|
Books > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Logic
This book is an example of fruitful interaction between
(non-classical) propo sitionallogics and (classical) model theory
which was made possible due to categorical logic. Its main aim
consists in investigating the existence of model completions for
equational theories arising from propositional logics (such as the
theory of Heyting algebras and various kinds of theories related to
proposi tional modal logic ). The existence of model-completions
turns out to be related to proof-theoretic facts concerning
interpretability of second order propositional logic into ordinary
propositional logic through the so-called 'Pitts' quantifiers' or
'bisimulation quantifiers'. On the other hand, the book develops a
large number of topics concerning the categorical structure of
finitely presented al gebras, with related applications to
propositional logics, both standard (like Beth's theorems) and new
(like effectiveness of internal equivalence relations, projectivity
and definability of dual connectives such as difference). A special
emphasis is put on sheaf representation, showing that much of the
nice categor ical structure of finitely presented algebras is in
fact only a restriction of natural structure in sheaves.
Applications to the theory of classifying toposes are also covered,
yielding new examples. The book has to be considered mainly as a
research book, reporting recent and often completely new results in
the field; we believe it can also be fruitfully used as a
complementary book for graduate courses in categorical and
algebraic logic, universal algebra, model theory, and non-classical
logics. 1."
The general aim of this book is to provide an elementary exposition
of some basic concepts in terms of which both classical and
non-dassicallogirs may be studied and appraised. Although
quantificational logic is dealt with briefly in the last chapter,
the discussion is chiefly concemed with propo- gjtional cakuli.
Still, the subject, as it stands today, cannot br covered in one
book of reasonable length. Rather than to try to include in the
volume as much as possible, I have put emphasis on some selected
topics. Even these could not be roverrd completely, but for each
topic I have attempted to present a detailed and precise
t'Xposition of several basic results including some which are
non-trivial. The roots of some of the central ideas in the volume
go back to J.Luka- siewicz's seminar on mathematicallogi
Philosophers have warned of the perils of a life spent without
reflection, but what constitutes reflective inquiry - and why it's
necessary in our lives - can be an elusive concept. Synthesizing
ideas from minds as diverse as John Dewey and Paulo Freire,
theHandbook of Reflection and Reflective Inquiry presents
reflective thought in its most vital aspects, not as a fanciful or
nostalgic exercise, but as a powerful means of seeing familiar
events anew, encouraging critical thinking and crucial insight,
teaching and learning. In its opening pages, two seasoned
educators, Maxine Greene and Lee Shulman, discuss reflective
inquiry as a form of active attention (Thoreau's "wide-awakeness"),
an act of consciousness, and a process by which people can
understand themselves, their work (particularly in the form of life
projects), and others. Building on this foundation, the Handbook
analyzes through the work of 40 internationally oriented authors: -
Definitional issues concerning reflection, what it is and is not; -
Worldwide social and moral conditions contributing to the growing
interest in reflective inquiry in professional education; -
Reflection as promoted across professional educational domains,
including K-12 education, teacher education, occupational therapy,
and the law; - Methods of facilitating and scaffolding reflective
engagement; - Current pedagogical and research practices in
reflection; - Approaches to assessing reflective inquiry.
Educators across the professions as well as adult educators,
counselors and psychologists, and curriculum developers concerned
with adult learning will find the Handbook of Reflection and
Reflective Inquiry an invaluable teaching tool for challenging
times.
The subject of Time has a wide intellectual appeal across different
dis ciplines. This has shown in the variety of reactions received
from readers of the first edition of the present Book. Many have
reacted to issues raised in its philosophical discussions, while
some have even solved a number of the open technical questions
raised in the logical elaboration of the latter. These results will
be recorded below, at a more convenient place. In the seven years
after the first publication, there have been some noticeable newer
developments in the logical study of Time and temporal expressions.
