|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500
In this book, Kevin M. Cherry compares the views of Plato and
Aristotle about the practice, study, and, above all, the purpose of
politics. The first scholar to place Aristotle's Politics in
sustained dialogue with Plato's Statesman, Cherry argues that
Aristotle rejects the view of politics advanced by Plato's Eleatic
Stranger, contrasting them on topics such as the proper
categorization of regimes, the usefulness and limitations of the
rule of law, and the proper understanding of phron sis. The various
differences between their respective political philosophies,
however, reflect a more fundamental difference in how they view the
relationship of human beings to the natural world around them.
Reading the Politics in light of the Statesman sheds new light on
Aristotle's political theory and provides a better understanding of
Aristotle's criticism of Socrates. Most importantly, it highlights
an enduring and important question: Should politics have as its
primary purpose the preservation of life, or should it pursue the
higher good of living well?"
|
Meditations
(Hardcover)
Marcus Aurelius; Translated by George Long
|
R553
Discovery Miles 5 530
|
Ships in 12 - 17 working days
|
|
Constantly regard the universe as one living being, having one
substance and one soul; and observe how all things have reference
to one perception, the perception of this one living being; and how
all things act with one movement; and how all things are the
cooperating causes of all things which exist; observe too the
continuous spinning of the thread and the contexture of the web.A"
Marcus Aurelius - 'Meditations' Marcus Aurelius is considered to
one of the great Emperors of Rome who was not only a skilled
military leader but also a great philosopher in the Stoic
tradition. He was born in 121 AD and both of his parents came from
wealthy backgrounds. His father died when Marcus was 3 years old
and by the time he was 6 he had gained the attention of the Emperor
Hadrian who oversaw his education. Hadrian ensured that Marcus was
taught by some of the greatest scholars in Rome who educated him in
literature, drama, geometry, Greek oratory, Greek and Latin. Marcus
later abandoned most of those subjects in favor of philosophy, with
the work of the Greek philosopher Epictetus being a major influence
on his thinking. In 138, while still a young man, the Emperor
Antoninus Pius adopted Marcus, and in 161 he himself became
Emperor. Marcus insisted he would only take up the Emperorship if
Lucius Verus were also installed. Marcus's insistence on Lucius
joining him as Emperor was a military one. At that time Rome was
fighting wars on multiple fronts and Marcus wanted someone he could
trust to marshal the troops who he knew would not at some point
lead a revolt against him. Lucius and Marcus were loyal to each
other up until Lucius's death in 169 AD. After Lucius's death,
Marcus was the sole Emperor and due to the incessant wars in the
provinces he was unable to spend much time indulging his
philosophical pursuits. He did manage to found four Chairs of
Philosophy in Athens, one for each of the main philosophical
schools of thought, Aristotelian, Epicurean, Platonic and Stoic.
Although Marcus spent almost all of his reign on campaigns in
foreign territories, he managed to write down his thoughts and
these became what are now considered a masterpiece of Roman
philosophy, the discourses 'Meditations'. Marcus wrote
'Meditations' around 170 - 180, whilst on a campaign in central
Europe, most probably in what is now Serbia, Hungary and Austria.
The 12 books that make up 'Meditations' were not written as an
exercise in explaining his philosophy but rather as a personal
notebook for self-improvement and study. 'Meditations' illustrates
just how important Epictetus was to Marcus as he quotes the Greek
philosopher's famed 'Discourses' on more than one occasion.
