, as including all the sciences of
nonliving systems. All eleven papers constituting this volume were
written for it. The problems tackled in this book concern certain
basic concepts, hypotheses, theories, and research programmes in
physical science. Some of these problems are topical, others new,
but they are all fundamental and the subject of research and
controversy. Consequently this volume is expected to serve those
students, teachers and researchers who enjoy learning, teaching,
discussing or doing theoretical physics. It is addressed to the
nine to niners rather than to the nine to fivers. It is expected to
attract the theoretician in search for new basic ideas, the teacher
eager to perfect his understanding of physical theory and transmit
his own zeal and his own doubts, as well as the student anxious to
get down to essentials. This book may also interest the
mathematician for whom physics offers a challenge (or a good
pretext). Finally, it should get the attention of the philosopher
of science aware of the advantages of philosophizing on foundations
research problems rather than on the popularization of some results
of research. There are at least two reasons for valuing foundations
research."
The word 'materialism' is ambiguous: it designates a moral doc
trine as well as a philosophy and, indeed, an entire world view.
Moral materialism is identical with hedonism, or the doctrine that
humans should pursue only their own pleasure. Philosophical ma
terialismis the view that the real worId is composed exclusively of
material things. The two doctrines are logically independent:
hedonism is consistent with immaterialism, and materialism is
compatible with high minded morals. We shall be concerned ex
c1usively with philosophical materialism. And we shall not confuse
it with realism, or the epistemological doctrine that knowIedge, or
at any rate scientific knowledge, attempts to represent reality.
Philosophical materialism is not a recent fad and it is not a solid
block: it is as old as philosophy and it has gone through six quite
different stages. The first was ancient materialism, centered
around Greek and Indian atomism. The second was the revival of the
first during the 17th century. The third was 18th century ma
terialism, partly derived from one side of Descartes' ambiguous
legacy. The fourth was the mid-19th century "scientific" material
ism, which flourished mainly in Germany and England, and was tied
to the upsurge of chemistry and biology. The fifth was dialec tical
and historical materialism, which accompanied the consolida tion of
the socialist ideology. And the sixth or current stage, evolved
mainly by Australian and American philosophers, is aca demic and
nonpartisan but otherwise very heterogeneous. Ancient materialism
was thoroughly mechanistic."
The aims of this Introduction are to characterize the philosophy of
science and technology, henceforth PS & T, to locate it on the
map ofiearning, and to propose criteria for evaluating work in this
field. 1. THE CHASM BETWEEN S & T AND THE HUMANITIES It has
become commonplace to note that contemporary culture is split into
two unrelated fields: science and the rest, to deplore this split -
and to do is some truth in the two cultures thesis, and even
nothing about it. There greater truth in the statement that there
are literally thousands of fields of knowledge, each of them
cultivated by specialists who are in most cases indifferent to what
happens in the other fields. But it is equally true that all fields
of knowledge are united, though in some cases by weak links,
forming the system of human knowledge. Because of these links, what
advances, remains stagnant, or declines, is the entire system of S
& T. Throughout this book we shall distinguish the main fields
of scientific and technological knowledge while at the same time
noting the links that unite them.
The purpose of this Introduction is to sketch our approach to the
study of value, morality and action, and to show the place we
assign it in the system of human knowledge. 1. VALUE, MORALITY AND
ACTION: FACT, THEORY, AND METATHEORY We take it that all animals
evaluate some things and some processes, and that some of them
learn the social behavior patterns we call 'moral principles', and
even act according to them at least some of the time. An animal
incapable of evaluating anything would be very short-lived; and a
social animal that did not observe the accepted social behavior
patterns would be punished. These are facts about values, morals
and behavior patterns: they are incorporated into the bodies of
animals or the structure of social groups. We distinguish then the
facts of valuation, morality and action from the study of such
facts. This study can be scientific, philosophic or both. wayan
animal evaluates environmental A zoologist may investigate the or
internal stimuli; a social psychologist may examine the way
children learn, or fail to learn, certain values and norms when
placed in certain environments. And a philosopher may study such
descriptive or explan atory studies, with a view to evaluating
valuations, moral norms, or behavior patterns; he may analyze the
very concepts of value, morals and action, as well as their
cognates; or he may criticize or reconstruct value beliefs, moral
norms and action plans."
