|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present > Western philosophy, c 1600 to c 1800
Modern philosophy originates during the scientific revolution, and
Michael Jacovides provides an engaging account of how this
scientific background influences one of the foremost figures of
early modern philosophy, John Locke. With this guiding thread,
Jacovides gives clear and accurate answers to some of the central
questions surrounding Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding.
Why does he say that we have an obscure idea of substance? Why does
he think that we perceive a two-dimensional array of color patches?
Why does he think that matter can't naturally think? Why does he
analyze secondary qualities as powers to produce ideas in us?
Jacovides' method also allows him to trace the effects of Locke's
scientific outlook on his descriptions of the way things appear to
him and on his descriptions of the boundaries of conceivability. By
placing Locke's thought in its scientific, religious, and
anti-scholastic contexts, Jacovides explains not only what Locke
believes but also why he believes it, and he thereby uncovers
reveals the extra-philosophical sources of some of the central
aspects of Locke's philosophy.
The acquisition of self-knowledge is often described as one of the
main goals of philosophical inquiry. At the same time, some sort of
self-knowledge is often regarded as a necessary condition of our
being a human agent or human subject. Thus self-knowledge is taken
to constitute both the beginning and the end of humans' search for
wisdom, and as such it is intricately bound up with the very idea
of philosophy. Not surprisingly therefore, the Delphic injunction
'Know thyself' has fascinated philosophers of different times,
backgrounds, and tempers. But how can we make sense of this
imperative? What is self-knowledge and how is it achieved? What are
the structural features that distinguish self-knowledge from other
types of knowledge? What role do external, second- and
third-personal, sources of knowledge play in the acquisition of
self-knowledge? How can we account for the moral impact ascribed to
self-knowledge? Is it just a form of anthropological knowledge that
allows agents to act in accordance with their aims? Or, does
self-knowledge ultimately ennoble the self of the subjects having
it? Finally, is self-knowledge, or its completion, a goal that may
be reached at all? The book addresses these questions in fifteen
chapters covering approaches of many philosophers from Plato and
Aristotle to Edmund Husserl or Elisabeth Anscombe. The short
reflections inserted between the chapters show that the search for
self-knowledge is an important theme in literature, poetry,
painting and self-portraiture from Homer.
The essays collected in this volume by Paul Guyer, one of the
world's foremost Kant scholars, explore Kant's attempt to develop a
morality grounded on the intrinsic and unconditional value of the
human freedom to set our own ends. When regulated by the principle
that the freedom of all is equally valuable, the freedom to set our
own ends - what Kant calls "humanity" - becomes what he calls
autonomy. These essays explore Kant's strategies for establishing
the premise that freedom is the inner worth of the world or the
essential end of humankind, as he says, and for deriving the
specific duties that fundamental principle of morality generates in
the empirical circumstances of human existence. The Virtues of
Freedom further investigates Kant's attempts to prove that we are
always free to live up to this moral ideal, that is, that we have
free will no matter what, as well as his more successful
explorations of the ways in which our natural tendencies to be
moral - dispositions to the feeling of respect and more specific
feelings such as love and self-esteem - can and must be cultivated
and educated. Guyer finally examines the various models of human
community that Kant develops from his premise that our associations
must be based on the value of freedom for all. The contrasts but
also similarities of Kant's moral philosophy to that of David Hume
but many of his other predecessors and contemporaries, such as
Stoics and Epicureans, Pufendorf and Wolff, Hutcheson, Kames, and
Smith, are also explored.
Is Kant really the 'bourgeois' philosopher that his advocates and
opponents take him to be? In this bold and original re-thinking of
Kant, Michael Wayne argues that with his aesthetic turn in the
Third Critique, Kant broke significantly from the problematic
philosophical structure of the Critique of Pure Reason. Through his
philosophy of the aesthetic Kant begins to circumnavigate the
dualities in his thought. In so doing he shows us today how the
aesthetic is a powerful means for imagining our way past the
apparent universality of contemporary capitalism. Here is an
unfamiliar Kant: his concepts of beauty and the sublime are
reinterpreted as attempts to socialise the aesthetic while Wayne
reconstructs the usually hidden genealogy between Kant and
important Marxist concepts such as totality, dialectics, mediation
and even production. In materialising Kant's philosophy, this book
simultaneously offers a Marxist defence of creativity and
imagination grounded in our power to think metaphorically and in
Kant's concept of reflective judgment. Wayne also critiques aspects
of Marxist cultural theory that have not accorded the aesthetic the
relative autonomy and specificity which it is due. Discussing such
thinkers as Adorno, Bourdieu, Colletti, Eagleton, Lukacs, Ranciere
and others, Red Kant: Aesthetics, Marxism and the Third Critique
presents a new reading of Kant's Third Critique that challenges
Marxist and mainstream assessments of Kant alike.