As far as Temporal Logic proper is concerned, it seems fair to say
that these amount to an increase in coverage and sophistication,
rather than further break-through innovation. In fact, perhaps the
most significant sources of new activity have been the applied
areas of Linguistics and Computer Science (including Artificial
Intelligence), where many intriguing new ideas have appeared
presenting further challenges to temporal logic. Now, since this
Book has a rather tight composition, it would have been difficult
to interpolate this new material without endangering
intelligibility."
Vladimir Aleksandrovich Smirnov was born on March 2, 1931. He
graduated from Moscow State University in 1954. From 1957 till 1961
he was a lecturer in philosophy and logic at the Tomsk University.
Since 1961 his scientific activity continued in Moscow at the
Institute of Philosophy of Academy of Sciences of the USSR. From
1970 and till the last days of his life V. A. Smirnov was lecturer
and then Professor at the Chair of Logic at Moscow State
University. V. A. Smirnov played an important role at the Institute
of Philosophy of Russian Academy of Sciences being the Head of
Department of Epistemology, Logic and Philosophy of Science and
Technology, and the Head of Section of Logic. Last years he was the
leader of the Centre of Logical Investigations of Russsian Academy
of Sciences. In 1990-91 he founded a new non-goverment Institute of
Logic, Cognitive Sciences and Development of Personality for
performing research, teaching, editorial and organization activity
in the field of humanities. At the Department of Philosophy of
Moscow State University and at the Institute of Philosophy V. A.
Smirnov and his close colleagues have founded a Russian logical
school which brought up many talented researchers who work at
several scientific centres in various countries.
Hard as it is to believe, what is possibly Galileo's most important
Latin manuscript was not transcribed for the National Edition of
his works and so has remained hidden from scholars for centuries.
In this volume William A. Wallace translates the logical treatises
contained in that manuscript and makes them intelligible to the
modern reader. He prefaces his translation with a lengthy
introduction describing the contents of the manuscript, the sources
from which it derives, its dating, and how it relates to Galileo's
other Pisan writings. The translation is accompanied by extensive
notes and commentary; these explain the text and tie it to the
fuller exposition of Galileo's logical methodology in the author's
companion volume, Galileo's Logic of Discovery and Proof. The
result is a research tool that is indispensable for anyone intent
on understanding Galileo's logic as described in that volume and
the documentary evidence on which it is based.
It is with great pleasure that we are presenting to the community
the second edition of this extraordinary handbook. It has been over
15 years since the publication of the first edition and there have
been great changes in the landscape of philosophical logic since
then. The first edition has proved invaluable to generations of
students and researchers in formal philosophy and language, as well
as to consumers of logic in many applied areas. The main logic
artiele in the Encyelopaedia Britannica 1999 has described the
first edition as 'the best starting point for exploring any of the
topics in logic'. We are confident that the second edition will
prove to be just as good. ! The first edition was the second
handbook published for the logic commu nity. It followed the North
Holland one volume Handbook 0/ Mathematical Logic, published in
1977, edited by the late Jon Barwise. The four volume Handbook 0/
Philosophical Logic, published 1983-1989 came at a fortunate
temporal junction at the evolution of logic. This was the time when
logic was gaining ground in computer science and artificial
intelligence cireles. These areas were under increasing commercial
press ure to provide devices which help and/or replace the human in
his daily activity. This pressure required the use of logic in the
modelling of human activity and organisa tion on the one hand and
to provide the theoretical basis for the computer program
constructs on the other.
Mathematician and popular science author Eugenia Cheng is on a
mission to show you that mathematics can be flexible, creative, and
visual. This joyful journey through the world of abstract
mathematics into category theory will demystify mathematical
thought processes and help you develop your own thinking, with no
formal mathematical background needed. The book brings abstract
mathematical ideas down to earth using examples of social justice,
current events, and everyday life - from privilege to COVID-19 to
driving routes. The journey begins with the ideas and workings of
abstract mathematics, after which you will gently climb toward more
technical material, learning everything needed to understand
category theory, and then key concepts in category theory like
natural transformations, duality, and even a glimpse of ongoing
research in higher-dimensional category theory. For fans of How to
Bake Pi, this will help you dig deeper into mathematical concepts
and build your mathematical background.
