|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500
Greek Heroes in and out of Hades is a study on heroism and
mortality from Homer to Plato. In a collection of thirty enjoyable
essays, Stamatia Dova combines intertextual research and
thought-provoking analysis to shed new light on concepts of the
hero in the Iliad and the Odyssey, Bacchylides 5, Plato's
Symposium, and Euripides' Alcestis. Through systematic readings of
a wide range of seemingly unrelated texts, the author offers a
cohesive picture of heroic character in a variety of literary
genres. Her characterization of Achilles, Odysseus, and Heracles is
artfully supported by a comprehensive overview of the theme of
descent to the underworld in Homer, Bacchylides, and Euripides.
Aimed at the specialist as well as the general reader, Greek Heroes
in and out of Hades brings innovative Classical scholarship and
insightful literary criticism to a wide audience.
Maximus the Confessor (c.580-662) has become one of the most
discussed figures in contemporary patristic studies. This is partly
due to the relatively recent discovery and critical edition of his
works in various genres, including On the Ascetic Life, Four
Centuries on Charity, Two Centuries on Theology and the
Incarnation, On the 'Our Father', two separate Books of
Difficulties, addressed to John and to Thomas, Questions and
Doubts, Questions to Thalassius, Mystagogy and the Short
Theological and Polemical Works. The impact of these works reached
far beyond the Greek East, with his involvement in the western
resistance to imperial heresy, notably at the Lateran Synod in 649.
Together with Pope Martin I (649-53 CE), Maximus the Confessor and
his circle were the most vocal opponents of Constantinople's
introduction of the doctrine of monothelitism. This dispute over
the number of wills in Christ became a contest between the imperial
government and church of Constantinople on the one hand, and the
bishop of Rome in concert with eastern monks such as Maximus, John
Moschus, and Sophronius, on the other, over the right to define
orthodoxy. An understanding of the difficult relations between
church and state in this troubled period at the close of Late
Antiquity is necessary for a full appreciation of Maximus'
contribution to this controversy. The editors of this volume aim to
provide the political and historical background to Maximus'
activities, as well as a summary of his achievements in the spheres
of theology and philosophy, especially neo-Platonism and
Aristotelianism.
This book (hardcover) is part of the TREDITION CLASSICS. It
contains classical literature works from over two thousand years.
Most of these titles have been out of print and off the bookstore
shelves for decades. The book series is intended to preserve the
cultural legacy and to promote the timeless works of classical
literature. Readers of a TREDITION CLASSICS book support the
mission to save many of the amazing works of world literature from
oblivion. With this series, tredition intends to make thousands of
international literature classics available in printed format again
- worldwide.
Aristotle described the scientific explanation of universal or
general facts as deducing them through scientific demonstrations,
that is, through syllogisms that met requirements of logical
validity and explanatoriness which he first formulated. In Chapters
19-23, he adds arguments for the further logical restrictions that
scientific demonstrations can neither be indefinitely long nor
infinitely extendible through the interposition of new middle
terms. Chapters 24-26 argue for the superiority of universal over
particular demonstration, of affirmative over negative
demonstration, and of direct negative demonstration over
demonstration to the impossible. Chapters 27-34 discuss different
aspects of sciences and scientific understanding, allowing us to
distinguish between sciences, and between scientific understanding
and other kinds of cognition, especially opinion. Philoponus'
comments on these chapters are interesting especially because of
his metaphysical analysis of universal predication and his
understanding of the notion of subordinate sciences. We learn from
his commentary that Philoponus believed in Platonic Forms as
inherent in, and posterior to, the Divine Intellect, but ascribed
to Aristotle an interpretation of Plato's Forms as independent
substances, prior to the Demiurgic Intellect. A very important
notion from Aristotle's Posterior Analytics is that of the
'subordination' of sciences, i.e. the idea that some sciences
depend on 'higher' ones for some of their principles. Philoponus
goes beyond Aristotle in suggesting a taxonomy of sciences, in
which the subordinate science concerns the same scientific genus as
the superordinate, but a different species.
Exploring the political ideology of Republicanism under the Roman
emperors of the first century AD, Sam Wilkinson puts forward the
hypothesis that there was indeed opposition to the political
structure and ideology of the rulers on the grounds of
Republicanism. While some Romans wanted a return to the Republic,
others wanted the emperor to ensure his reign was as close to
Republican moral and political ideology as possible. Analysing the
discourse of the period, the book charts how the view of law,
morality and behaviour changed under the various Imperial regimes
of the first century AD. Uniquely, this book explores how emperors
could choose to set their regime in a more Republican or more
Imperial manner, thus demonstrating it was possible for both the
opposition and an emperor to be Republican. The book concludes by
providing evidence of Republicanism in the first century AD which
not only created opposition to the emperors, but also became part
of the political debate in this period.
When the Romans adopted Greek literary genres, artistic techniques,
and iconographies, they did not slavishly imitate their models.
Rather, the Romans created vibrant and original literature and art.
The same is true for philosophy, though the rich Roman
philosophical tradition is still too often treated as a mere
footnote to the history of Greek philosophy. This volume aims to
reassert the significance of Roman philosophy and to explore the
"Romanness" of philosophical writings and practices in the Roman
world. The contributors reveal that the Romans, in their creative
adaptation of Greek modes of thought, developed sophisticated forms
of philosophical discourse shaped by their own history and
institutions, concepts and values-and last, but not least, by the
Latin language, which nearly all Roman philosophers used to express
their ideas. The thirteen chapters-which are authored by an
international group of specialists in ancient philosophy, Latin
literature, and Roman social and intellectual history-move from
Roman attitudes to and practices of philosophy to the great late
Republican writers Cicero and Lucretius, then onwards to the early
Empire and the work of Seneca the Younger, and finally to
Epictetus, Apuleius, and Augustine. Using a variety of approaches,
the essays do not combine into one grand narrative but instead
demonstrate the diversity and originality of the Roman
philosophical discourse over the centuries.
