|
Showing 1 - 13 of
13 matches in All Departments
This book represents a major contribution to game theory. It offers
this conception of equilibrium in games: strategic equilibrium.
This conception arises from a study of expected utility decision
principles, which must be revised to take account of the evidence a
choice provides concerning its outcome. The argument for these
principles distinguishes reasons for action from incentives, and
draws on contemporary analyses of counterfactual conditionals. The
book also includes a procedure for identifying strategic equilibria
in ideal normal-form games. In synthesizing decision theory and
game theory in a powerful way this book will be of particular
interest to all philosophers concerned with decision theory and
game theory as well as economists and other social scientists.
Good decisions account for risks. For example, the risk of an
accident while driving in the rain makes a reasonable driver decide
to slow down. While risk is a large topic in theoretical
disciplines such as economics and psychology, as well as in
practical disciplines such as medicine and finance, philosophy has
a unique contribution to make in developing a normative theory of
risk that states what risk is, and to what extent our responses to
it are rational. Weirich here develops a philosophical theory of
the rationality of responses to risk. He first distinguishes two
types of risk: first, a chance of a bad event, and second, an act's
risk in relation to its possible outcomes. He argues that this
distinction has normative significance in the sense that one's
attitudes towards these types of risks - and how one acts on them -
are governed by different general principles of rationality.
Consequently, a comprehensive account of risk must not only
characterize rational responses to risk but also explain why these
responses are rational. Weirich explains how, for a rational ideal
agent, the expected utilities of the acts available in a decision
problem explain the agent's preferences among the acts. As a
result, maximizing expected utility is just following preferences
among the acts. His view takes an act's expected utility, not just
as a feature of a representation of preferences among acts, but
also as a factor in the explanation of preferences among acts. The
book's precise formulation of general standards of rationality for
attitudes and for acts, and its rigorous argumentation for these
standards, make it philosophical; but while mainly of interest to
philosophers, its broader arguments will contribute to the
conceptual foundations of studies of risk in all disciplines that
study it.
Classical decision theory evaluates entire worlds, specified so as
to include everything a decision-maker cares about. Thus applying
decision theory requires performing computations far beyond an
ordinary decision-maker's ability. In this book Paul Weirich
explains how individuals can simplify and streamline their choices.
He shows how different 'parts' of options (intrinsic, temporal,
spatiotemporal, causal) are separable, so that we can know what
difference one part makes to the value of an option, regardless of
what happens in the other parts. He suggests that the primary value
of options is found in basic intrinsic attitudes towards outcomes:
desires, aversions, or indifferences. And using these two facts he
argues that we need only compare small parts of the options we face
in order to make a rational decision. This important book will
interest readers in decision theory, economics, and the behavioral
sciences.
Within traditional decision theory, common decision principles --
e.g. the principle to maximize utility -- generally invoke
idealization; they govern ideal agents in ideal circumstances. In
Realistic Decision Theory, Paul Weirch adds practicality to
decision theory by formulating principles applying to nonideal
agents in nonideal circumstances, such as real people coping with
complex decisions. Bridging the gap between normative demands and
psychological resources, Realistic Decision Theory is essential
reading for theorists seeking precise normative decision principles
that acknowledge the limits and difficulties of human
decision-making.
An agent often does not have precise probabilities or utilities to
guide resolution of a decision problem. I advance a principle of
rationality for making decisions in such cases. To begin, I
represent the doxastic and conative state of an agent with a set of
pairs of a probability assignment and a utility assignment. Then I
support a decision principle that allows any act that maximizes
expected utility according to some pair of assignments in the set.
Assuming that computation of an option's expected utility uses
comprehensive possible outcomes that include the option's risk, no
consideration supports a stricter requirement.
Food products with genetically modified (GM) ingredients are
common, yet many consumers are unaware of this. When polled,
consumers say that they want to know whether their food contains GM
ingredients, just as many want to know whether their food is
natural or organic. Informing consumers is a major motivation for
labeling. Consumers who want GM-free products will pay a premium to
support voluntary labeling. Labeling need not be mandatory. When
polled, consumers say that they want to know whether their food
contains GM ingredients, just as many want to know whether their
food is natural or organic. Informing consumers is a major
motivation for labeling. Why do consumers want to know about GM
ingredients? GM foods are tested to ensure safety and have been on
the market for more than a decade. Still, many consumers, including
some with food allergies, want to be cautious. Also, GM crops may
affect neighboring plants through pollen drift. Despite tests for
environmental impact, some consumers may worry that GM crops will
adversely effect the environment. The study of risk and its
management raises questions not settled by the life sciences alone.
This book surveys various labeling policies and the cases for them.
It is the first comprehensive, interdisciplinary treatment of the
debate about labeling genetically modified food. The contributors
include philosophers, bioethicists, food and agricultural
scientists, attorneys/legal scholars, and economists.
Classical decision theory evaluates entire worlds, specified so as
to include everything a decision-maker cares about. Thus applying
decision theory requires performing computations far beyond an
ordinary decision-maker's ability. In this book Paul Weirich
explains how individuals can simplify and streamline their choices.