This volume contains a selection of papers (keynote addresses and
other important papers) from the International Conference on
Argumentation at Amsterdam of 2002 by prominent international
scholars of argumentation theory. The contributions are
representative of the main approaches to the study of
argumentation: the informal logical approach, the logical approach,
the dialectical approach, the rhetorical and the communicative
approach. Taken together the papers in this volume provide an
insightful cross-section of the current state of affairs in
argumentation research.
The collection of essays as a whole will be of interest to all
those working in the field of argumentation theory and to all
scholars who are interested in recent developments in this field.
This book revisits the definition of polemical discourse and deals
with its functions in the democratic sphere. It first examines
theoretical questions concerning the management of disagreement in
democracy and the nature of polemical discourse. Next, it analyses
case studies involving such issues as the place of women in the
public space, illustrated by the case of the burqa in France and
public controversy in the media on the exclusion of women from the
public space. The book then explores reason, passion and violence
in polemical discourse by means of cases involving confrontations
between secular and ultra-orthodox circles, controversies about the
Mexican Wall and fierce discussions about stock-options, and
bonuses in times of financial crisis. Although polemical exchanges
in the public sphere exacerbate dissent instead of resolving
conflicts, they are quite frequent in the media and on the Net. How
can we explain such a paradox? Most studies in argumentation avoid
the question: they mainly focus on the verbal procedures leading to
agreement. This focus stems from the centrality conferred upon
consensus in our democratic societies, where decisions should be
the result of a process of deliberation. What is then the social
function of a confrontational management of dissent that does not
primarily seek to achieve agreement? Is it just a sign of
decadence, failure and powerlessness, or does it play a
constructive role? This book answers these questions.
The aim of this book is to present and analyze philosophical
conceptions concerning mathematics and logic as formulated by
Polish logicians, mathematicians and philosophers in the 1920s and
1930s. It was a remarkable period in the history of Polish science,
in particular in the history of Polish logic and mathematics.
Therefore, it is justified to ask whether and to what extent the
development of logic and mathematics was accompanied by a
philosophical reflection. We try to answer those questions by
analyzing both works of Polish logicians and mathematicians who
have a philosophical temperament as well as their research
practice. Works and philosophical views of the following Polish
scientists will be analyzed: Waclaw Sierpinski, Zygmunt
Janiszewski, Stefan Mazurkiewicz, Stefan Banach Hugo Steinhaus,
Eustachy Zylinsk and Leon Chwistek, Jan Lukasiewicz, Zygmunt
Zawirski, Stanislaw Lesniewski, Tadeusz Kotarbinski, Kazimierz
Ajdukiewicz, Alfred Tarski, Andrzej Mostowski and Henryk Mehlberg,
Jan Sleszynski, Stanislaw Zaremba and Witold Wilkosz. To indicate
the background of scientists being active in the 1920s and 1930s we
consider in Chapter 1 some predecessors, in particular: Jan
Sniadecki, Jozef Maria Hoene-Wronski, Samuel Dickstein and Edward
Stamm.
Intellectics' seeks to understand the functions, structure and
operation of the human intellect and to test artificial systems to
see the extent to which they can substitute or complement such
functions. The word itself was introduced in the early 1980s by
Wolfgang Bibel to describe the united fields of artificial
intelligence and cognitive science. The book collects papers by
distinguished researchers, colleagues and former students of
Bibel's, all of whom have worked together with him, and who present
their work to him here to mark his 60th birthday. The papers
discuss significant issues in intellectics and computational logic,
ranging across automated deduction, logic programming, the
logic-based approach to intellectics, cognitive robotics, knowledge
representation and reasoning. Each paper contains new, previously
unpublished, reviewed results. The collection is a state of the art
account of the current capabilities and limitations of a
computational-logic-based approach to intellectics. Readership:
Researchers who are convinced that the intelligent behaviour of
machines should be based on a rigid formal treatment of knowledge
representation and reasoning.
