|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Metaphysics & ontology
In The Republic, Plato suggests that the enlightened person will
find himself disoriented on his return to the realm of the shadows.
So at the very beginning of the Western philosophical tradition,
there is a clear affirmation of the idea that following
enlightenment, the sensory world can be differently experienced. In
this book, Mark Wynn takes up this idea, but argues that
'enlightenment' or spiritual maturity may result in, and may partly
consist in, not so much a state of confusion or bewilderment in our
experience of sensory things, but in a renewal of the realm of the
senses. On this view, the 'shadows', as they feature in the seer's
experience, can bear the imprint of religious thoughts and
attitudes, and it is therefore possible to be occupied with
religious thoughts even as we engage with the realm of sensory
things. And if that is so, then one standard objection to
Christian, and in general broadly Platonic, conceptions of the
spiritual life will have been removed: attending to the realm of
religious truth need not after all imply any neglect of the world
of sensory forms; and it may even be that it is in our encounter
with the realm of sensory forms that certain religious insights are
presented to us most vividly.
We must all make choices about how we want to live. We evaluate our
possibilities by relying on historical, moral, personal, political,
religious, and scientific modes of evaluations, but the values and
reasons that follow from them conflict. Philosophical problems are
forced on us when we try to cope with such conflicts. There are
reasons for and against all proposed ways of coping with the
conflicts, but none of them has been generally accepted by
reasonable thinkers. The constructive aim of The Nature of
Philosophical Problems is to propose a way of understanding the
nature of such philosophical problems, explain why they occur, why
they are perennial, and propose a pluralist approach as the most
reasonable way of coping with them. This approach is practical,
context-dependent, and particular. It follows from it that the
recurrence of philosophical problems is not a defect, but a welcome
consequence of the richness of our modes of understanding that
enlarges the range of possibilities by which we might choose to
live. The critical aim of the book is to give reasons against both
the absolutist attempt to find an overriding value or principle for
resolving philosophical problems and of the relativist claim that
reasons unavoidably come to an end and how we want to live is
ultimately a matter of personal preference, not of reasons.
Abstract objects have been a central topic in philosophy since
antiquity. Philosophers have defended various views about abstract
objects by appealing to metaphysical considerations, considerations
regarding mathematics or science, and, not infrequently, intuitions
about natural language. This book pursues the question of how and
whether natural language allows for reference to abstract objects
in a fully systematic way. By making full use of contemporary
linguistic semantics, it presents a much greater range of
linguistic generalizations than has previously been taken into
consideration in philosophical discussions, and it argues for an
ontological picture is very different from that generally taken for
granted by philosophers and semanticists alike. Reference to
abstract objects such as properties, numbers, propositions, and
degrees is considerably more marginal than generally held. Instead,
natural language is rather generous in allowing reference to
particularized properties (tropes), the use of nonreferential
expressions in apparent referential position, and the use of
"nominalizing expressions," such as quantifiers like "something."
Reference to abstract objects is achieved generally only by the use
of 'reifying terms', such as "the number eight."
Is truth objective or relative? What exists independently of our
minds? This book is about these two questions. The essays in its
pages variously defend and critique answers to each, grapple over
the proper methodology for addressing them, and wonder whether
either question is worth pursuing. In so doing, they carry on a
long and esteemed tradition - for our two questions are among the
oldest of philosophical issues, and have vexed almost every major
philosopher, from Plato, to Kant to Wittgenstein. Fifteen eminent
contributors bring fresh perspectives, renewed energy and original
answers to debates which have been the focus of a tremendous amount
of interest in the last three decades both within philosophy and
the culture at large.
Susanne Bobzien presents the definitive study of one of the most important intellectual legacies of the ancient Greeks: the Stoic theory of causal determinism. She reconstructs the theory and discusses how the Stoics (third century BC to second century AD) justified it, and how it relates to their views on possibility, action, freedom, moral responsibility, and many other topics. She demonstrates the considerable philosophical richness and power that these ideas retain today.
