|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500
This book features a major new critical assessment of Heidegger's
interpretation and political use of Plato's "Republic". Heidegger's
"Platonism" challenges Heidegger's 1940 interpretation of Plato as
the philosopher who initiated the West's ontological decline into
contemporary nihilism. Mark A. Ralkowski argues that, in his
earlier lecture course, "On the Essence of Truth", in which he
appropriates Plato in a positive light, Heidegger discovered the
two most important concepts of his later thought, namely the
difference between the Being of beings and Being as such, and the
'belonging together' of Being and man in what he eventually calls
Ereignis, the 'event of appropriation'. Ralkowski shows that, far
from being the grand villain of metaphysics, Plato was in fact the
gateway to Heidegger's later period. Because Heidegger discovers
the seeds of his later thought in his positive appropriation of
Plato, this book argues that Heidegger's later thought is a return
to and phenomenological transformation of Platonism, which is
ironic not least because Heidegger thought of himself as the West's
first truly post-Platonic philosopher. "Continuum Studies in
Continental Philosophy" presents cutting-edge scholarship in the
field of modern European thought. The wholly original arguments,
perspectives and research findings in titles in this series make it
an important and stimulating resource for students and academics
from across the discipline.
This book deals with some Aristotelian philosophers of the
Hellenistic Age, ranging from Theophrastus of Eresus to Cratippus
of Pergamum. The problem of knowledge, the question of time, and
the doctrine of the soul are investigated by comparing these
Peripatetics' views with Aristotle's philosophy, and above all by
setting their doctrines within the broader framework of
post-Aristotelian and Hellenistic philosophies (the Old Academy,
Epicureanism, and Stoicism).
In archaic societies myths were believed to tell true stories -
stories about the ultimate origin of reality. For us, on the
contrary, the term 'myth' denotes a false belief. Between the
archaic notion of myth and ours stands Plato's. This 2009 volume is
a collection of ten studies by eminent scholars that focus on the
ways in which some of Plato's most famous myths are interwoven with
his philosophy. The myths discussed include the eschatological
myths of the Gorgias, the Phaedo, the Republic and Laws 10, the
central myths of the Phaedrus and the Statesman, and the so-called
myth of the Noble Lie from the Republic. The mythical character of
the Timaeus cosmology is also amply discussed. The volume also
contains seventeen rare Renaissance illustrations of Platonic
myths. The contributors argue that in Plato myth and philosophy are
tightly bound together, despite Plato's occasional claim that they
are opposed modes of discourse.
Pharmakon: Plato, Drug Culture, and Identity in Ancient Athens
examines the emerging concern for controlling states of
psychological ecstasy in the history of western thought, focusing
on ancient Greece (c. 750 - 146 BCE), particularly the Classical
Period (c. 500 - 336 BCE) and especially the dialogues of the
Athenian philosopher Plato (427 - 347 BCE). Employing a diverse
array of materials ranging from literature, philosophy, medicine,
botany, pharmacology, religion, magic, and law, Pharmakon
fundamentally reframes the conceptual context of how we read and
interpret Plato's dialogues. Michael A. Rinella demonstrates how
the power and truth claims of philosophy, repeatedly likened to a
pharmakon, opposes itself to the cultural authority of a host of
other occupations in ancient Greek society who derived their powers
from, or likened their authority to, some pharmakon. These included
Dionysian and Eleusinian religion, physicians and other healers,
magicians and other magic workers, poets, sophists, rhetoricians,
as well as others. Accessible to the general reader, yet
challenging to the specialist, Pharmakon is a comprehensive
examination of the place of drugs in ancient thought that will
compel the reader to understand Plato in a new way.
From Homer to Aristotle, understanding anger and harnessing its
power was at the core of Hellenic civilization. Homer created the
framework for philosophical inquiries into anger, one that
persisted until it was overturned by Stoicism and Christianity.
Plato saw anger as the guardian of justice and Aristotle conceived
of it as bound to friendship. Yet both showed that anger can become
a guardian of injustice and a defender of our psychological
abnormalities. Plato claimed that reason is a tertiary factor in
controlling anger and Aristotle argued that non-cognitive powers
can issue commands for anger's arousal - findings that shed light
as to why cognitive therapeutic approaches often prove to be
ineffective. Both proposed nurturing the "thumos," the receptacle
of anger and the seat of self-esteem. Aristotle's view of public
anger as an early warning sign of social dissolution continues to
be relevant to this day. In this carefully argued study, Kostas
Kalimtzis examines the theories of anger in the context of the
ancient world with an eye to their implications for the modern
predicament.