Epictetus was a legendary figure in Greek philosophy and many claim
he is the greatest of the Stoics; texts that remain in existence
from the period suggest that in his native Greece, he was even more
popular than Plato. As was previously mentioned, 'Meditations' was
not written for public consumption but rather as an aid to personal
development. Marcus wanted to change his way of living and thinking
and to do this he embarked on a set of philosophical exercises. He
would reflect on philosophical ideas and by writing them down and
by repeating them he hoped to re-programme his mind and find his
own philosophy to live by. One of the key exercises in the book
discusses Marcus attempting to look at the world from 'the point of
view of the cosmos' in a bid to try and look at life and the
universe outside of the common and limited parameters of individual
concerns. You have the power to strip away many superfluous
troubles located wholly in your judgment, and to possess a large
room for yourself embracing in thought the whole cosmos, to
consider everlasting time, to think of the rapid change in the
parts of each thing, of how short it is from birth until
dissolution, and how the void before birth and that after
dissolution are equally infinite.A" Marcus Aurelius died on March
17, 180, in the city of Vindobona which was situated where Vienna
is today. History remembers him as the last of the 'Five Good
Emperors' of the Nervan-Antonian dynasty. Marcus' son Commodus
replaced his father as Emperor and although he reigned over a
relatively stable period in Roman history, in terms of war and
peace, his personal behavior and antics were not in the spirit of
those Emperors that came immediately before him. Commodus was
eventually murdered in a plot that involved his mistress Marcia,
thus bringing to an end the highly regarded Nervan-Antonian
dynasty.
|
The Republic
(Paperback)
Plato; Foreword by Simon Blackburn; Translated by Benjamin Jowett
|
R206
R191
Discovery Miles 1 910
Save R15 (7%)
|
Ships in 10 - 15 working days
|
|
Packaged in handsome, affordable trade editions, Clydesdale
Classics is a new series of essential works. From the musings of
intellectuals such as Thomas Paine in Common Sense to the striking
personal narrative of Harriet Jacobs in Incidents in the Life of a
Slave Girl, this new series is a comprehensive collection of our
intellectual history through the words of the exceptional few.
Originating in approximately 380 BC, Republic is a Socratic
dialogue written by famed Greek philosopher Plato. Often referred
to as Plato's masterwork, Republic's central goal is to define the
ideal state. By conceptualizing this model state, Greeks believed
it would lead states formed with its principles in mind to function
the most efficiently and fairly, striving toward justice and the
greater good of society. This edition includes a foreword by
British American philosopher and Plato expert Simon Blackburn.
Widely read around the world by philosophy students and academics
alike, Plato's Republic is sure to pass on its invaluable lessons
and enlighten the next generation of thinkers.
Anonymous' and Stephanus' commentaries, written in the 12th century
AD, are the first surviving commentaries on Aristotle's Rhetoric.
Their study, including the environment in which they were written
and the philosophical ideas expressed in them, provides a better
understanding of the reception of Aristotle's Rhetoric in
Byzantium, the Byzantine practice of commenting on classical texts,
and what can be called "Byzantine philosophy". For the first time,
this book explores the context of production of the commentaries,
discusses the identity and features of their authors, and reveals
their philosophical and philological significance. In particular, I
examine the main topics discussed by Aristotle in the Rhetoric as
contributing to persuasion, namely valid and fallacious rhetorical
arguments, ethical notions, emotional response and style, and I
analyse the commentators' interpretations of these topics. In this
analysis, I focus on highlighting the value of the philosophical
views expressed, and on creating a discussion between the Byzantine
and the modern interpretations of the treatise. Conclusively, the
two commentators need to be considered as independent thinkers, who
aimed primarily at integrating the treatise within the Aristotelian
philosophical system.
Elijah Del Medigo (1458-1493) was a Jewish Aristotelian philosopher
living in Padua, whose work influenced many of the leading
philosophers of the early Renaissance. His Two Investigations on
the Nature of the Human Soul uses Aristotle's De anima to theorize
on two of the most discussed and most controversial philosophical
debates of the Renaissance: the nature of human intellect and the
obtaining of immortality through intellectual perfection. In this
book, Michael Engel places Del Medigo's philosophical work and his
ideas about the human intellect within the context of the wider
Aristotelian tradition. Providing a detailed account of the unique
blend of Hebrew, Islamic, Latin and Greek traditions that
influenced the Two Investigations, Elijah Del Medigo and Paduan
Aristotelianism provides an important contribution to our
understanding of Renaissance Aristotelianisms and scholasticisms.
