|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500 > General
This book studies the pilgrimage of the Ancient World in its search
for moral truth. After a brief examination of the values which
dominated Homeric society and the subsequent aristocracies, the
central portion of the book is an account and analysis of the moral
ideas which illuminated the Greek, Roman and Hebrew worlds during
the classical period. The volume discusses the cardinal virtues,
the place of friendship, Plato's love, philanthropia and the moral
insights of the Jewish prophets and subsequently examines Christian
love.
Plato and the Creation of the Hebrew Bible for the first time
compares the ancient law collections of the Ancient Near East, the
Greeks and the Pentateuch to determine the legal antecedents for
the biblical laws. Following on from his 2006 work, Berossus and
Genesis, Manetho and Exodus, Gmirkin takes up his theory that the
Pentateuch was written around 270 BCE using Greek sources found at
the Great Library of Alexandria, and applies this to an examination
of the biblical law codes. A striking number of legal parallels are
found between the Pentateuch and Athenian laws, and specifically
with those found in Plato's Laws of ca. 350 BCE. Constitutional
features in biblical law, Athenian law, and Plato's Laws also
contain close correspondences. Several genres of biblical law,
including the Decalogue, are shown to have striking parallels with
Greek legal collections, and the synthesis of narrative and legal
content is shown to be compatible with Greek literature. All this
evidence points to direct influence from Greek writings, especially
Plato's Laws, on the biblical legal tradition. Finally, it is
argued that the creation of the Hebrew Bible took place according
to the program found in Plato's Laws for creating a legally
authorized national ethical literature, reinforcing the importance
of this specific Greek text to the authors of the Torah and Hebrew
Bible in the early Hellenistic Era. This study offers a fascinating
analysis of the background to the Pentateuch, and will be of
interest not only to biblical scholars, but also to students of
Plato, ancient law, and Hellenistic literary traditions.
Originally published in 1991, this book focuses on the concept of
virtue, and in particular on the virtue of wisdom or knowledge, as
it is found in the epic poems of Homer, some tragedies of
Sophocles, selected writings of Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoic and
Epicurean philosophers. The key questions discussed are the nature
of the virtues, their relation to each other, and the relation
between the virtues and happiness or well-being. This book provides
the background and interpretative framework to make classical works
on Ethics, such as Plato's Republic and Aristotle's Nicomachean
Ethics, accessible to readers with no training in the classics.
Ludwig Edelstein (1902-1965) is well-known for his work on the
history of anceint medicine and ancient philosophy, and to both of
these areas he made contributions of primary importance. This
collection, originally published in 1987, makes avaialable
Edelstein's main papers to scholars and students, and includes
papers from 1931-1965.
Pride is pervasive in Roman texts, as an emotion and a political
and social concept implicated in ideas of power. This study
examines Roman discourse of pride from two distinct complementary
perspectives. The first is based on scripts, mini-stories told to
illustrate what pride is, how it arises and develops, and where it
fits within the Roman emotional landscape. The second is semantic,
and draws attention to differences between terms within the pride
field. The peculiar feature of Roman pride that emerges is that it
appears exclusively as a negative emotion, attributed externally
and condemned, up to the Augustan period. This previously unnoticed
lack of expression of positive pride in republican discourse is a
result of the way the Roman republican elite articulates its values
as anti-monarchical and is committed, within the governing class,
to power-sharing and a kind of equality. The book explores this
uniquely Roman articulation of pride attributed to people, places,
and institutions and traces the partial rehabilitation of pride
that begins in the texts of the Augustan poets at the time of great
political change. Reading for pride produces innovative readings of
texts that range from Plautus to Ausonius, with major focus on
Cicero, Livy, Vergil, and other Augustan poets.
W.K.C. Guthrie has written a survey of the great age of Greek
philosophy - from Thales to Aristotle - which combines
comprehensiveness with brevity. Without pre-supposing a knowledge
of Greek or the Classics, he sets out to explain the ideas of Plato
and Aristotle in the light of their predecessors rather than their
successors, and to describe the characteristic features of the
Greek way of thinking and outlook on the world. Thus The Greek
Philosophers provides excellent background material for the general
reader - as well as providing a firm basis for specialist studies.