About Aquinas: St Thomas Aquinas lived from 1224/5 to 1274, mostly
in his native Italy but for a time in France. He was the greatest
of the medieval philosopher/theologians, and one of the most
important of all Western thinkers. His most famous books are the
two summaries of his teachings, the Summa contra gentiles and the
Summa theologiae. About this book: Norman Kretzmann expounds and
criticizes Aquinas's natural theology of creation, which is
`natural' (or philosophical) in virtue of Aquinas's having
developed it without depending on the data of Scripture. The
Metaphysics of Creation is a continuation of the project Kretzmann
began in The Metaphysics of Theism, moving the focus from the first
to the second book of Aquinas's Summa contra gentiles. Here we find
Aquinas building upon his account of the existence and nature of
God, arguing that the existence of things other than God must be
explained by divine creation out of nothing. He develops arguments
to identify God's motivation for creating, to defend the
possibility of a beginningless created universe, and to explain the
origin of species. He then focuses exclusively on creatures with
intellects, with the result that more than half of his natural
theology of creation constitutes a philosophy of mind. Kretzmann
gives a masterful guide through all these arguments. As before, he
not only expounds Aquinas's natural theology, but advocates it as
the best historical instance available to us.
David Charles presents a study of Aristotle's views on meaning, essence, necessity, and related topics. These interconnected views are central to Aristotle's metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophy of science. They are also highly relevant to current debates in philosophy of language. Charles aims, on the basis of a careful reading of Aristotle's texts and many subsequent works, to reach a clear understanding of his claims and arguments, and to assess their truth and their importance to philosophy ancient and modern.
Proclus (412-485 A.D.) was one of the last official 'successors' of
Plato at the head of the Academy in Athens at the end of Antiquity,
before the school was finally closed down in 529. As a prolific
author of systematic works on a wide range of topics and one of the
most influential commentators on Plato of all times, the legacy of
Proclus in the cultural history of the west can hardly be
overestimated. This book introduces the reader to Proclus' life and
works, his place in the Platonic tradition of Antiquity and the
influence his work exerted in later ages. Various chapters are
devoted to Proclus' metaphysical system, including his doctrines
about the first principle of all reality, the One, and about the
Forms and the soul. The broad range of Proclus' thought is further
illustrated by highlighting his contribution to philosophy of
nature, scientific theory, theory of knowledge and philosophy of
language. Finally, also his most original doctrines on evil and
providence, his Neoplatonic virtue ethics, his complex views on
theology and religious practice, and his metaphysical aesthetics
receive separate treatments. This book is the first to bring
together the leading scholars in the field and to present a state
of the art of Proclean studies today. In doing so, it provides the
most comprehensive introduction to Proclus' thought currently
available.
This is a reissue, with new introduction, of Susan Sauve Meyer's
1993 book, in which she presents a comprehensive examination of
Aristotle's accounts of voluntariness in the Eudemian and
Nicomachean Ethics. She makes the case that these constitute a
theory of moral responsibility--albeit one with important
differences from modern theories.
Highlights of the discussion include a reconstruction of the
dialectical argument in the Eudemian Ethics II 6-9, and a
demonstration that the definitions of 'voluntary' and 'involuntary'
in Nicomachean Ethics III 1 are the culmination of that argument.
By identifying the paradigms of voluntariness and involuntariness
that Aristotle begins with and the opponents (most notably Plato)
he addresses, Meyer explains notoriously puzzling features of the
Nicomachean account--such as Aristotle's requirement that
involuntary agents experience pain or regret. Other familiar
features of Aristotle's account are cast in a new light. That we
are responsible for the characters we develop turns out not to be a
necessary condition of responsible agency. That voluntary action
has its "origin" in the agent and that our actions are "up to us to
do and not to so"--often interpreted as implying a libertarian
conception of agency--turn out to be perfectly compatible with
causal determinism, a point Meyer makes by locating these locutions
in the context of a Aristotle's general understanding of causality.
While Aristotle does not himself face or address worries that
determinism is incompatible with responsibility, his causal
repertoire provides the resources for a powerful response to
incompatibilist arguments. On this and other fronts Aristotle's is
a view to be taken seriously by theorists of moral responsibility.
This is the third volume of philosophical writings by Donald
Davidson. He presents a selection of his work on knowledge, mind,
and language from the 1980s and the 1990s. We all have knowledge of
our own minds, knowledge of the contents of other minds, and
knowledge of the shared environment. Davidson examines the nature
and status of each of these three sorts of knowledge, and the
connections and differences among them. Along the way he has
illuminating things to say about truth, human rationality, and the
relations between language, thought, and the world.