In this Introduction we shall state the business of both
descriptive and normative epistemology, and shall locate them in
the map oflearning. This must be done because epistemology has been
pronounced dead, and methodology nonexisting; and because, when
acknowledged at all, they are often misplaced. 1. DESCRIPTIVE
EPISTEMOLOGY The following problems are typical of classical
epistemology: (i) What can we know? (ii) How do we know? (iii)
What, if anything, does the subject contribute to his knowledge?
(iv) What is truth? (v) How can we recognize truth? (vi) What is
probable knowledge as opposed to certain knowledge? (vii) Is there
a priori knowledge, and if so of what? (viii) How are knowledge and
action related? (ix) How are knowledge and language related? (x)
What is the status of concepts and propositions? In some guise or
other all of these problems are still with us. To be sure, if
construed as a demand for an inventory of knowledge the first
problem is not a philosophical one any more than the question 'What
is there?'. But it is a genuine philosophical problem if construed
thus: 'What kinds of object are knowable-and which ones are not?'
However, it is doubtful that philosophy can offer a correct answer
to this problem without the help of science and technology. For
example, only these disciplines can tell us whether man can know
not only phenomena (appearances) but also noumena (things in
themselves or self-existing objects).
In this Introduction' we shall sketch the business of ontology, or
metaphysics, and shall locate it on the map of learning. This has
to be done because there are many ways of construing the word
'ontology' and because of the bad reputation metaphysics has
suffered until recently - a well deserved one in most cases. 1.
ONTOLOGICAL PROBLEMS Ontological (or metaphysical) views are
answers to ontological ques tions. And ontological (or
metaphysical) questions are questions with an extremely wide scope,
such as 'Is the world material or ideal - or perhaps neutral?" 'Is
there radical novelty, and if so how does it come about?', 'Is
there objective chance or just an appearance of such due to human
ignorance?', 'How is the mental related to the physical?', 'Is a
community anything but the set of its members?', and 'Are there
laws of history?'. Just as religion was born from helplessness,
ideology from conflict, and technology from the need to master the
environment, so metaphysics - just like theoretical science - was
probably begotten by the awe and bewilderment at the boundless
variety and apparent chaos of the phenomenal world, i. e. the sum
total of human experience. Like the scientist, the metaphysician
looked and looks for unity in diversity, for pattern in disorder,
for structure in the amorphous heap of phenomena - and in some
cases even for some sense, direction or finality in reality as a
whole."
The present volume collects some of the talks given at the Bertrand
Russell Colloquium on Exact Philosophy, attached to the McGill
University Foundations and Philosophy of Science Unit. It also
includes a paper, on Bertrand Russell's method of philosophizing,
read at the memorial symposium held at Sir Gorge Williams
University shortly after the philosopher's death. All the papers
appear here for the first time. Unlike many a philosophy of science
anthology, this one is not center ed on the philosophy of physics.
In fact the papers deal with conceptual and, in particular,
philosophical problems that pop up in almost every one of the
provinces of the vast territory constituted by the foundations,
meth odology and philosophy of science. A couple of border
territories which are in the process of being infiltrated have been
added for good measure. The inclusion of papers in the philosophy
of formal science and in the philosophies of physics and of
biology, in a volume belonging to a series devoted to the
philosophy and methodology of the social and behavioral sciences,
should raise no eyebrows. Because the sciences of man make use of
logic and mathematics, they are interested in questions such as
whether the formal sciences have anything to do with reality
(rather than with our theories about reality) and whether or not
logic has kept up with the practice of mathematicians. These two
problems are tackled in Part II, on the philosophy of formal
science."
|
You may like...
Loot
Nadine Gordimer
Paperback
(2)
R383
R310
Discovery Miles 3 100
|