This book offers an original account of one of Aristotle's central
doctrines, his theory of material substance. Gad Freudenthal argues
that Aristotle's concept of heat is a crucial but hitherto ignored
part of this account. Aristotle's 'canonical', four-element theory
of matter fails to explain the coming-to-be of material substances
(the way matter becomes organised) and their persistence (why
substances do not disintegrate into their components). Interpreters
have highlighted Aristotle's claim that soul is the active cause of
the coming-to-be and persistence of living beings. Dr Freudenthal
draws on dispersed remarks in Aristotle's writings, to argue that
Aristotle in parallel also draws on a comprehensive 'naturalistic'
theory, which accounts for material persistence through the
concepts of heat, specifically vital heat, and connate pneuma. This
theory, which bears also on the higher soul-functions, is central
in Aristotle's understanding of the relationship between matter and
form, body and soul. Dr Freudenthal aims not only to recover this
theory and to highlight its explanatory roles, but also to make
suggestions concerning its origin in Presocratic thought and in
Aristotle's own early theology. He further offers a brief review of
how later ages came to grips with the difficulties inherent in the
received version of Aristotle's matter theory. This book is an
important contribution to the proper understanding of a central
Aristotelian doctrine, which straddles 'chemistry', biology, the
theory of soul, and metaphysics.
A superb new edition of Epictetus's famed handbook on
Stoicism-translated by one of the world's leading authorities on
Stoic philosophy Born a slave, the Roman Stoic philosopher
Epictetus (c. 55-135 AD) taught that mental freedom is supreme,
since it can liberate one anywhere, even in a prison. In How to Be
Free, A. A. Long-one of the world's leading authorities on Stoicism
and a pioneer in its remarkable contemporary revival-provides a
superb new edition of Epictetus's celebrated guide to the Stoic
philosophy of life (the Encheiridion) along with a selection of
related reflections in his Discourses. Freedom, for Epictetus, is
not a human right or a political prerogative but a psychological
and ethical achievement, a gift that we alone can bestow on
ourselves. We can all be free, but only if we learn to assign
paramount value to what we can control (our motivations and
reactions), treat what we cannot control with equanimity, and view
our circumstances as opportunities to do well and be well, no
matter what happens to us through misfortune or the actions of
other people. How to Be Free features splendid new translations and
the original Greek on facing pages, a compelling introduction that
sets Epictetus in context and describes the importance of Stoic
freedom today, and an invaluable glossary of key words and
concepts. The result is an unmatched introduction to this powerful
method of managing emotions and handling life's situations, from
the most ordinary to the most demanding.
'It is impossible to live the pleasant life without also living
sensibly, nobly and justly' The ancient Greek philosopher and
teacher Epicurus argued that pleasure - not sensual hedonism, but
the absence of pain or fear - is the highest goal of life. His
hugely influential lessons on happiness are a call to appreciate
the joy of being alive. One of twenty new books in the bestselling
Penguin Great Ideas series. This new selection showcases a diverse
list of thinkers who have helped shape our world today, from
anarchists to stoics, feminists to prophets, satirists to Zen
Buddhists.
This book, originally published in 1991, sets forth the assumptions
about thought and language that made falsehood seem so problematic
to Plato and his contemporaries, and expounds the solution that
Plato finally reached in the Sophist. Free from untranslated Greek,
the book is accessible to all studying ancient Greek philosophy. As
a well-documented case study of a definitive advance in logic,
metaphysics and epistemology, the book will also appeal to
philosophers generally.
Modern literary theory is increasingly looking to philosophy for
its inspiration. After a wave of structural analysis, the growing
influence of deconstruction and hermeneutic readings continues to
bear witness to this. This exciting and important collection, first
published in 1988, reveals the diversity of approaches that mark
the post-structuralist endeavour, and provides a challenge to the
conventional practice of classical studies and ancient philosophy.
This book will be of interest to students of ancient philosophy,
classical studies and literary theory.
