|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500 > General
In the Platonic work "Alcibiades I," a divinely guided Socrates
adopts the guise of a lover in order to divert Alcibiades from an
unthinking political career. The contributors to this carefully
focussed volume cover aspects of the background to the work; its
arguments and the philosophical issues it raises; its relationship
to other Platonic texts, and its subsequent history up to the time
of the Neoplatonists. Despite its ancient prominence, the
authorship of "Alcibiades I" is still unsettled; the essays and two
appendices, one historical and one stylometric, come together to
suggest answers to this tantalising question.
Written while Boethius was in prison awaiting execution, The
Consolation of Philosophy consists of a dialogue in alternating
prose and verse between the author, lamenting his own sorrows, and
a majestic woman, who is the incarnation of his guardian
Philosophy. The woman develops a modified form of Neoplatonism and
Stoicism, demonstrating the unreality of earthly fortunes, then
proving that the highest good and the highest happiness are in God,
and reconciling the apparent contradictions concerning the
existence of everything.
The purpose of this book, first published in 1957, is to make a
critical analysis of the controversial Socratic problem. The
Socratic issue owes its paramount difficulty not only to the status
of available source materials, but also to the diversity of opinion
as to the proper use of these materials. This volume offers a new
approach to the problem, and a starting point to further
investigations.
Epicurus on the Self reconstructs a part of Epicurean ethics which
only survives on the fragmentary papyrus rolls excavated from an
ancient library in Herculaneum, On Nature XXV. The aim of this book
is to contribute to a deeper understanding of Epicurus' moral
psychology, ethics and of its robust epistemological framework. The
book also explores how the notion of the self emerges in Epicurus'
struggle to express the individual perspective of oneself in the
process of one's holistic self-reflection as an individual
psychophysical being.
The Hegel Lectures Series Series Editor: Peter C. Hodgson Hegel's
lectures have had as great a historical impact as the works he
himself published. Important elements of his system are elaborated
only in the lectures, especially those given in Berlin during the
last decade of his life. The original editors conflated materials
from different sources and dates, obscuring the development and
logic of Hegel's thought. The Hegel Lectures series is based on a
selection of extant and recently discovered transcripts and
manuscripts. The original lecture series are reconstructed so that
the structure of Hegel's argument can be followed. Each volume
presents an accurate new translation accompanied by an editorial
introduction and annotations on the text, which make possible the
identification of Hegel's many allusions and sources. Hegel's
interpretation of the history of philosophy not only played a
central role in the shaping of his own thought, but also has had a
great influence on the development of historical thinking. In his
own view the study of the history of philosophy is the study of
philosophy itself. This explains why such a large proportion of his
lectures, from 1805 to 1831, the year of his death, were about
history of philosophy. The text of these lectures, presented here
in the first authoritative English edition, is therefore a document
of the greatest importance in the development of Western thought:
they constitute the very first comprehensive history of philosophy
that treats philosophy itself as undergoing genuine historical
development. And they are crucial for understanding Hegel's own
systematic works such as the Phenomenology, the Logic, and the
Encyclopedia, for central to his thought is the theme of spirit as
engaged in self-realization through the processes of historical
change. Furthermore, they played a crucial role in one of the
determining events of modern intellectual history: the rise of a
new consciousness of human life, culture, and intellect as
historical in nature. This third volume of the lectures covers the
medieval and modern periods, and includes fascinating discussion of
scholastic, Renaissance, and Reformation philosophy, and of such
great modern thinkers as Descartes, Locke, Leibniz, and especially
Kant.
This book analyses the diverse ways in which women have been
represented in the Puranic traditions in ancient India - the
virtuous wife, mother, daughter, widow, and prostitute - against
the socio-religious milieu around CE 300-1000. Puranas (lit.
ancient narratives) are brahmanical texts that largely fall under
the category of socio-religious literature which were more
broad-based and inclusive, unlike the Smrtis, which were accessible
mainly to the upper sections of society. In locating, identifying,
and commenting on the multiplicity of the images and depictions of
women's roles in Puranic traditions, the author highlights their
lives and experiences over time, both within and outside the
traditional confines of the domestic sphere. With a focus on five
Mahapuranas that deal extensively with the social matrix Visnu,
Markandeya Matsya, Agni, and Bhagavata Puranas, the book explores
the question of gender and agency in early India and shows how such
identities were recast, invented, shaped, constructed, replicated,
stereotyped, and sometimes reversed through narratives. Further, it
traces social consequences and contemporary relevance of such
representations in marriage, adultery, ritual, devotion, worship,
fasts, and pilgrimage. This volume will be of interest to
researchers and scholars in women and gender studies, ancient
Indian history, religion, sociology, literature, and South Asian
studies, as also the informed general reader.