The philosophical and philological study of Aristotle fragments and
lost works has fallen somewhat into the background since the
1960's. This is regrettable considering the different and
innovative directions the study of Aristotle has taken in the last
decades. This collection of new peer-reviewed essays applies the
latest developments and trends of analysis, criticism, and
methodology to the study of Aristotle's fragments. The individual
essays use the fragments as tools of interpretation, shed new light
on different areas of Aristotle philosophy, and lay bridges between
Aristotle's lost and extant works. The first part shows how
Aristotle frames parts of his own understanding of Philosophy in
his published, 'popular' work. The second part deals with issues of
philosophical interpretation in Aristotle's extant works which can
be illuminated by fragments of his lost works. The philosophical
issues treated in this section range from Theology to Natural
Science, Psychology, Politics, and Poetics. As a whole, the book
articulates a new approach to Aristotle's lost works, by providing
a reassessment and new methodological explorations of the
fragments.
Aristotle and Confucius are pivotal figures in world history;
nevertheless, Western and Eastern cultures have in modern times
largely abandoned the insights of these masters. Remastering Morals
is the first book-length scholarly comparison of the ethics of
Aristotle and Confucius. May Sim's comparisons offer fresh
interpretations of the central teachings of both men. More than a
catalog of similarities and differences, her study brings two great
traditions into dialog so that each is able to learn from the
other. This is essential reading for anyone interested in
virtue-oriented ethics.
In several of the dialogues of Plato, doubts have arisen among his
interpreters as to which of the various subjects discussed in them
is the main thesis. The speakers have the freedom of conversation;
no severe rules of art restrict them, and sometimes we are inclined
to think, with one of the dramatis personae in the Theaetetus, that
the digressions have the greater interest. Yet in the most
irregular of the dialogues there is also a certain natural growth
or unity; the beginning is not forgotten at the end, and numerous
allusions and references are interspersed, which form the loose
connecting links of the whole. We must not neglect this unity, but
neither must we attempt to confine the Platonic dialogue on the
Procrustean bed of a single idea. (Compare Introduction to the
Phaedrus.) Two tendencies seem to have beset the interpreters of
Plato in this matter. First, they have endeavoured to hang the
dia-logues upon one another by the slightest threads; and have thus
been led to opposite and contradictory assertions respec-ting their
order and sequence. The mantle of Schleiermacher has descended upon
his successors, who have applied his method with the most various
results.
The awe with which Plato regarded the character of 'the great'
Parmenides has extended to the dialogue which he calls by his name.
None of the writings of Plato have been more copiously illustrated,
both in ancient and modern times, and in none of them have the
interpreters been more at variance with one another. Nor is this
surprising. For the Parmenides is more fragmentary and isolated
than any other dialogue, and the design of the writer is not
expressly stated. The date is uncertain; the relation to the other
writings of Plato is also uncertain; the connexion between the two
parts is at first sight extremely obscure; and in the latter of the
two we are left in doubt as to whether Plato is speaking his own
sentiments by the lips of Parmenides, and overthrowing him out of
his own mouth, or whether he is propounding consequences which
would have been admitted by Zeno and Parmenides themselves. The
contradictions which follow from the hypotheses of the one and many
have been regarded by some as transcendental mysteries; by others
as a mere illustration, taken at random, of a new method. They seem
to have been inspired by a sort of dialectical frenzy, such as may
be supposed to have prevailed in the Megarian School (compare
Cratylus, etc.). The criticism on his own doctrine of Ideas has
also been considered, not as a real criticism, but as an exuberance
of the metaphysical imagination which enabled Plato to go beyond
himself.
The Cratylus has always been a source of perplexity to the student
of Plato. While in fancy and humour, and perfection of style and
metaphysical originality, this dialogue may be ranked with the best
of the Platonic writings, there has been an uncertainty about the
motive of the piece, which interpreters have hitherto not succeeded
in dispelling. We need not suppose that Plato used words in order
to conceal his thoughts, or that he would have been unintelligible
to an educated contemporary. In the Phaedrus and Euthydemus we also
find a difficulty in determining the precise aim of the author.
Plato wrote satires in the form of dialogues, and his meaning, like
that of other satirical writers, has often slept in the ear of
posterity. Two causes may be assigned for this obscurity: 1st, the
subtlety and allusiveness of this species of composition; 2nd, the
difficulty of reproducing a state of life and literature which has
passed away. A satire is unmeaning unless we can place ourselves
back among the persons and thoughts of the age in which it was
written.