Infinite regresses (e.g., event3 caused event2, event2 caused
event1, ad infinitum; statement3 justifies statement2, statement2
justifies statement1, ad infinitum) have been used as premises in
arguments on a great variety of topics in both Eastern and Western
philosophy since ancient times. They are part of a philosopher's
tool kit of argumentation. But how sharp or strong is this tool?
How effectively is it used? The typical presentation of infinite
regress arguments throughout history is so succinct and has so many
gaps that it is often unclear how an infinite regress is derived,
and why an infinite regress is logically problematic, and as a
result, it is often difficult to evaluate infinite regress
arguments. These prevalent consequences indicate that there is a
need for a theory to re-orient our practice. After well over two
thousand years of using infinite regresses as premises, one would
have expected that at least some theory of infinite regress
arguments would have emerged. None exists. There have been only a
few articles on infinite regress arguments, but they are based on
the examination of only a small number of examples, discuss only a
few logical or rhetorical aspects of infinite regress arguments,
and so they help to meet the need for a theory in only a limited
way.
Given the situation, I examined many infinite regress arguments
to clarify the various aspects of the derivation of infinite
regresses, and explain the different ways in which certain infinite
regresses are unacceptable. My general approach consisted of
collecting and evaluating as many infinite regress arguments as
possible, comparing and contrasting many of the formal and
non-formal properties, looking for recurring patterns, and
identifying the properties that appeared essential to those
patterns. The six chapters of this book gradually emerged from this
approach. Two very general questions guided this work: (1) How are
infinite regresses generated in infinite regress arguments? (2) How
do infinite regresses logically function in an argument? In
answering these questions I avoided as much as possible addressing
the philosophical content and historical background of the
arguments examined. Due to the already extensive work done on
causal regresses and regresses of justification, only a few
references are made to them. However, the focus is on other issues
that have been neglected, and that do contribute to a general
theory of infinite regress arguments: I clarify the notion of an
infinite regress; identify different logical forms of infinite
regresses; describe different kinds of infinite regress arguments;
distinguish the rhetoric from the logic in infinite regress
arguments; and discuss the function of infinite regresses in
arguments. The unexamined derivation of infinite regresses is worth
deriving to discover what we have kept hidden from ourselves,
improve our ways of constructing and evaluating these arguments,
and sharpen and strengthen one of our argumentative tools. This
work is one example of empirical logic applied to infinite regress
arguments: "the attempt to formulate, to test, to clarify, and to
systematize concepts and principles for the interpretation, the
evaluation, and the sound practice of reasoning" (Finocchiaro, M.
Arguments about Arguments, Systematic, Critical and Historical
Essays in Logical Theory. P48). "
This is a single volume reference guide to the latest work and
potential future directions in Philosophical Logic, written by an
international team of leading scholars. "The Continuum Companion to
Philosophical Logic" offers the definitive guide to a key area of
contemporary philosophy. The book covers all the fundamental areas
of philosophical logic - topics that have continued to attract
interest historically as well as topics that have emerged more
recently as active areas of research. Seventeen specially
commissioned essays from an international team of experts reveal
where important work continues to be done in the area and, most
valuably, the exciting new directions the field is taking. The
Companion explores issues pertaining to classical logic and its
rivals, extensional and intensional extensions of classical logic,
semantics for parts of natural language, and the application of
logic in the theory of rationality. Crucially the emphasis is on
the role that logic plays in understanding philosophical problems.
Featuring a series of indispensable research tools, including an A
to Z of key terms and concepts, a detailed list of resources, a
bibliography and a companion website, this is the essential
reference tool for anyone working in contemporary philosophical
logic. "The Continuum Companions" series is a major series of
single volume companions to key research fields in the humanities
aimed at postgraduate students, scholars and libraries. Each
companion offers a comprehensive reference resource giving an
overview of key topics, research areas, new directions and a
manageable guide to beginning or developing research in the field.