He shows how different 'parts' of options (intrinsic, temporal,
spatiotemporal, causal) are separable, so that we can know what
difference one part makes to the value of an option, regardless of
what happens in the other parts. He suggests that the primary value
of options is found in basic intrinsic attitudes towards outcomes:
desires, aversions, or indifferences. And using these two facts he
argues that we need only compare small parts of the options we face
in order to make a rational decision. This important book will
interest readers in decision theory, economics, and the behavioral
sciences.
This book represents a major contribution to game theory. It offers
this conception of equilibrium in games: strategic equilibrium.
This conception arises from a study of expected utility decision
principles, which must be revised to take account of the evidence a
choice provides concerning its outcome. The argument for these
principles distinguishes reasons for action from incentives, and
draws on contemporary analyses of counterfactual conditionals. The
book also includes a procedure for identifying strategic equilibria
in ideal normal-form games. In synthesizing decision theory and
game theory in a powerful way this book will be of particular
interest to all philosophers concerned with decision theory and
game theory as well as economists and other social scientists.
In Decision Space: Multidimensional Utility Analysis, first
published in 2001, Paul Weirich increases the power and versatility
of utility analysis and in the process advances decision theory.
Combining traditional and novel methods of option evaluation into
one systematic method of analysis, multidimensional utility
analysis is a valuable tool. It provides formulations of important
decision principles, such as the principle to maximize expected
utility; enriches decision theory in solving recalcitrant decision
problems; and provides in particular for the cases in which an
expert must make a decision for a group of people. The multiple
dimensions of this analysis create a decision space broad enough to
accommodate all factors affecting an option's utility. The book
will be of interest to advanced students and professionals working
in the subject of decision theory, as well as to economists and
other social scientists.
In Decision Space: Multidimensional Utility Analysis, Paul Weirich increases the power and versatility of utility analysis and in the process advances decision theory. Combining traditional and novel methods of option evaluation into one systematic method, multidimensional utility analysis is a valuable new tool. The multiple dimensions of this analysis create a decision space broad enough to accommodate all factors affecting an option's utility. The book will be of interest to advanced students and professionals working in the subject of decision theory, as well as to economists and other social scientists.
Groups of people perform acts that are subject to standards of
rationality. A committee may sensibly award fellowships, or may
irrationally award them in violation of its own policies. A theory
of collective rationality defines collective acts that are
evaluable for rationality and formulates principles for their
evaluation. This book argues that a group's act is evaluable for
rationality if it is the products of acts its members fully
control. It also argues that such an act is collectively rational
if the acts of the group's members are rational. Efficiency is a
goal of collective rationality, but not a requirement, except in
cases where conditions are ideal for joint action and agents have
rationally prepared for joint action.
The people engaged in a game of strategy form a group, and the
combination of their acts yields a collective act. If their
collective act is rational, it constitutes a solution to their
game. A theory of collective rationality yields principles
concerning solutions to games. One principle requires that a
solution constitute an equilibrium among the incentives of the
agents in the game. In a cooperative game some agents are
coalitions of individuals, and it may be impossible for all agents
to pursue all incentives. Because rationality is attainable, the
appropriate equilibrium standard for cooperative games requires
that agents pursue only incentives that provide sufficient reasons
to act. The book's theory of collective rationality supports an
attainable equilibrium-standard for solutions to cooperative games
and shows that its realization follows from individuals' rational
acts.
By extending the theory of rationality to groups, this book reveals
the characteristics that make an act evaluable for rationality and
the way rationality's evaluation of an act responds to the type of
control its agent exercises over the act. The book's theory of
collective rationality contributes to philosophical projects such
as contractarian ethics and to practical projects such as the
design of social institutions.
Groups of people perform acts that are subject to standards of
rationality. A committee may sensibly award fellowships, or may
irrationally award them in violation of its own policies. A theory
of collective rationality defines collective acts that are
evaluable for rationality and formulates principles for their
evaluation. This book argues that a group's act is evaluable for
rationality if it is the products of acts its members fully
control. It also argues that such an act is collectively rational
if the acts of the group's members are rational. Efficiency is a
goal of collective rationality, but not a requirement, except in
cases where conditions are ideal for joint action and agents have
rationally prepared for joint action. The people engaged in a game
of strategy form a group, and the combination of their acts yields
a collective act. If their collective act is rational, it
constitutes a solution to their game. A theory of collective
rationality yields principles concerning solutions to games. One
principle requires that a solution constitute an equilibrium among
the incentives of the agents in the game. In a cooperative game
some agents are coalitions of individuals, and it may be impossible
for all agents to pursue all incentives. Because rationality is
attainable, the appropriate equilibrium standard for cooperative
games requires that agents pursue only incentives that provide
sufficient reasons to act. The book's theory of collective
rationality supports an attainable equilibrium-standard for
solutions to cooperative games and shows that its realization
follows from individuals' rational acts. By extending the theory of
rationality to groups, this book reveals the characteristics that
make an act evaluable for rationality and the way rationality's
evaluation of an act responds to the type of control its agent
exercises over the act. The book's theory of collective rationality
contributes to philosophical projects such as contractarian ethics
and to practical projects such as the design of social
institutions.
|
You may like...
Workplace law
John Grogan
Paperback
R900
R820
Discovery Miles 8 200
|