The Sceptics is the first comprehensive, up-to-date treatment of
Greek scepticism, from the beginnings of epistemology with
Xenophanes, to the final full development of Pyrrhonism as
presented in the work of Sextus Empiricus. Tracing the evolution of
scepticism from 500 B.C to A.D 200, this clear and rigorous
analysis presents the arguments of the Greek sceptics in their
historical context and provides an in-depth study of the various
strands of the sceptical tradition.
Euripides and the Boundaries of the Human presents the first
single-volume reading in nearly fifty years of all of Euripides'
surviving plays. Rather than examining one or a handful of dramas
in monograph or article form, Mark Ringer insists on the thematic
and stylistic parallels that unite a diverse canon of works.
Euripides is often referred to as the most modern of the three
Ancient Greek tragedians, but in what way can the work of this
fifth-century B.C. artist be claimed as modern? The multi-layered
presentation of character is new within the context of Athenian
Tragedy. The plays also reveal equal concern with the preservation
and re-vitalization of tradition, especially with respect to the
portrayal of the Olympian gods. Euripidean drama upholds tradition
just as vigorously as it posits a new kind of realism in character
portrayal in the Ancient Theatre. Euripidean drama fuses what was
old with what was new in order to revitalize and perpetuate the art
of tragedy. This book will be of interest to professionals and
students in the fields of classics, Greek drama in translation or
in the original Greek, theater studies, comparative literature,
tragedy, and religion.
Forms, Souls, and Embryos allows readers coming from different
backgrounds to appreciate the depth and originality with which the
Neoplatonists engaged with and responded to a number of
philosophical questions central to human reproduction, including:
What is the causal explanation of the embryo's formation? How and
to what extent are Platonic Forms involved? In what sense is a
fetus 'alive,' and when does it become a human being? Where does
the embryo's soul come from, and how is it connected to its body?
This is the first full-length study in English of this fascinating
subject, and is a must-read for anyone interested in Neoplatonism
or the history of medicine and embryology.
Is music just matter of hearing and producing notes? And is it of
interest just to musicians? By exploring different authors and
philosophical trends of the Roman Empire, from Philo of Alexandria
to Alexander of Aphrodisias, from the rebirth of Platonism with
Plutarch to the last Neoplatonists, this book sheds light on
different ways in which music and musical notions were made a
crucial part of philosophical discourse. Far from being mere
metaphors, notions such as harmony, concord and attunement became
key philosophical tools in order to better grasp and conceptualise
fundamental notions in philosophical debates from cosmology to
ethics and from epistemology to theology. The volume is written by
a distinguished international team of contributors.
Plotinus (205-269 AD) is considered the founder of Neoplatonism,
the dominant philosophical movement of late antiquity, and a rich
seam of current scholarly interest. Whilst Plotinus' influence on
the subsequent philosophical tradition was enormous, his ideas can
also be seen as the culmination of some implicit trends in the
Greek tradition from Parmenides, Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics.
Emilsson's in-depth study focuses on Plotinus' notion of Intellect,
which comes second in his hierarchical model of reality, after the
One, unknowable first cause of everything. As opposed to ordinary
human discursive thinking, Intellect's thought is all-at-once,
timeless, truthful and a direct intuition into 'things themselves';
it is presumably not even propositional. Emilsson discusses and
explains this strong notion of non-discursive thought and explores
Plotinus' insistence that this must be the primary form of thought.
Plotinus' doctrine of Intellect raises a host of questions that
Emilsson addresses. First, Intellect's thought is described as an
attempt to grasp the One and at the same time as self-thought. How
are these two claims related? How are they compatible? What lies in
Plotinus' insistence that Intellect's thought is a thought of
itself? Second, Plotinus gives two minimum requirements of thought:
that it must involve a distinction between thinker and object of
thought, and that the object itself must be varied. How are these
two pluralist claims related? Third, what is the relation between
Intellect as a thinker and Intellect as an object of thought?
Plotinus' position here seems to amount to a form of idealism, and
this is explored.
Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy is an annual publication which
includes original articles, which may be of substantial length, on
a wide range of topics in ancient philosophy, and review articles
of major books. Contributors to this volume; Paul A. Vander Waerdt,
Christopher Rowe, Rachel Rue, Paula Gottlieb, Robert Bolton, and
John M. Cooper.