A distinctive feature of the series is that each companion provides
practical guidance on advanced study and research in the field,
including research methods and subject-specific resources.
Constructive mathematics is based on the thesis that the meaning of
a mathematical formula is given, not by its truth-conditions, but
in terms of what constructions count as a proof of it. However, the
meaning of the terms `construction' and `proof' has never been
adequately explained (although Kriesel, Goodman and Martin-Loef
have attempted axiomatisations). This monograph develops precise
(though not wholly formal) definitions of construction and proof,
and describes the algorithmic substructure underlying
intuitionistic logic. Interpretations of Heyting arithmetic and
constructive analysis are given. The philosophical basis of
constructivism is explored thoroughly in Part I. The author seeks
to answer objections from platonists and to reconcile his position
with the central insights of Hilbert's formalism and logic.
Audience: Philosophers of mathematics and logicians, both academic
and graduate students, particularly those interested in Brouwer and
Hilbert; theoretical computer scientists interested in the
foundations of functional programming languages and program
correctness calculi.
"Foundations of the Formal Sciences" (FotFS) is a series of
interdisciplinary conferences in mathematics, philosophy, computer
science and linguistics. The main goal is to reestablish the
traditionally strong links between these areas of research that
have been lost in the past decades.
The second conference in the series had the subtitle
"Applications of Mathematical Logic in Philosophy and Linguistics"
and brought speakers from all parts of the Formal Sciences together
to give a holistic view of how mathematical methods can improve our
philosophical and technical understanding of language and
scientific discourse, ranging from the theoretical level up to
applications in language recognition software.
Audience: This volume is of interest to all formal philosophers
and theoretical linguists. In addition to that, logicians
interested in the applications of their field and logic students in
mathematics, computer science, philosophy and linguistics can use
the volume to broaden their knowledge of applications of logic.
This monograph is designed to provide an introduction to the
principal areas of tense logic. Many of the developments in this
ever-growing field have been intentionally excluded to fulfill this
aim. Length also dictated a choice between the alternative
notations of A. N. Prior and Nicholas Rescher - two pioneers of the
subject. I choose Prior's because of the syntactical parallels with
the language it symbolizes and its close ties with other branches
of logi cal theory, especially modal logic. The first chapter
presents a wider view of the material than later chapters. Several
lines of development are consequently not followed through the
remainder of the book, most notably metric systems. Although it is
import ant to recognize that the unadorned Prior-symbolism can be
enriched in vari ous ways it is an advanced subject as to how to
actually carry off these enrichments. Readers desiring more
information are referred to the appropri ate literature.
Specialists will notice that only the first of several quantifi
cational versions of tense logic is proven complete in the final
chapter. Again constraints of space are partly to blame. The proof
for the 'star' systems is wildly complex and at the time of this
writing is not yet ready for publi cation."
This book aids in the rehabilitation of the wrongfully deprecated
work of William Parry, and is the only full-length investigation
into Parry-type propositional logics. A central tenet of the
monograph is that the sheer diversity of the contexts in which the
mereological analogy emerges - its effervescence with respect to
fields ranging from metaphysics to computer programming - provides
compelling evidence that the study of logics of analytic
implication can be instrumental in identifying connections between
topics that would otherwise remain hidden. More concretely, the
book identifies and discusses a host of cases in which analytic
implication can play an important role in revealing distinct
problems to be facets of a larger, cross-disciplinary problem. It
introduces an element of constancy and cohesion that has previously
been absent in a regrettably fractured field, shoring up those who
are sympathetic to the worth of mereological analogy. Moreover, it
generates new interest in the field by illustrating a wide range of
interesting features present in such logics - and highlighting
these features to appeal to researchers in many fields.
|
|