Although the Greeks were responsible for the first systematic
philosophy of which we have any record, they were not alone in the
Mediterranean world and were happy to draw inspiration from other
traditions; traditions that are now largely neglected by
philosophers and scholars. This book tells the story of 'Greek
Philosophy', paying due attention to its historical context and the
contributions made by Egyptians, Hebrews, Persians and even
barbarians from northern Europe. Stephen Clark provides a narrative
history of the philosophical traditions that took shape over
several centuries in the Mediterranean world and offers a
comprehensive survey of this crucial period in the history of
philosophy. The book includes a thorough historical and
philosophical overview of all the key thinkers, events and ideas
that characterized the period and explores in detail central themes
such as the contest of gods and giants, the contrast between the
reality and appearance, and the idea of the philosopher. Ideal for
undergraduate students, this concise and accessible book provides a
comprehensive guide to a fascinating period in the history of
philosophy.>
Both our view of Seneca's philosophical thought and our approach to
the ancient consolatory genre have radically changed since the
latest commentary on the Consolatio ad Marciam was written in 1981.
The aim of this work is to offer a new book-length commentary on
the earliest of Seneca's extant writings, along with a revision of
the Latin text and a reassessment of Seneca's intellectual program,
strategies, and context. A crucial document to penetrate Seneca's
discourse on the self in its embryonic stages, the Ad Marciam is
here taken seriously as an engaging attempt to direct the
persuasive power of literary models and rhetorical devices toward
the fundamentally moral project of healing Marcia's grief and
correcting her cognitive distortions. Through close reading of the
Latin text, this commentary shows that Seneca invariably adapts
different traditions and voices - from Greek consolations to
Plato's dialogues, from the Roman discourse of gender and
exemplarity to epic poetry - to a Stoic framework, so as to give
his reader a lucid understanding of the limits of the self and the
ineluctability of natural laws.
Ibn Bagga's commentary on Aristotle's On Generation and Corruption
(Kitab al-Kawn wa-l-fasad, Latin De generatione et corruptione) is
one of the first commentaries to elaborate on the essential aspect
of Aristotle's text, that is, the analysis of change ( , tagayyur).
The commentary's extant parts comprise a consecutive exposition of
the contents of Aristotle's work. However, the commentary may be
read more as an introduction or a guide to the topic of generation
than as a substitution for the original, as the paraphrases by
Averroes seem to have become in the later tradition. The present
study provides a new critical edition of the Arabic text and, for
the first time, an English translation and a study of the structure
of the commentary on the basis of the only two known manuscripts.
Aristotle's theory of eternal continuous motion and his argument
from everlasting change and motion to the existence of an unmoved
primary cause of motion, provided in book VIII of his Physics, is
one of the most influential and persistent doctrines of ancient
Greek philosophy. Nevertheless, the exact wording of Aristotle's
discourse is doubtful and contentious at many places. The present
critical edition of Ishaq ibn Hunayn's Arabic translation (9th c.)
is supposed to replace the faulty edition by A. Badawi and aims at
contributing to the clarification of these textual difficulties by
means of a detailed collation of the Arabic text with the most
important Greek manuscripts, supported by comprehensive Greek and
Arabic glossaries.
In this part of the Posterior Analytics, Aristotle elaborates his
assessment of how universal truths of science can be scientifically
explained as inevitable in demonstrative proofs. But he introduces
complications: some sciences discuss phenomena that can only be
explained by higher sciences and again sometimes we reason out a
cause from an effect, rather than an effect from a cause.
Philoponus takes these issues further. Reasoning from particular to
universal is the direction taken by induction, and in mathematics
reasoning from a theorem to the higher principles from which it
follows is considered particularly valuable. It corresponds to the
direction of analysis, as opposed to synthesis. This volume
contains an English translation of Philoponus' commentary, a
detailed introduction, extensive explanatory notes and a
bibliography.
This study focuses on the metaphysics of the great Arabic
philosopher Avicenna (or Ibn Sina, d. 1037 C.E.). More
specifically, it delves into Avicenna's theory of quiddity or
essence, a topic which seized the attention of thinkers both during
the medieval and modern periods. Building on recent contributions
in Avicennian studies, this book proposes a new and comprehensive
interpretation of Avicenna's theory of 'the pure quiddity' (also
known as 'the quiddity in itself') and of its ontology. The study
provides a careful philological analysis of key passages gleaned
from the primary sources in Arabic and a close philosophical
contextualization of Avicenna's doctrines in light of the legacy of
ancient Greek philosophy in Islam and the early development of
Arabic philosophy (falsafah) and theology (kalam). The study pays
particular attention to how Avicenna's theory of quiddity relates
to the ancient Greek philosophical discussion about the universals
or common things and Mu'tazilite ontology. Its main thesis is that
Avicenna articulated a sophisticated doctrine of the ontology of
essence in light of Greek and Bahshamite sources, which decisively
shaped subsequent intellectual history in Islam and the Latin West.
In the Politics, Aristotle sets out to discover what is the best
form that the state can take. Similar to his mentor Plato,
Aristotle considers the form that will produce justice and
cultivate the highest human potential; however Aristotle takes a
more empirical approach, examining the constitution of existing
states and drawing on specific case-studies. In doing so he lays
the foundations of modern political science. This Readers Guide is
the ideal companion to this most influential of texts offering
guidance on: Philosophical and historical context Key themes
Reading the text Reception and influence Further reading
|
|