Allen W. Wood presents the first book-length systematic exposition
in English of Fichte's most important ethical work, the System of
Ethics (1798). He places this work in the context of Fichte's life
and career, of his philosophical system as conceived in the later
Jena period, and in relation to his philosophy of right or justice
and politics. Wood discusses Fichte's defense of freedom of the
will, his grounding of the moral principle, theory of moral
conscience, transcendental deduction of intersubjectivity, and his
conception of free rational communication and the rational society.
He develops and emphasizes the social and political radicalism of
Fichte's moral and political philosophy, and brings out the
philosophical interest of Fichte's positions and arguments for
present day philosophy. Fichte's Ethical Thought defends the
position that Fichte is a major thinker in the history of ethics,
and the most important figure in the history of modern continental
philosophy in the past two centuries.
This volume offers a fresh view of the work of Thomas Reid, a
leading figure in the history of eighteenth-century philosophy. A
team of leading experts in the field explore the significance of
Reid's thought in his time and ours, focusing in particular on
three broad themes: mind, knowledge, and value. Together, they
argue that Reid's philosophy is about developing agents in a rich
world of objects and values, agents with intellectual and active
powers whose regularity is productive. Though such agents are
equipped at first with rudimentary abilities, those abilities are
responsive. Our powers consist in a fundamental and on-going
engagement with the world, a world that calls on us to be flexible,
sensitive, astute, and ultimately, practical. Thomas Reid on Mind,
Knowledge, and Value represents both the vitality of Reid's work,
and the ways in which current philosophers are engaging with his
ideas.
This book defends a new interpretation of Hegel's theoretical
philosophy, according to which Hegel's project in his central
Science of Logic has a single organizing focus, provided by taking
metaphysics as fundamental to philosophy, rather than any
epistemological problem about knowledge or intentionality. Hegel
pursues more specifically the metaphysics of reason, concerned with
grounds, reasons, or conditions in terms of which things can be
explained-and ultimately with the possibility of complete reasons.
There is no threat to such metaphysics in epistemological or
skeptical worries. The real threat is Kant's Transcendental
Dialectic case that metaphysics comes into conflict with itself.
But Hegel, despite familiar worries, has a powerful case that
Kant's own insights in the Dialectic can be turned to the purpose
of constructive metaphysics. And we can understand in these terms
the unified focus of the arguments at the conclusion of Hegel's
Science of Logic. Hegel defends, first, his general claim that the
reasons which explain things are always found in immanent concepts,
universals or kinds. And he will argue from here to conclusions
which are distinctive in being metaphysically ambitious yet
surprisingly distant from any form of metaphysical foundationalism,
whether scientistic, theological, or otherwise. Hegel's project,
then, turns out neither Kantian nor Spinozist, but more
distinctively his own. Finally, we can still learn a great deal
from Hegel about ongoing philosophical debates concerning
everything from metaphysics, to the philosophy of science, and all
the way to the nature of philosophy itself.
Henry E. Allison presents an analytical and historical commentary
on Kant`s transcendental deduction of the pure concepts of the
understanding in the Critique of Pure Reason. He argues that,
rather than providing a new solution to an old problem (refuting a
global skepticism regarding the objectivity of experience), it
addresses a new problem (the role of a priori concepts or
categories stemming from the nature of the understanding in
grounding this objectivity), and he traces the line of thought that
led Kant to the recognition of the significance of this problem in
his 'pre-critical' period. Allison locates four decisive steps in
this process: the recognition that sensibility and understanding
are distinct and irreducible cognitive powers, which Kant referred
to as a 'great light' of 1769; the subsequent realization that,
though distinct, these powers only yield cognition when they work
together, which is referred to as the 'discursivity thesis' and
which led directly to the distinction between analytic and
synthetic judgments and the problem of the synthetic a priori; the
discovery of the necessary unity of apperception as the supreme
norm governing discursive cognition; and the recognition, through
the influence of Tetens, of the role of the imagination in
mediating between sensibility and understanding. In addition to the
developmental nature of the account of Kant`s views, two
distinctive features of Allison'sreading of the deduction are a
defense of Kant`s oft criticized claim that the conformity of
appearances to the categories must be unconditionally rather than
merely conditionally necessary (the 'non-contingency thesis') and
an insistence that the argument cannot be separated from Kant`s
transcendental idealism (the 'non-separability thesis').
