|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500
This work offers a radical new interpretation of Augustine and of a
central aspect of medieval thought as a whole.Augustine and Roman
Virtue seeks to correct what the author sees as a fundamental
misapprehension in medieval thought, a misapprehension that fuels
further problems and misunderstandings in the historiography of
philosophy. This misapprehension is the assumption that the
development of certain themes associated with medieval philosophy
is due, primarily if not exclusively, to extra-philosophical
religious commitments rather than philosophical argumentation,
referred to here as the 'sacralization thesis'.Brian Harding
explores this problem through a detailed reading of Augustine's
"City of God" as understood in a Latin context, that is, in
dialogue with Latin writers, such as Cicero, Livy, Sallust and
Seneca. The book seeks to revise a common reading of Augustine's
critique of ancient virtue by focusing on that dialogue, while
showing that his attitude towards those authors is more
sympathetic, and more critical, than one might expect. Harding
argues that the criticisms rest on sympathy and that Augustine's
critique of ancient virtue thinks through and develops certain
trends noticeable in the major figures of Latin philosophy.
One of the most influential works in the history of political
theory, Aristotle's Politics is a treatise in practical philosophy,
intended to inform legislators and to create the conditions for
virtuous and self-sufficient lives for the citizens of a state. In
this Companion, distinguished scholars offer new perspectives on
the work and its themes. After an opening exploration of the
relation between Aristotle's ethics and his politics, the central
chapters follow the sequence of the eight books of the Politics,
taking up questions such as the role of reason in legitimizing
rule, the common good, justice, slavery, private property,
citizenship, democracy and deliberation, unity, conflict, law and
authority, and education. The closing chapters discuss the
interaction between Aristotle's political thought and contemporary
democratic theory. The volume will provide a valuable resource for
those studying ancient philosophy, classics, and the history of
political thought.
The Republic is a dialogue by Plato in which the famous Athenian
philosopher examines the nature of an ideal society. The insights
are profound and timeless. A landmark of Western literature, The
Republic is essential reading for philosophy students.
This volume presents collected essays - some brand new, some
republished, and others newly translated - on the ancient
commentators on Aristotle and showcases the leading research of the
last three decades. Through the work and scholarship inspired by
Richard Sorabji in his series of translations of the commentators
started in the 1980s, these ancient texts have become a key field
within ancient philosophy. Building on the strength of the series,
which has been hailed as 'a scholarly marvel', 'a truly
breath-taking achievement' and 'one of the great scholarly
achievements of our time' and on the widely praised edited volume
brought out in 1990 (Aristotle Transformed) this new book brings
together critical new scholarship that is a must-read for any
scholar in the field. With a wide range of contributors from across
the globe, the articles look at the commentators themselves,
discussing problems of analysis and interpretation that have arisen
through close study of the texts. Richard Sorabji introduces the
volume and himself contributes two new papers. A key recent area of
research has been into the Arabic, Latin and Hebrew versions of
texts, and several important essays look in depth at these. With
all text translated and transliterated, the volume is accessible to
readers without specialist knowledge of Greek or other languages,
and should reach a wide audience across the disciplines of
Philosophy, Classics and the study of ancient texts.
In this lively and original book, Russell Winslow pursues a new
interpretation of logos in Aristotle. Rather than a reading of
rationality that cleaves human beings from nature, this new
interpretation suggests that, for Aristotle, consistent and
dependable rational arguments reveal a deep dependency upon nature.
To this end, the author shows that a rational account of a being is
in fact subject to the very same principle that governs the
physical motion and generation of a being under inquiry. Among the
many consequences of this argument is a rejection of both of the
prevailing oppositional claims that Aristotle's methodological
procedure of discovery is one resting on either empirical or
conceptual grounds: discovery reveals a more complex structure than
can be grasped by either of these modern modes. Further, Winslow
argues that this interpretation of rational discovery also
contributes to the ethical debates surrounding Aristotle's work,
insofar as an ethical claim is achieved through reason, but is not
thereby conceived as objective. Again, the demand for agreement in
ethical/political decision will be disclosed as superseding in its
complexity both those accounts of ethical decision as subjective
(for example, "emotivist" accounts) and those as objective
("realist" accounts).
The Roman Emperor Marcus Aurelius wrote down his thoughts between
170 and 180. He was a late Stoic Philosopher and this one of the
few examples of this type of literature that exists today. The book
is written as personal notes to himself and his thesis is that one
can obtain inner calm irrespective of outer adversity. The text
considers good and evil, solidarity, adversity and inner freedom.