Rae Langton offers a new interpretation and defence of Kant's
doctrine of things in themselves. Kant distinguishes things in
themselves from phenomena, and in so doing he makes a metaphysical
distinction between intrinsic and relational properties of
substances. Kant says that phenomena-things as we know them-consist
'entirely of relations', by which he means forces. His claim that
we have no knowledge of things in themselves is not idealism, but
epistemic humility: we have no knowledge of the intrinsic
properties of substances. This humility has its roots in some
plausible philosophical beliefs: an empiricist belief in the
receptivity of human knowledge and a metaphysical belief in the
irreducibility of relational properties. Langton's interpretation
vindicates Kant's scientific realism, and shows his
primary/secondary quality distinction to be superior even to
modern-day competitors. And it answers the famous charge that
Kant's tale of things in themselves is one that makes itself
untellable.
Oxford Cognitive Science Series General Editors: Martin Davies,
Wilde Reader in Mental Philosophy, University of Oxford, UK, James
Higginbotham , Professor of General Linguistics, University of
Oxford, UK, John O'Keefe, Professor of Cognitive Neuroscience,
University College, London, UK, Christopher Peacocke, Waynflete
Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy, University of Oxford, UK, and
Kim Plunkett, University Lecturer in Psychology, University of
Oxford, UK The Oxford Cognitive Science series is a forum for the
best contemporary work in this flourishing field, where various
disciplines-cognitive psychology, philosophy, linguistics,
cognitive neuroscience, and computational theory-join forces in the
investigation of thought, awareness, understanding, and associated
workings of the mind. Each book will represent an original
contribution to its subject, but will be accessible beyond the
ranks of specialists, so as to reach a broad interdisciplinary
readership. The series will be carefully shaped and steered by the
general editors, with the aim of representing the most important
developments in the field and bringing together its constituent
disciplines. About this book The renowned philosopher Jerry Fodor,
who has been a leading figure in the study of the mind for more
than twenty years, presents a strikingly original theory of the
basic constituents of thought. He suggests that the heart of a
cognitive science is its theory of concepts, and that cognitive
scientists have gone badly wrong in many areas because their
assumptions about concepts have been seriously mistaken. Fodor
argues compellingly for an atomistic theory of concepts, deals out
witty and pugnacious demolitions of the rival theories that have
prevailed in recent years, and suggests that future work on human
cognition should build upon new foundations. This lively,
conversational, accessible book is the first volume in the Oxford
Cognitive Science Series, where the best original work in this
field will be presented to a broad readership. Concepts will
fascinate anyone interested in contemporary work on mind and
language. Cognitive science will never be the same again.
In Contradiction advocates and defends the view that there are true
contradictions (dialetheism), a view that flies in the face of
orthodoxy in Western philosophy since Aristotle. The book has been
at the center of the controversies surrounding dialetheism ever
since its first publication in
1987. This second edition of the book substantially expands upon
the original in various ways, and also contains the author's
reflections on developments over the last two decades. Further
aspects of dialetheism are discussed in the companion volume, Doubt
Truth to be a Liar, also published by
Oxford University Press in 2006.
In this short, lucid, rich book Michael Dummett sets out his views
about some of the deepest questions in philosophy. The fundamental
question of metaphysics is: what does reality consist of? To answer
this, Dummett holds, it is necessary to say what kinds of fact
obtain, and what constitutes their holding good. Facts correspond
with true propositions, or true thoughts: when we know which
propositions, or thoughts, in general, are true, we shall know what
facts there are in general. Dummett considers the relation between
metaphysics, our conception of the constitution of reality, and
semantics, the theory that explains how statements are determined
as true or as false in terms of their composition out of their
constituent expressions. He investigates the two concepts on which
the bridge that connects semantics to metaphysics rests, meaning
and truth, and the role of justification in a theory of meaning. He
then examines the special semantic and metaphysical issues that
arise with relation to time and tense. On this basis Dummett puts
forward his controversial view of reality as indeterminate: there
may be no fact of the matter about whether an object does or does
not have a given property. We have to relinquish our deep-held
realist understanding of language, the illusion that we know what
it is for any proposition that we can frame to be true
independently of our having any means of recognizing its truth, and
accept that truth depends on our capacity to apprehend it. Dummett
concludes with a chapter about God.