Modern Conspiracy attempts to sketch a new conception of conspiracy
theory. Where many commentators have sought to characterize
conspiracy theory in terms of the collapse of objectivity and
Enlightenment reason, Fleming and Jane trace the important role of
conspiracy in the formation of the modern world: the scientific
revolution, social contract theory, political sovereignty,
religious paranoia and mass communication media. Rather than see in
conspiratorial thinking the imminent death of Enlightenment reason,
and a regression to a new Dark Age, Modern Conspiracy contends that
many characteristic features of conspiracies tap very deeply into
the history of the Enlightenment itself: among other things, its
vociferous critique of established authorities, and a conception of
political sovereignty fuelled by fear of counter-plots. Drawing out
the roots of modern conspiratorial thinking leads us to truths less
salacious and scandalous than the claims of conspiracy theorists
themselves yet ultimately far more salutary: about mass
communication; about individual and crowd psychology; and about our
conception of and relation to knowledge. Perhaps, ultimately, what
conspiracy theory affords us is a renewed opportunity to reflect on
our very relationship to the truth itself.
Most philosophers have taken the importance of Kant's Critique of
Judgement to lie primarily in its contributions to aesthetics and
to the philosophy of biology. Hannah Ginsborg, however, sees the
Critique of Judgement as representing a central contribution to the
understanding of human cognition more generally. The fourteen
essays collected here advance a common interpretive project: that
of bringing out the philosophical significance of the notion of
judgement which figures in the third Critique and showing its
importance both to Kant's own theoretical philosophy and to
contemporary views of human thought and cognition. To possess the
capacity of judgment, on the interpretation presented here, is to
respond to the world in a way which involves the recognition of
one's responses as normatively appropriate to the objects which
cause them. It is through this capacity that we are able not merely
to respond discriminatively to objects, as animals do, but to bring
them under concepts and so to make claims about them which can be
true or false. The Critique of Judgement, on this reading, rejects
the traditional dichotomy between the natural and the normative,
taking nature itself both human nature and nature outside us to be
comprehensible only in normative terms. The essays in this book
develop this reading in its own right, and draw on it to address
interpretive debates in Kant's aesthetics, theory of knowledge, and
philosophy of biology. They also bring out its relevance to
contemporary debates about concept-acquisition, the content of
perception, and skepticism about rule-following and meaning.
The appeal of philosophy has always been its willingness to speak
to those pressing questions that haunt us as we make our way
through life. What is truth? Could we think without language? Is
materialism everything? But in recent years, philosophy has been
largely absent from mainstream cultural commentary. Many have come
to believe that the field is excessively technical and
inward-looking and that it has little to offer outsiders. The 25
interviews collected in this volume, all taken from a series of
online interviews with leading philosophers published by the
cultural magazine 3ammagazine.com, were carried out with the aim of
confronting widespread ignorance about contemporary philosophy.
Interviewer Richard Marshall's informed and enthusiastic questions
help his subjects explain the meaning of their work in a way that
is accessible to non-specialists. Contemporary philosophical issues
are presented through engaging but serious dialogues that, taken
together, offer a glimpse into key debates across the discipline.
Alongside metaphysics, philosophy of mind, epistemology, logic,
philosophy of science, philosophy of language, political philosophy
and ethics, discussed here are feminist philosophy, continental
philosophy, pragmatism, philosophy of religion, experimental
philosophy, bioethics, animal rights, and legal philosophy.
Connections between philosophy and fields such as psychology,
cognitive science, and theology are likewise examined. Marshall
interviews philosophers both established and up-and coming.
Engaging, thoughtful and thought-provoking, inviting anyone with a
hunger for philosophical questions and answers to join in,
Philosophy at 3:AM shows that contemporary philosophy can be
relevant - and even fun.
Kant's Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason was written
late in his career. It presents a theory of 'radical evil' in human
nature, touches on the issue of divine grace, develops a
Christology, and takes a seemingly strong interest in the issue of
scriptural interpretation. The essays in this Critical Guide
explore the reasons why this is so, and offer careful and
illuminating interpretations of the themes of the work. The
relationship of Kant's Religion to his other writings is discussed
in ways that underscore the importance of this work for the entire
critical philosophy, and provide a broad perspective on his moral
thought; connections are also drawn between religion, history, and
politics in Kant's later thinking. Together the essays offer a rich
exploration of the work which will be of great interest to those
involved in Kant studies and the philosophy of religion.