Plato often rejects hedonism, but in the Protagoras, Plato's
Socrates seems to endorse hedonism. In this book, J. Clerk Shaw
removes this apparent tension by arguing that the Protagoras as a
whole actually reflects Plato's anti-hedonism. He shows that Plato
places hedonism at the core of a complex of popular mistakes about
value and especially about virtue: that injustice can be prudent,
that wisdom is weak, that courage is the capacity to persevere
through fear, and that virtue cannot be taught. The masses
reproduce this system of values through shame and fear of
punishment. The Protagoras and other dialogues depict sophists and
orators who have internalized popular morality through shame, but
who are also ashamed to state their views openly. Shaw's reading
not only reconciles the Protagoras with Plato's other dialogues,
but harmonizes it with them and even illuminates Plato's wider
anti-hedonism.
In this important and highly original book, place, commonality and
judgment provide the framework within which works central to the
Greek philosophical and literary tradition are usefully located and
reinterpreted. Greek life, it can be argued, was defined by the
interconnection of place, commonality and judgment. Similarly
within the Continental philosophical tradition topics such as
place, judgment, law and commonality have had a pervasive
centrality. Works by Jacques Derrida and Giorgio Agamben amongst
others attest to the current exigency of these topics. Yet the ways
in which they are interrelated has been barely discussed within the
context of Ancient Philosophy. The conjecture of this book is that
not only are these terms of genuine philosophical importance in
their own right, but they are also central to Ancient Philosophy.
Andrew Benjamin ultimately therefore aims to underscore the
relevance of Ancient Philosophy for contemporary debates in
Continental Philosophy.
This book develops a new account of Socratic method, based on a
psychological model of Plato's dramatic depiction of Socrates'
character and conduct. Socratic method is seen as a blend of three
types of philosophical discourse: refutation, truth-seeking, and
persuasion. Cain focuses on the persuasive features of the method
since, in her view, it is this aspect of Socrates' method that best
explains the content and the value of the dialectical arguments.
Emphasizing the persuasive aspect of Socratic method helps us
uncover the operative standards of dialectical argumentation in
fifth-century Athens. Cain considers both the sophistic style of
rhetoric and contentious debate in Socrates' time, and Aristotle's
perspective on the techniques of argument and their purposes. An
informal, pragmatic analysis of argumentation appropriate to the
dialectical context is developed. We see that Socrates uses
ambiguity and other strategic fallacies with purposeful play, and
for moral ends. Taking specific examples of refutations from
Plato's dialogues, Cain links the interlocutors' characters and
situations with the dialectical argument that Socrates constructs
to refute them. The merit of this interpretation is that it gives
broad range, depth, and balance to Socrates' argumentative style;
it also maintains a keen sensitivity to the interlocutors'
emotional reactions, moral values, and attitudes. The book
concludes with a discussion of the overall value, purpose, and
success of Socratic method, and draws upon a Platonic/Socratic
conception of the soul and a dialectical type of self-knowledge.
This work offers a radical new interpretation of Augustine and of a
central aspect of medieval thought as a whole.Augustine and Roman
Virtue seeks to correct what the author sees as a fundamental
misapprehension in medieval thought, a misapprehension that fuels
further problems and misunderstandings in the historiography of
philosophy. This misapprehension is the assumption that the
development of certain themes associated with medieval philosophy
is due, primarily if not exclusively, to extra-philosophical
religious commitments rather than philosophical argumentation,
referred to here as the 'sacralization thesis'.Brian Harding
explores this problem through a detailed reading of Augustine's
"City of God" as understood in a Latin context, that is, in
dialogue with Latin writers, such as Cicero, Livy, Sallust and
Seneca. The book seeks to revise a common reading of Augustine's
critique of ancient virtue by focusing on that dialogue, while
showing that his attitude towards those authors is more
sympathetic, and more critical, than one might expect. Harding
argues that the criticisms rest on sympathy and that Augustine's
critique of ancient virtue thinks through and develops certain
trends noticeable in the major figures of Latin philosophy.
This book offers a controversial new interpretation of Plato s
Apology of Socrates. By paying unusually close attention to what
Socrates indicates about the meaning and extent of his irony, David
Leibowitz arrives at unconventional conclusions about Socrates
teaching on virtue, politics, and the gods; the significance of his
famous turn from natural philosophy to political philosophy; and
the purpose of his insolent defense speech. Leibowitz shows that
Socrates is not just a colorful and quirky figure from the distant
past but an unrivaled guide to the good life the thoughtful life
who is as relevant today as in ancient Athens. On the basis of his
unconventional understanding of the dialogue as a whole, and of the
Delphic oracle story in particular, Leibowitz also attempts to show
that the Apology is the key to the Platonic corpus, indicating how
many of the disparate themes and apparently contradictory
conclusions of the other dialogues fit together."
|
|