In particular, through his defense of the Muslim philosopher
Averroes' hotly debated interpretation of the De anima and his
rejection of the moderate Latin Aristotelianism championed by the
Christian Thomas Aquinas, Engel traces how Del Medigo's work on the
human intellect contributed to the development of a major
Aristotelian controversy. Investigating the ways in which
multicultural Aristotelian sources contributed to his own theory of
a united human intellect, Elijah Del Medigo and Paduan
Aristotelianism demonstrates the significant impact made by this
Jewish philosopher on the history of the Aristotelian tradition.
This book concentrates on the conversation between Socrates and
Gorgias which takes place in the first part of Plato's Gorgias.
Scholars have tended to concentrate on the following two
conversations held by Socrates with Polus and, especially, with
Callicles. This first, relatively short, conversation is usually
taken to be a kind of preface coming before Plato's 'real'
philosophy. The present study challenges this assumption, arguing
that the conversation between Socrates and Gorgias actually
anticipates the message of the whole dialogue, which concerns the
essence of rhetoric and its implications.
William Desmond, taking issue with common popular and scholarly
views of the ancient Greek Cynics, contends that early Cynics like
Antisthenes and Diogenes were not cultural outcasts or marginal
voices in classical culture; rather, the Cynic movement through the
fourth century B.C. had deep and significant roots in what Desmond
calls "the Greek praise of poverty." Desmond demonstrates that
classical views of wealth were complex and allowed for the
admiration of poverty and the virtues it could inspire. He explains
Cynicism's rise in popularity in the ancient world by exploring the
set of attitudes that collectively formed the Greek praise of
poverty. Desmond argues that in the fifth and fourth centuries
B.C., economic, political, military, and philosophical thought
contained explicit criticisms of wealth and praise of poverty. From
an economic and political point of view, the poor majority at
Athens and elsewhere were natural democrats who distrusted great
concentrations of wealth as potentially oligarchical or tyrannical.
In contemporary literature, the poor are those who do most of the
necessary work and are honest, self-sufficient, and temperate. The
rich, on the other hand, are idle, arrogant, and unjust. These
perspectives were reinforced by the Greek experience of war and the
belief that poverty fostered the virtues of courage, strength, and
endurance. Finally, from an early date, Greek philosophers
associated wisdom with the transcendence of sense experience and of
conventional values such as wealth and honor. The Cynics, Desmond
asserts, assimilated all of these ideas in creating their
distinctive and radical brand of asceticism. Desmond's work is a
compelling reevaluation of ancient Cynicism and its classical
environment, one that makes an important contribution to
scholarship of the classical and early Hellenistic periods.
It is widely agreed that Plato laid the foundations for the whole
history of western thought and, well over 2000 years later, his
work is still studied by every student of philosophy. Yet his
thought and writings continue to evoke perplexity in readers; and
perplexity (aporia) is itself a characteristic of many of his
writings, a recurrent motif of his thought, and apparently an
important stage one must pass through along the path to wisdom that
Plato presents. Plato: A Guide for the Perplexed is a clear and
thorough account of Plato's philosophy, his major works and ideas,
providing an ideal guide to the important and complex thought of
this key philosopher. The book offers a detailed review of all the
major dialogues and explores the particular perplexities of the
dialogue form. Geared towards the specific requirements of students
who need to reach a sound understanding of Plato's thought, the
book also provides a cogent and reliable survey of the whole
history of Platonic interpretation and his far-reaching influence.
This is the ideal companion to the study of this most influential
and challenging of philosophers.
Plato was central both to the genesis of Stoic theory and to
subsequent debates within the Stoa. These essays provide new and
detailed explorations of the complex relationship between Plato and
the Greek and Roman Stoic traditions, and together they show the
directness and independence with which Stoics examined Plato's
writing. What were the philosophical incentives to consulting and
then returning to Plato's dialogues? To what extent did Plato,
rather than Xenophon or Antisthenes, control Stoic reconstructions
of Socrates' ethics? What explains the particular focus of Stoic
polemic against Plato, and how strong is the evidence for a later
reconciliation between Plato and Stoicism? This book will be
important for all scholars and advanced students interested in the
relationship between a major philosopher and one of the most
important philosophical movements.