This book provides a new interpretation of the ethical theory of
G.W.F. Hegel. The aim is not only to give a new interpretation for
specialists in German Idealism, but also to provide an analysis
that makes Hegel's ethics accessible for all scholars working in
ethical and political philosophy. While Hegel's political
philosophy has received a good deal of attention in the literature,
the core of his ethics has eluded careful exposition, in large part
because it is contained in his claims about conscience. This book
shows that, contrary to accepted wisdom, conscience is the central
concept for understanding Hegel's view of practical reason and
therefore for understanding his ethics as a whole. The argument
combines careful exegesis of key passages in Hegel's texts with
detailed treatments of problems in contemporary ethics and
reconstructions of Hegel's answers to those problems. The main
goals are to render comprehensible Hegel's notoriously difficult
texts by framing arguments with debates in contemporary ethics, and
to show that Hegel still has much to teach us about the issues that
matter to us most. Central topics covered in the book are the
connection of self-consciousness and agency, the relation of
motivating and justifying reasons, moral deliberation and the
holism of moral reasoning, mutual recognition, and the rationality
of social institutions.
The twelfth-century philosopher Averroes is often identified by
modern Arab thinkers as an early advocate of the Enlightenment.
Saud M. S. Al-Tamamy demonstrates that an historical as well as
comparative approach to Averroes' thought refutes this widely held
assumption. The philosophical doctrine of Averroes is compared with
that of the key figure of the Enlightenment in Western thought,
Immanuel Kant. By comparing Averroes and Kant, Al-Tamamy evaluates
the ideologies of each thinker's work and in particular focuses on
their respective political implications on two social groups: the
Elite, in Averroes' case, and the Public, in the case of Kant. The
book's methodology is at once historical, analytical and
communicative, and is especially relevant when so many thinkers -
both Western and Middle Eastern - are anxious to find common
denominators between the formations of Islamic and Western
cultures. It responds to a need for comparative analysis in the
field of Averroes studies, and takes on the challenge to uncover
the philosopher's influence on the Enlightenment.
The keywords of the Enlightenment-freedom, tolerance, rights,
equality-are today heard everywhere, and they are used to endorse a
wide range of positions, some of which are in perfect
contradiction. While Orwell's 1984 claims that there is one phrase
in the English language that resists translation into Newspeak,
namely the opening lines of that key Enlightenment text, the
Declaration of Independence: 'We hold these truths to be
self-evident, that all men are created equal...', we also find the
Wall Street Journal saying of the Iraq War that the US was
'fighting for the very notion of the Enlightenment'. It seems we
are no longer sure whether these truths are self-evident nor quite
what they might mean today. Based on the critically acclaimed
Oxford Amnesty Lectures series, this book brings together a number
of major international figures to debate the history of freedom,
tolerance, equality, and to explore the complex legacy of the
Enlightenment for human rights. The lectures are published here
with responses from other leading figures in the field.
"Rationality and Feminist Philosophy" argues that the Enlightenment
conception of rationality that feminists are fond of attacking is
no longer a live concept. Deborah K. Heikes shows how contemporary
theories of rationality are consonant with many feminist concerns
and proposes that feminists need a substantive theory of
rationality, which she argues should be a virtue theory of
rationality.
Within both feminist and non-feminist philosophical circles, our
understanding of rationality depends upon the concept's history.
Heikes traces the development of theories of rationality from
Descartes through to the present day, examining the work of
representative philosophers of the Enlightenment and twentieth and
twenty-first centuries. She discusses feminist concerns with
rationality as understood by each philosopher discussed and also
focuses on the deeper problems that lie outside specifically
feminist issues. She goes on to consider how each conception of
rationality serves to ground the broadly conceived feminist
philosophical goals of asserting the reality and injustice of
oppression. She ultimately concludes that a virtue rationality may
serve feminist needs well, without the accompanying baggage of
Enlightenment rationality.
A unifying theme of Loeb's work is epistemological - that Descartes
and Hume advance theories of knowledge that rely on a substantial
'naturalistic' component, adopting one or another member of a
cluster of psychological properties of beliefs as the goal of
inquiry and the standard for assessing belief-forming mechanisms.
Thus Loeb shows a surprising affinity between the epistemologies of
the two figures -- surprising because they are often thought of as
polar opposites in this respect.
Descartes and Hume are unique in that their philosophical texts are
accessible beyond just a narrow audience in the history of
philosophy; their ideas continue to be a vital part of the field at
large. This volume will thus appeal to advanced students and
scholars not just in the history of early modern philosophy but in
epistemology and other core areas of the discipline.