What is poetry? Why do human beings produce and consume it? What
effects does it have on them? Can it give them insight into truth,
or is it dangerously misleading? This book is a wide-ranging study
of the very varied answers which ancient philosophers gave to such
questions. An extended discussion of Plato's Republic shows how the
two discussions of poetry are integrated with each other and with
the dialogue's central themes. Aristotle's Poetics is read in the
context of his understanding of poetry as a natural human behaviour
and an intrinsically valuable component of a good human life. Two
chapters trace the development of the later Platonist tradition
from Plutarch to Plotinus, Longinus and Porphyry, exploring its
intellectual debts to Epicurean, allegorical and Stoic approaches
to poetry. It will be essential reading for classicists as well as
ancient philosophers and modern philosophers of art and aesthetics.
This book examines the origins of ancient Greek science using the
vehicles of blood, blood vessels, and the heart. Careful attention
to biomedical writers in the ancient world, as well as to the
philosophical and literary work of writers prior to the Hippocratic
authors, produce an interesting story of how science progressed and
the critical context in which important methodological questions
were addressed. The end result is an account that arises from
debates that are engaged in and "solved" by different writers.
These stopping points form the foundation for Harvey and for modern
philosophy of biology. Author Michael Boylan sets out the history
of science as well as a critical evaluation based upon principles
in the contemporary canon of the philosophy of science-particularly
those dealing with the philosophy of biology.
Nietzsche is undoubtedly one of the most original and influential
thinkers in the history of philosophy. With ideas such as the
overman, will to power, the eternal recurrence, and perspectivism,
Nietzsche challenges us to reconceive how it is that we know and
understand the world, and what it means to be a human being.
Further, in his works, he not only grapples with previous great
philosophers and their ideas, but he also calls into question and
redefines what it means to do philosophy. Nietzsche and the
Philosophers for the first time sets out to examine explicitly
Nietzsche's relationship to his most important predecessors. This
anthology includes essays by many of the leading Nietzsche
scholars, including Keith Ansell-Pearson, Daniel Conway, Tracy B.
Strong, Gary Shapiro, Babette Babich, Mark Anderson, and Paul S.
Loeb. These excellent writers discuss Nietzsche's engagement with
such figures as Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Socrates, Hume,
Schopenhauer, Emerson, Rousseau, and the Buddha. Anyone interested
in Nietzsche or the history of philosophy generally will find much
of great interest in this volume.
This important monograph examines Plato's contribution to virtue
ethics and shows how his dialogues contain interesting and
plausible insights into current philosophical concerns. Ancient
philosophy is no longer an isolated discipline. Recent years have
seen the development of a dialogue between ancient and contemporary
philosophers writing on central issues in moral and political
philosophy. The renewed interest in character and virtue as ethical
concepts is one such issue, yet Plato's contribution has been
largely neglected in contemporary virtue ethics.In "Plato on Virtue
and the Law", Sandrine Berges seeks to address this gap in the
literature by exploring the contribution that virtue ethics make to
the understanding of laws alongside the interesting and plausible
insights into current philosophical concerns evident in Plato's
dialogues. The book argues that a distinctive virtue theory of law
is clearly presented in Plato's political dialogues. Through a new
reading of the "Crito", "Menexenus", "Gorgias", "Republic",
"Statesman and Laws", Berges shows how Plato proposes several ways
in which we can understand the law from the perspective of virtue
ethics.
This volume presents a commentary on Aristotle's Metaphysics Book
12 by pseudo-Alexander in a new translation accompanied by
explanatory notes, introduction and indexes. Fred D. Miller, Jr.
argues that the author of the commentary is in fact not Alexander
of Aphrodisias, Aristotle's distant successor in early 3rd century
CE Athens and his leading defender and interpreter, but Michael of
Ephesus from Constantinople as late as the 12th century CE. Robert
Browning had earlier made the case that Michael was enlisted by
Princess Anna Comnena in a project to restore and complete the
ancient Greek commentaries on Aristotle, including those of
Alexander; he did so by incorporating available ancient
commentaries into commentaries of his own. Metaphysics Book 12
posits a god as the supreme cause of motion in the cosmic system
Aristotle had elaborated elsewhere as having the earth at the
centre. The fixed stars are whirled around it on an outer sphere,
the sun, moon and recognised planets on interior spheres, but with
counteracting spheres to make the motions of each independent of
the motions of others and of the fixed stars, thus yielding a total
of 55 spheres. Motion is transmitted from a divine unmoved mover
through divine moved movers which move the celestial spheres, and
on to the perishable realms. Chapters 1 to 5 describe the
principles and causes of the perishable substances nearer the
centre of the universe, while Chapters 6 to 10 seek to prove the
existence and attributes of the celestial substances beyond.
The Laws is Plato's last and longest dialogue. Although it has been
neglected (compared to such works as the Republic and Symposium),
it is beginning to receive a great deal of scholarly attention.