Written by a group of leading scholars, this unique collection of
essays investigates the views of both pagan and Christian
philosophers on causation and the creation of the cosmos.
Structured in two parts, the volume first looks at divine agency
and how late antique thinkers, including the Stoics, Plotinus,
Porphyry, Simplicius, Philoponus and Gregory of Nyssa, tackled
questions such as: is the cosmos eternal? Did it come from nothing
or from something pre-existing? How was it caused to come into
existence? Is it material or immaterial? The second part looks at
questions concerning human agency and responsibility, including the
problem of evil and the nature of will, considering thinkers such
as Plotinus, Porphyry, Proclus and Augustine. Highlighting some of
the most important and interesting aspects of these philosophical
debates, the volume will be of great interest to upper-level
students and scholars of philosophy, classics, theology and ancient
history.
Early modern philosophers looked for inspiration to the later ancient thinkers when they rebelled against the dominant Platonic and Aristotelian traditions. The impact of the Hellenistic philosophers on such philosophers as Descartes, Leibniz, Spinoza, and Locke was profound and is ripe for reassessment. These new essays offer precisely that. Leading historians of philosophy explore the connections between Hellenistic and early modern philosophy by taking account of new scholarly and philosophical advances in these essays. There work provides invaluable point of reference for philosophers, historians of ideas and classicists.
This is a student-friendly introduction to a key text in Ancient
Philosophy. In many regards the dialectical counterpart of the
"Republic, the Symposium" is one of the richest and most
influential of the Platonic dialogues, resonating not only with
Western philosophy, but also with literature art and theology.
While Plato ostensibly dramatizes a humorous account of a drinking
party, he presents a profoundly serious explication of Eros that
challenges the limits of reason, the nature of gender, identity and
narrative form. "Plato's Symposium: A Reader's Guide" presents a
concise introduction to the text, offering invaluable guidance on:
historical, literary and philosophical context; key themes; reading
the text; reception and influence; and, further reading. "Continuum
Reader's Guides" are clear, concise and accessible introductions to
key texts in literature and philosophy. Each book explores the
themes, context, criticism and influence of key works, providing a
practical introduction to close reading, guiding students towards a
thorough understanding of the text. They provide an essential,
up-to-date resource, ideal for undergraduate students.
Becoming god was an ideal of many ancient Greek philosophers, as
was the life of reason, which they equated with divinity. This book
argues that their rival accounts of this equation depended on their
divergent attitudes toward time. Affirming it, Heraclitus developed
a paradoxical style of reasoning--"chiasmus"--that was the activity
of his becoming god. Denying it as contradictory, Parmenides sought
to purify thinking of all contradiction, offering eternity to those
who would follow him. Plato did, fusing this pure style of
reasoning--consistency--with a Pythagorean program of purification
and divinization that would then influence philosophers from
Aristotle to Kant. Those interested in Greek philosophical and
religious thought will find fresh interpretations of its early
figures, as well as a lucid presentation of the first and most
influential attempts to link together divinity, rationality, and
selfhood.
This title presents an exploration of the life and philosophical
reflections of this complex Stoic philosopher and Roman emperor.
This book is a clear and concise introduction to the Roman Emperor
Marcus Aurelius Antoninus. His one major surviving work, often
titled 'meditations' but literally translated simply as 'to
himself', is a series of short, sometimes enigmatic reflections
divided seemingly arbitrarily into twelve books and apparently
written only to be read by him. For these reasons Marcus is a
particularly difficult thinker to understand. His musings, framed
as 'notes to self' or 'memoranda', are the exhortations of an
earnest, conscientious Stoic burdened with the onerous
responsibilities of ruling an entire empire. William O. Stephens
lucidly sketches Marcus Aurelius' upbringing, family relations,
rise to the throne, military campaigns, and legacy, situating his
philosophy amidst his life and times, explicating the factors
shaping Marcus' philosophy, and clarifying key themes in the
Memoranda. Specifically designed to meet the needs of students
seeking a thorough understanding of this key figure and his major
work, "Marcus Aurelius: A Guide for the Perplexed" is the ideal
guide for understanding this Stoic author - the only philosopher
who was also an emperor. "Continuum's Guides for the Perplexed" are
clear, concise and accessible introductions to thinkers, writers
and subjects that students and readers can find especially
challenging - or indeed downright bewildering. Concentrating
specifically on what it is that makes the subject difficult to
grasp, these books explain and explore key themes and ideas,
guiding the reader towards a thorough understanding of demanding
material.