This book is an attempt to conduct a comprehensive examination of
Kant's metaphysic of Transcendental Idealism, which is everywhere
presupposed by his critical theory of knowledge, his theory of the
moral and the aesthetic judgement, and his rational approach to
religion. It will attempt to show that this metaphysic is
profoundly coherent, despite frequent inconsistencies of
expression, and that it throws an indispensable light on his
critical enquiries. Kant conceives of knowledge in especially
narrow terms, and there is nothing absurd in the view that
thinkables must, in his sense, extend far more widely than
knowables. Kant also goes further than most who have thought in his
fashion in holding that, not only the qualities of the senses, but
also the space and time in which we place them, have non-sensuous,
non-spatial, and non-temporal foundations in relations among
thinkables that transcend empirical knowledge. This contention also
reposes on important arguments, and can be given a sense that will
render it interesting and consistent. The book explores this sense,
and connects it with the thought of Kant's immediate predecessors
in the great German scholastic movement that began with Leibniz:
this scholasticism, it will be held, is throughout preserved as the
unspoken background of Kant's critical developments, whose great
innovation really consisted in pushing it out of the region of the
knowable, into the region of what is permissively or, in some
cases, obligatorily, thinkable.
Frank Jackson champions the cause of conceptual analysis as central
to philosophical inquiry. In recent years conceptual analysis has
been undervalued and, Jackson suggests, widely misunderstood; he
argues that there is nothing especially mysterious about it and a
whole range of important questions cannot be productively addressed
without it. He anchors his argument in discussion of specific
philosophical issues, starting with the metaphysical doctrine of
physicalism and moving on, via free will, meaning, personal
identity, motion and change, to the philosophy of colour and to
ethics. The significance of different kinds of supervenience
theses, Kripke and Putnam's work in the philosophy of modality and
language, and the role of intuitions about possible cases receive
detailed attention. Jackson concludes with a defence of a version
of analytical descriptivism in ethics. In this way the book not
only offers a methodological programme for philosophy, but also
throws fascinating new light on some much-debated problems and
their interrelations. puffs which may be quoted (please do not edit
without consulting OUP editor): 'This is an outstanding book. It
covers a vast amount of philosophy in a very short space, advances
a number of original and striking positions, and manages to be both
clear and concise in its expositions of other views and forceful in
its criticisms of them. The book offers something new for those
interested in the various individual problems it
discusses-conceptual analysis, the mind-body relation, secondary
qualities, modality, and ethical realism. But unifying these
individual discussions is an ambitious structure which amounts to
an outline of a complete metaphysical system, and an outline of an
epistemology for this metaphysics. It is hard to think of a central
area of analytic philosophy which will not be touched by Jackson's
conclusions.' Tim Crane, Reader in Philosophy, University College
London 'The writing is clear, straightforward, and down to
earth-the usual virtues one expects from Jackson . . . what he has
to say is innovative and valuable . . . the book deals with a large
number of apparently diverse philosophical issues, but it is also
an elegantly unified work. What gives it unity is the
metaphilosophical framework that Jackson works out with great care
and persuasiveness. This is the first serious and sustained work on
the methodology of metaphysics in recent memory. What he says about
the role of conceptual analysis in metaphysics is an important and
timely contribution. . . . It is refreshing and heartening to see a
first-class analytic philosopher doing some serious
metaphilosophical work . . . I think that the book will be greeted
as an important event in philosophical publishing.' Jaegwon Kim,
Professor of Philosophy, Brown University
This book is intended as an introduction to the philosophical
problems of space and time, suitable for any reader who has an
interest in the nature of the universe and who has a
secondary-school knowledge of physics and mathematics. In
particular, it is hoped that the book may find a use in philosophy
departments and physics departments within universities and other
tertiary institutions. The attempt is always to introduce the
problems from a twentieth-century point of view. It is preferable
to introduce the history of the topic if and when that history
becomes relevant to the development and solution of the problems,
rather than to introduce a problem that was of importance in some
previous age and to trace the development of it down the years.
Meaning (significance) and nature are this book's principal topics.
They seem an odd couple, like raisins and numbers, though they
elide when meanings of a global sort-ideologies and religions, for
example-promote ontologies that subordinate nature. Setting one
against the other makes reality contentious. It signifies workmates
and a coal face to miners, gluons to physicists, prayer and
redemption to priests. Are there many realities, or many
perspectives on one? The answer I prefer is the comprehensive
naturalism anticipated by Aristotle and Spinoza: "natura naturans,
natura naturata." Nature naturing is an array of mutually
conditioning material processes in spacetime. Each structure or
event-storm clouds forming, nature natured-is self-differentiating,
self-stabilizing, and sometimes self-disassembling; each alters or
transforms a pre-existing state of affairs. This surmise
anticipated discoveries and analyses to which neither thinker had
access, though physics and biology confirm their hypothesis beyond
reasonable doubt. Hence the question this book considers: Is
reality divided:nature vrs. lived experience? Or is experience,
with all its meanings and values, the complex expression of natural
processes?
|
|