The City-State of the Soul: Self-Constitution in Plato's Republic
explores Plato's idea that the moral life consists in the founding
of one's own soul. This insight is central to the long argument of
the Republic and, in particular, to the complex relation between
the city and the human soul. This fruitful picture of the moral
life, however, has not received the attention it deserves. As Kevin
M. Crotty argues, Plato's distinctive insight is that justice is
above all a creative force. Plato presents justice not as a
relation amongst fully formed individuals, but rather as the
quality that galvanizes a diverse welter of disparate parts into a
coherent entity (above all, a soul or a city). Justice, then, is
the virtue most closely associated with being-the source of its
philosophical stature. Plato presents a conception of justice meant
to impress the young, bright and ambitious as a noble pursuit, and
a task worthy of their best talents. The City-State of the Soul is
written for anyone interested in the Republic, including but not
limited to students and scholars of ancient philosophy, political
philosophy, ethics, and ancient Greek literature.
This is the first book to provide an account of the influence of
Proclus, a member of the Athenian Neoplatonic School, during more
than one thousand years of European history (c.500-1600). Proclus
was the most important philosopher of late antiquity, a dominant
(albeit controversial) voice in Byzantine thought, the second most
influential Greek philosopher in the later western Middle Ages
(after Aristotle), and a major figure (together with Plotinus) in
the revival of Greek philosophy in the Renaissance. Proclus was
also intensively studied in the Islamic world of the Middle Ages
and was a major influence on the thought of medieval Georgia. The
volume begins with a substantial essay by the editor summarizing
the entire history of Proclus' reception. This is followed by the
essays of more than a dozen of the world's leading authorities in
the various specific areas covered.
Ancient thought, particularly that of Plato and Aristotle, has
played an important role in the development of the field of
aesthetics, and the ideas of ancient thinkers are still influential
and controversial today. Ancient Aesthetics introduces and
discusses the central contributions of key ancient philosophers to
this field, carefully considering their theories regarding the
arts, especially poetry, but also music and visual art, as well as
the theory of beauty more generally. With a focus on Plato and
Aristotle, the philosophers who have given us their thought about
the arts at the greatest length, this volume also discusses
Hellenistic aesthetics and Plotinus' theory of beauty, which was to
prove very influential in later thought. Ancient Aesthetics is a
valuable contribution to its field, and will be of interest to
students of philosophy and classics.
In this bold new study, Andrew J. Mason seeks both to shed light on
the key issue of flux in Plato's work, and to show that there is
also in Plato a notion of flow that needs to be distinguished from
flux. Mason brings out the importance of this hitherto neglected
distinction, and proposes on its basis a new way of understanding
the development of Plato's thought. The opposition between the
'being' of Forms and the 'becoming' or 'flux' of sensibles has been
fundamental to the understanding of Plato from Aristotle to the
present day. One key concern of this volume is to clarify which
kinds or levels of flux Plato accepts in sensibles. In addition,
Mason argues that this traditional approach is unsatisfactory, as
it leaves out the important notion of flow. Unlike flux, flow is a
kind of motion that does not entail intrinsic change. It is also
not restricted to the sensible, but covers motions of soul as well,
including the circular motion of nous (intelligence) that is
crucial in Plato's later thought, particularly his cosmology. In
short, flow is not incompatible with 'being', and in this study
Plato's development is presented, largely, as his arrival at this
view, in correction of his earlier conflation of flux and flow in
establishing the dichotomy between being and becoming. Mason's
study offers fresh insights into many dialogues and difficult
passages in Plato's oeuvre, and situates Plato's conception and
usage of 'flow' and 'flux' in relation to earlier usage in the
Greek poetic tradition and the Presocratic thinkers, particularly
Heraclitus. The first study of its kind, Flow and Flux uncovers
dimensions of Plato's thinking that may reshape the way his
philosophy is understood.
|
You may like...
Republic
Plato
Paperback
R95
R76
Discovery Miles 760
|