Human life is susceptible of changing suddenly, of shifting
inadvertently, of appearing differently, of varying unpredictably,
of being altered deliberately, of advancing fortuitously, of
commencing or ending accidentally, of a certain malleability. In
theory, any human being is potentially capacitated to conceive
of-and convey-the chance, view, or fact that matters may be
otherwise, or not at all; with respect to other lifeforms, this
might be said animal's distinctive characteristic. This state of
play is both an everyday phenomenon, and an indispensable
prerequisite for exceptional innovations in culture and science:
contingency is the condition of possibility for any of the arts-be
they dominantly concerned with thinking, crafting, or enacting.
While their scope and method may differ, the (f)act of reckoning
with-and taking advantage of-contingency renders rhetoricians and
philosophers associates after all. In this regard, Aristotle and
Blumenberg will be exemplary, hence provide the framework. Between
these diachronic bridgeheads, close readings applying the nexus of
rhetoric and contingency to a selection of (Early) Modern texts and
authors are intercalated-among them La Celestina, Machiavelli,
Shakespeare, Wilde, Fontane.
Early Greek Thought calls into question a longstanding mythology -
operative in both the Analytic and Continental traditions - that
the 'Pre-Socratics had the grandiose audacity to break with all
traditional forms of knowledge' (Badiou). Each of the variants of
this mythology is dismantled in an attempt to not only retrieve an
'indigenous' interpretation of early Greek thought, but also to
expose the mythological character of our own contemporary
meta-narratives regarding the 'origins' of 'Western', 'Occidental'
philosophy. Using an original hermeneutical approach, James Luchte
excavates the context ofemergence of early Greek thought through an
exploration of the mytho-poetic horizons of the archaic world, in
relation to which, as Plato testifies, the Greeks were merely
'children'. Luchte discloses 'philosophy in the tragic age' as a
creative response to a 'contestation' of mytho-poetic narratives
and 'ways of being'. The tragic character of early Greek thought is
unfolded through a cultivation of a conversation between its basic
thinkers, one which would remain incomprehensible, with Bataille,
in the 'absence of myth' and the exile of poetry.
Long understudied, Plato's Laws has been the object of renewed
attention in the past decade and is now considered to be his major
work of political philosophy besides the Republic. In his last
dialogue, Plato returns to the project of describing the foundation
of a just city and sketches in considerable detail its
constitution, laws and other social institutions. Written by
leading Platonists, the essays in this volume cover a wide range of
topics central for understanding the Laws, such as the aim of the
Laws as a whole, the ethical psychology of the Laws, especially its
views of pleasure and non-rational motivations, and whether and, if
so, how the strict law code of the Laws can encourage genuine
virtue. They make an important contribution to ongoing debates and
will open up fresh lines of inquiry for further research.
Aristotle's Topics is a handbook for dialectic, which can be
understood as a philosophical debate between a questioner and a
respondent. In book 2, Aristotle mainly develops strategies for
making deductions about 'accidents', which are properties that
might or might not belong to a subject (for instance, Socrates has
five fingers, but might have had six), and about properties that
simply belong to a subject without further specification. In the
present commentary, here translated into English for the first
time, Alexander develops a careful study of Aristotle's text. He
preserves objections and replies from other philosophers whose work
is now lost, such as the Stoics. He also offers an invaluable
picture of the tradition of Aristotelian logic down to his time,
including innovative attempts to unify Aristotle's guidance for
dialectic with his general theory of deductive argument (the
syllogism), found in the Analytics. The work will be of interest
not only for its perspective on ancient logic, rhetoric, and
debate, but also for its continuing influence on argument in the
Middle Ages and later.
|
You may like...
Republic
Plato
Paperback
R95
R76
Discovery Miles 760
|