|
Showing 1 - 4 of
4 matches in All Departments
This book argues that it can be both reasonable and appropriate to
adopt a certain kind of misanthropy. The author defends a
cognitivist version of misanthropy, an attitude whose central
feature is the judgment that humanity is morally bad. Misanthropy
is often dismissed on moral grounds. Many people hold that malice
toward human persons is problematic and vulnerable to moral
objections. In this book, the author advocates for cognitivist
misanthropy. He defends an Asymmetry Thesis, according to which a
morally bad deed carries more weight than a morally good deed, even
if the harm of the former is exactly equal to the benefit of the
latter. He makes the case that being misanthropic in the
cognitivist sense is morally permissible and compatible with a
broad range of moral reasons for action. He also considers the role
of misanthropy in environmental thought, arguing that charges of
misanthropy against certain "non-anthropocentric" views do not have
the force they are typically thought to carry. Finally, the author
investigates the practical implications of adopting cognitivist
misanthropy, asking what living with such an attitude would
involve. A Philosophical Defense of Misanthropy will appeal to
researchers and advanced students working in ethics and the
philosophy of human nature.
In this book, Toby Svoboda develops and defends a Kantian
environmental virtue ethic, challenging the widely-held view that
Kant's moral philosophy has little to offer environmental ethics.
On the contrary, Svoboda contends that on Kantian grounds, there is
good moral reason to care about non-human organisms in their own
right and to value their flourishing independently of human
interests, since doing so is constitutive of certain
(environmental) virtues. Svoboda argues that Kant's account of
indirect duties regarding nature can ground a compelling
environmental ethic: the Kantian duty to develop morally virtuous
dispositions strictly proscribes unnecessarily harming organisms,
and it also gives us moral reason to act in ways that benefit such
organisms. Svoboda's account engages the recent literature on
environmental virtue (including Rosalind Hursthouse, Philip Cafaro,
Ronald Sandler, Thomas Hill, and Louke van Wensveen) and provides
an original argument for an environmental ethic firmly rooted in
Kant's moral philosophy.
In this book, Toby Svoboda develops and defends a Kantian
environmental virtue ethic, challenging the widely-held view that
Kant's moral philosophy has little to offer environmental ethics.
On the contrary, Svoboda contends that on Kantian grounds, there is
good moral reason to care about non-human organisms in their own
right and to value their flourishing independently of human
interests, since doing so is constitutive of certain
(environmental) virtues. Svoboda argues that Kant's account of
indirect duties regarding nature can ground a compelling
environmental ethic: the Kantian duty to develop morally virtuous
dispositions strictly proscribes unnecessarily harming organisms,
and it also gives us moral reason to act in ways that benefit such
organisms. Svoboda's account engages the recent literature on
environmental virtue (including Rosalind Hursthouse, Philip Cafaro,
Ronald Sandler, Thomas Hill, and Louke van Wensveen) and provides
an original argument for an environmental ethic firmly rooted in
Kant's moral philosophy.
This book analyzes major ethical issues surrounding the use of
climate engineering, particularly solar radiation management (SRM)
techniques, which have the potential to reduce some risks of
anthropogenic climate change but also carry their own risks of harm
and injustice. The book argues that we should approach the ethics
of climate engineering via "non-ideal theory," which investigates
what justice requires given the fact that many parties have failed
to comply with their duty to mitigate greenhouse gas emissions.
Specifically, it argues that climate justice should be approached
comparatively, evaluating the relative justice or injustice of
feasible policies under conditions that are likely to hold within
relevant timeframes. Likely near-future conditions include
"pessimistic scenarios," in which no available option avoids
serious ethical problems. The book contends that certain uses of
SRM can be ethically defensible in some pessimistic scenarios. This
is the first book devoted to the many ethical issues surrounding
climate engineering.
|
|