|
Showing 1 - 4 of
4 matches in All Departments
Roman Ingarden's very extensive philosophical work in metaphysics,
ontology, epistemology, and aesthetics con tinues to attract
increasing attention both in Poland and in North America. Further
work left uncompleted at his death is appearing. Major
bibliographies of his work as well as of studies about his work are
now in print. Ingar den's scattered articles on various questions
in philosophy are being collected. And conferences devoted to his
work are now held regularly. These diverse activities might suggest
a similar diver sity in Ingarden's philosophical legacy. But such a
sugges tion would be misleading. For interest in Ingarden's work
has continued to centre on the one area which is arguably at the
core of his achievement, namely the complex prob lems of
aesthetics. In this field Ingarden seemed to pull together his
various interests in ontology and epistemology especially. Here he
brought those interests to focus on a set of issues that would
occupy him creatively throughout the vicissitudes of his long and
difficult scholarly life. More over, aesthetics is also the field
where Ingarden perhaps most succeeded in orchestrating the many
themes he owed to his phenomenological training while finally
transposing the central issues into something original, something
dis tinctively his own that philosophers can no longer identify as
merely phenomenological. Ingarden's aesthetics not surprisingly has
captured the interest today of many scholars in different fields."
The book offers an extensive and detailed philosophical analysis of
the phenomenon of the comic. The author critically presents the
hitherto existing theories of the comic from Aristotle up to the
present and classifies them. At the same time he advances his own
definition of the comic as a broadly understood deviation from
norm, which takes into account the deviation from an objectively
existing norm as well as the subjective sense of the normal. Many
pages have been devoted to the analysis of the main forms of the
comic. The author offers their taxonomy and discusses the major
techniques of evoking the comic. The final part of the book deals
with the social aspects of the comic and discusses the social role
of humour, mockery, satire, irony, etc. The author elaborates on
the educational, integrating, punitive, and therapeuric aspects of
various forms of comic activities. The book is based upon ample
material drawn from a multitude of sources. The author does not
limit the scope of his analysis to the philosophical and the
aesthetic aspects of the comic but takes into account its
extra-aesthetic occurrences and applications as presented by
psychologists, cultural anthropologists, sociologists,
theoreticians and historians of literature, film, and music, which
makes the work truly interdisciplinary in character. The Comical: A
Philosophical Analysis will be useful to aestheticians and
philosophers of art, as well as to the students of literary
criticism, theatre, and film studies, educational theory,
psychology and even the theory of argumentation.
The problem of the comical is one of the most interesting issues in
aesthetics. Its significance extends well beyond the sphere of
aesthetic studies and has at tracted the attention of the scholars
working in other fields such as the theorists and historians of
particular art forms, sociologists, psychologists, as well as
anthropologists, ethnographers and the theorists of education.
Philosophy has devoted a lot of attention to the comical. Since
Aristotle al most every philosopher has felt obliged to comment on
this question. However, even though they have offered a number of
accurate observations on the subject, the philosophers involved in
the discussion about the comical have earned a reputation of being
rather devoid of the sense of the comical and many a time their
considerations have been compared to those of a blind man talking
about colours. And yet the problem of the comical kept attracting
them to such an ex tent that they paid no heed to the difficulties
involved and neglected the risk of becoming ridiculous themselves.
Adolf Zeissing once remarked that all the litera ture on the
comical is a "comedy of errors" committed while defining the comi
cal. Yet even he could not resist the temptation of adding another
page to this "comedy of errors." Tadeusz Boy-Zeleriski claimed that
the good thing about the philosophical writing concerning the
comical is that it offers not only the theory of the comical but at
the same time is the theory's practical application."
Roman Ingarden's very extensive philosophical work in metaphysics,
ontology, epistemology, and aesthetics con tinues to attract
increasing attention both in Poland and in North America. Further
work left uncompleted at his death is appearing. Major
bibliographies of his work as well as of studies about his work are
now in print. Ingar den's scattered articles on various questions
in philosophy are being collected. And conferences devoted to his
work are now held regularly. These diverse activities might suggest
a similar diver sity in Ingarden's philosophical legacy. But such a
sugges tion would be misleading. For interest in Ingarden's work
has continued to centre on the one area which is arguably at the
core of his achievement, namely the complex prob lems of
aesthetics. In this field Ingarden seemed to pull together his
various interests in ontology and epistemology especially. Here he
brought those interests to focus on a set of issues that would
occupy him creatively throughout the vicissitudes of his long and
difficult scholarly life. More over, aesthetics is also the field
where Ingarden perhaps most succeeded in orchestrating the many
themes he owed to his phenomenological training while finally
transposing the central issues into something original, something
dis tinctively his own that philosophers can no longer identify as
merely phenomenological. Ingarden's aesthetics not surprisingly has
captured the interest today of many scholars in different fields."
|
|