It is a book that offers wisdom, comfort and inspiration. As well
as the thought, this edition contains a biographical sketch and
summary of the philosophy of Marcus Aurelius, a number of
illustrations and both an index and index of terms.
Julie K. Ward examines Aristotle's thought regarding how language
informs our views of what is real. First she places Aristotle's
theory in its historical and philosophical contexts in relation to
Plato and Speusippus. Ward then explores Aristotle's theory of
language as it is deployed in several works, including Ethics,
Topics, Physics, and Metaphysics, so as to consider its relation to
dialectical practice and scientific explanation as Aristotle
conceived it.
The magnum opus of Plato's writings that detail out the utopia that
Socrates had thought of when debating with his contemporaries in
ancient Greece. While many people have criticized these views over
the years, these ideas have sparked many ideas of what makes
government work and what does not as well as laying down the
foundations for our own democratic systems in the present day.
Socrates has many things to say about people and society in general
making it a very enlightening piece of work.
Galen's treatises on the classification and causation of diseases
and symptoms are an important component of his prodigious oeuvre,
forming a bridge between his theoretical works and his practical,
clinical writings. As such, they remained an integral component of
the medical teaching curriculum well into the second millennium.
This edition was originally published in 2006. In these four
treatises (only one of which had been previously translated into
English), Galen not only provides a framework for the exhaustive
classification of diseases and their symptoms as a prelude to his
analysis of their causation, but he also attempts to establish
precise definitions of all the key terms involved. Unlike other of
his works, these treatises are notably moderate in tone, taking
into account different views on structure and causation in a
relatively even-handed way. Nonetheless, they are a clear statement
of the Dogmatic position on the theoretical foundations of medicine
in his time.
The work of Aristotle (384-322 BC) is considered to be one of the
great achievements of the ancient world, and is a foundation of
both Western and Middle Eastern philosophy and science. Although
Aristotle left significant material on almost all branches of
learning, what has survived is a somewhat disorganized collection
of notes and lectures. Moreover, the centuries of interpretation
across various epochs and cultures tend to cloud our understanding
of him. Thomas Kiefer breaks through this cloud of interpretation
and provides an organized account of one key part of Aristotle's
philosophy, namely his theory of knowledge. This theory concerns
what is knowledge, what we can know, and how we can do so. Kiefer's
book is the first work that takes this theory as its sole focus and
reconstructs it systematically. Kiefer's work throughout provides
many new interpretations of key parts of Aristotle's philosophy,
including an unnoticed -but crucial-distinction between knowledge
in general and knowledge for us, the differences between his
semantic and psychological requirements for knowledge, and 'nous',
which is perhaps the most obscure notion in Aristotle's work. He
also concludes with a summary of Aristotle's theory in the terms
and style of contemporary epistemology. Kiefer's work should be of
interest to anyone involved in the history of philosophy or
contemporary epistemology.
This is the first of a two-volume edition of Alexander of
Aphrodisias' commentary on Aristotle's Metaphysics. The new
edition, which includes a philosophical and philological
introduction, as well as notes on textcritical issues, is based on
a critical evaluation of the entire manuscript tradition of the
commentary. It also takes into account its indirect tradition and
the Latin translation of Juan Gines Sepulveda.
This book offers an introduction to Socrates, ideal for
undergraduate students taking courses in Ancient and Greek
Philosophy. Socrates is regarded as the founder of Western
philosophical inquiry. Yet he left no writings and claimed to know
'nothing fine or worthy'. He spent his life perplexing those who
encountered him and is as important and perplexing now as he was
2500 years ago. Drawing on the various competing sources for
Socrates that are available to us, "Socrates: A Guide for the
Perplexed" guides the reader through the main themes and ideas of
Socrates' thought. Taking into account the puzzles surrounding his
trial and death, the philosophical methods and ethical positions
associated with Socrates, and his lasting influence, Sara
Ahbel-Rappe presents a concise and accessible introduction to this
most influential and important of philosophers. She concludes by
suggesting that it is in fact the Socratic insistence on
self-knowledge that makes Socrates at once so pivotal and so
elusive for the student of philosophy. This book is the ideal
companion to the study of key thinker in the history of philosophy.
Continuum's "Guides for the Perplexed" are clear, concise and
accessible introductions to thinkers, writers and subjects that
students and readers can find especially challenging - or indeed
downright bewildering. Concentrating specifically on what it is
that makes the subject difficult to grasp, these books explain and
explore key themes and ideas, guiding the reader towards a thorough
understanding of demanding material.