This title presents a concise and coherent overview of Locke, ideal
for second- or third-year undergraduates who require more than just
a simple introduction to his work and thought. John Locke is a
clear and lucid writer who wrote on many subjects and founded many
new schools of thought. Yet, while his work is not impossible to
read, his thought is sufficiently subtle, complex and intricate
that he can be agonizingly hard to follow, presenting students of
philosophy with a number of difficulties and challenges. "Locke: A
Guide for the Perplexed" is a clear and thorough account of Locke's
philosophy, his major works and ideas, providing an ideal guide to
the important and complex thought of this key philosopher. The book
covers the whole range of Locke's philosophical work, offering a
thematic review of his thought, together with detailed examination
of his landmark text, "An Essay Concerning Human Understanding".
Geared towards the specific requirements of students who need to
reach a sound understanding of Locke's thought, the book provides a
cogent and reliable survey of his life, political context and
philosophical influences, and clearly and concisely reviews the
competing interpretations of the Essay. This is the ideal companion
to the study of this most influential and challenging of
philosophers. "Continuum's Guides for the Perplexed" are clear,
concise and accessible introductions to thinkers, writers and
subjects that students and readers can find especially challenging
- or indeed downright bewildering. Concentrating specifically on
what it is that makes the subject difficult to grasp, these books
explain and explore key themes and ideas, guiding the reader
towards a thorough understanding of demanding material.
Gillian Rose is among the twentieth century's most important social
philosophers. In perhaps her most significant work, Hegel Contra
Sociology, Rose mounts a forceful defence of Hegelian speculative
thought. Demonstrating how, in his criticisms of Kant and Fichte,
Hegel supplies a preemptive critique of Weber, Durkheim, and all of
the sociological traditions that stem from these "neo-Kantian"
thinkers, Rose argues that any attempt to preserve Marxism from a
similar critique and any attempt to renew sociology cannot succeed
without coming to terms with Hegel's own speculative discourse.
With an analysis of Hegel's mature works in light of his early
radical writings, this book represents a profound step toward
enacting just such a return to the Hegelian.
This work offers a concise and accessible introduction to the key
empiricists of the 17th and 18th centuries, ideal for undergraduate
students. Empiricism is one of the most widely discussed topics in
philosophy. Students regularly encounter the well known opposition
between rationalism and empiricism - the clash between reason and
experience as sources of knowledge and ideas - at an early stage in
their studies. "The Empiricists: A Guide for the Perplexed" offers
a clear and thorough guide to the key thinkers responsible for
developing this central concept in the history of philosophy. The
book focuses on the canonical figures of the empiricist movement,
Locke, Berkeley and Hume, but also explores the contributions made
by other key figures such as Bacon, Hobbes, Boyle and
Newton.Laurence Carlin presents the views of these hugely
influential thinkers in the context of the Scientific Revolution,
the intellectual movement in which they emerged, and explores in
detail the philosophical issues that were central to their work.
Specifically designed to meet the needs of students seeking a
thorough understanding of the topic, this book is the ideal guide
to a key concept in the history of philosophy. "Continuum's Guides
for the Perplexed" are clear, concise and accessible introductions
to thinkers, writers and subjects that students and readers can
find especially challenging - or indeed downright bewildering.
Concentrating specifically on what it is that makes the subject
difficult to grasp, these books explain and explore key themes and
ideas, guiding the reader towards a thorough understanding of
demanding material.
This is a collection of Paul Hoffman's wide-ranging essays on
Descartes composed over the past twenty-five years. The essays in
Part I include his celebrated "The Unity of Descartes' Man," in
which he argues that Descartes accepts the Aristotelian view that
soul and body are related as form to matter and that the human
being is a substance; a series of subsequent essays elaborating on
this interpretation and defending it against objections; and an
essay on Descartes' theory of distinction. In the essays in Part II
he argues that Descartes retains the Aristotelian theory of
causation according to which an agent's action is the same as the
passion it brings about, and explains the significance of this
doctrine for understanding Descartes' dualism and physics. In the
essays in Part III he argues that Descartes accepts the
Aristotelian theory of cognition according to which perception is
possible because things that exist in the world are also capable of
a different way of existing in the soul, and he shows how this
theory figures in Descartes' account of misrepresentation and in
the controversy over whether Descartes is a direct realist or a
representationalist. The essays in Part IV examine Descartes'
theory of the passions of the soul: their definition; their effect
on our happiness, virtue, and freedom; and methods of controlling
them.
|
You may like...
The Coven
Lizzie Fry
Paperback
R451
R414
Discovery Miles 4 140
|