How to Think Like a Roman Emperor takes readers on a transformative
journey along with Marcus, following his progress from a young
noble at the court of Hadrian - taken under the wing of some of the
finest philosophers of his day - through to his reign as emperor of
Rome at the height of its power. Robertson shows how Marcus used
philosophical doctrines and therapeutic practices to build
emotional resilience and endure tremendous adversity, and guides
readers through applying the same methods to their own lives.
Combining remarkable stories from Marcus's life with insights from
modern psychology and the enduring wisdom of his philosophy, How to
Think Like a Roman Emperor puts a human face on Stoicism and offers
a timeless and essential guide to handling the ethical and
psychological challenges we face today.
THE science which has to do with nature clearly concerns itself for
the most part with bodies and magnitudes and their properties and
movements, but also with the principles of this sort of substance,
as many as they may be. For of things constituted by nature some
are bodies and magnitudes, some possess body and magnitude, and
some are principles of things which possess these. Now a continuum
is that which is divisible into parts always capable of
subdivision, and a body is that which is every way divisible.
This is an important new monograph on Plato's metaphysics, focusing
on the theory of the forms, which is the central philosophical
concept in Plato's theory.Few philosophical doctrines have been as
influential and as widely discussed as Plato's theory of Forms; yet
few have been as misunderstood. Most philosophers, following the
recommendation of Aristotle, regard the Forms as abstract entities.
However, this view is difficult to square with other aspects of
Plato's thought, in particular his theory of knowledge.Francis A.
Grabowski aims to dissociate the theory of Forms from its
Aristotelian reception, by interpreting it within the larger
framework of Plato's philosophy. Grabowski notes that the theory
emerged largely from epistemological concerns. He shows that the
ancients conceived of knowledge almost exclusively as a
perception-like acquaintance with things. He goes on to examine
Plato's epistemology and shows that Plato also regards knowledge as
the mind being directly acquainted with its object. Grabowski
argues that, by modelling knowledge on perception, Plato could not
have conceived of the Forms as Aristotle and others have claimed.
He concludes that an interpretation of the Forms as concrete rather
than abstract entities provides a more plausible and coherent view
of Plato's overall philosophical project.
It has long been thought that the ancient Greeks did not take
mechanics seriously as part of the workings of nature, and that
therefore their natural philosophy was both primitive and marginal.
In this book Sylvia Berryman challenges that assumption, arguing
that the idea that the world works 'like a machine' can be found in
ancient Greek thought, predating the early modern philosophy with
which it is most closely associated. Her discussion ranges over
topics including balancing and equilibrium, lifting water,
sphere-making and models of the heavens, and ancient Greek
pneumatic theory, with detailed analysis of thinkers such as
Aristotle, Archimedes, and Hero of Alexandria. Her book shows
scholars of ancient Greek philosophy why it is necessary to pay
attention to mechanics, and shows historians of science why the
differences between ancient and modern reactions to mechanics are
not as great as was generally thought.
A new account of Aristotle's Ethics, this book argues for the
central importance of the concept of techne or craft in Aristotle's
moral theory. Exploring the importance of techne in the Platonic
and pre-Platonic intellectual context in which Aristotle was
writing, Tom Angier here shows that this concept has an important
role in Aristotle's Ethics that has rarely been studied in
Anglo-American scholarship. Through close-analysis of the primary
texts, this book uses the focus on techne to systematically
critique and renew Aristotelian moral philosophy. Techne in
Aristotle's Ethics provides a novel and challenging approach to one
of the Ancient World's most enduring intellectual legacies.
In this book, Kevin M. Cherry compares the views of Plato and
Aristotle about the practice, study, and, above all, the purpose of
politics. The first scholar to place Aristotle's Politics in
sustained dialogue with Plato's Statesman, Cherry argues that
Aristotle rejects the view of politics advanced by Plato's Eleatic
Stranger, contrasting them on topics such as the proper
categorization of regimes, the usefulness and limitations of the
rule of law, and the proper understanding of phron sis. The various
differences between their respective political philosophies,
however, reflect a more fundamental difference in how they view the
relationship of human beings to the natural world around them.
Reading the Politics in light of the Statesman sheds new light on
Aristotle's political theory and provides a better understanding of
Aristotle's criticism of Socrates. Most importantly, it highlights
an enduring and important question: Should politics have as its
primary purpose the preservation of life, or should it pursue the
higher good of living well?"
|
|