Book 10 of the Laws contains Plato's fullest defence of the
existence of the gods, and his last word on their nature, as well
as a presentation and defence of laws against impiety (e.g.
atheism). Plato's primary aim is to defend the idea that the gods
exist and that they are good - this latter meaning that they do not
neglect human beings and cannot be swayed by prayers and sacrifices
to overlook injustice. As such, the Laws is an important text for
anyone interested in ancient Greek religion, philosophy, and
politics generally, and the later thought of Plato in particular.
Robert Mayhew presents a new translation, with commentary, of Book
10 of the Laws. His primary aim in the translation is fidelity to
the Greek. His commentary focuses on philosophical issues (broadly
understood to include religion and politics), and deals with
philological matters only when doing so serves to better explain
those issues. Knowledge of Greek is not assumed, and the Greek that
does appear has been transliterated. It is the first commentary in
English of any kind on Laws 10 for nearly 140 years.
John Palmer develops and defends a modal interpretation of
Parmenides, according to which he was the first philosopher to
distinguish in a rigorous manner the fundamental modalities of
necessary being, necessary non-being or impossibility, and
non-necessary or contingent being. This book accordingly
reconsiders his place in the historical development of Presocratic
philosophy in light of this new interpretation. Careful treatment
of Parmenides' specification of the ways of inquiry that define his
metaphysical and epistemological outlook paves the way for detailed
analyses of his arguments demonstrating the temporal and spatial
attributes of what is and cannot not be. Since the existence of
this necessary being does not preclude the existence of other
entities that are but need not be, Parmenides' cosmology can
straightforwardly be taken as his account of the origin and
operation of the world's mutable entities. Later chapters reassess
the major Presocratics' relation to Parmenides in light of the
modal interpretation, focusing particularly on Zeno, Melissus,
Anaxagoras, and Empedocles. In the end, Parmenides' distinction
among the principal modes of being, and his arguments regarding
what what must be must be like, simply in virtue of its mode of
being, entitle him to be seen as the founder of metaphysics or
ontology as a domain of inquiry distinct from natural philosophy
and theology. An appendix presents a Greek text of the fragments of
Parmenides' poem with English translation and textual notes.
This book features a major new critical assessment of Heidegger's
interpretation and political use of Plato's "Republic". Heidegger's
"Platonism" challenges Heidegger's 1940 interpretation of Plato as
the philosopher who initiated the West's ontological decline into
contemporary nihilism. Mark A. Ralkowski argues that, in his
earlier lecture course, "On the Essence of Truth", in which he
appropriates Plato in a positive light, Heidegger discovered the
two most important concepts of his later thought, namely the
difference between the Being of beings and Being as such, and the
'belonging together' of Being and man in what he eventually calls
Ereignis, the 'event of appropriation'. Ralkowski shows that, far
from being the grand villain of metaphysics, Plato was in fact the
gateway to Heidegger's later period. Because Heidegger discovers
the seeds of his later thought in his positive appropriation of
Plato, this book argues that Heidegger's later thought is a return
to and phenomenological transformation of Platonism, which is
ironic not least because Heidegger thought of himself as the West's
first truly post-Platonic philosopher. "Continuum Studies in
Continental Philosophy" presents cutting-edge scholarship in the
field of modern European thought. The wholly original arguments,
perspectives and research findings in titles in this series make it
an important and stimulating resource for students and academics
from across the discipline.
The ancient Greeks played a fundamental role in the history of
mathematics and their ideas were reused and developed in subsequent
periods all the way down to the scientific revolution and beyond.
In this, the first complete history for a century. Reviel Netz
offers a panoramic view of the rise and influence of Greek
mathematics and its significance in world history. He explores the
Near Eastern antecedents and the social and intellectual
developments underlying the subject's beginnings in Greece in the
fifth century BCE. He leads the reader through the proofs and
arguments of key figures like Archytas, Euclid and Archimedes, and
considers the totality of the Greek mathematical achievement which
also includes, in addition to pure mathematics, such applied fields
as optics, music, mechanics and, above all, astronomy. This is the
story not only of a major historical development, but of some of
the finest mathematics ever created.
Most people think that the difficulty of balancing career and
personal/family relationships is the fault of present-day society
or is due to their own inadequacies. But in this major new book,
eminent moral philosopher Michael Slote argues that the difficulty
runs much deeper, that it is due to the essential nature of the
divergent goods involved in this kind of choice. He shows more
generally that perfect human happiness and perfect virtue are
impossible in principle, a view originally enunciated by Isaiah
Berlin, but much more thoroughly and synoptically defended here
than ever before.
Ancient Greek and modern-day Enlightenment thought typically
assumed that perfection was possible, and this is also true of
Romanticism and of most recent ethical theory. But if, as Slote
maintains, imperfection is inevitable, then our inherited
categories of virtue and personal good are far too limited and
unqualified to allow us to understand and cope with the richer and
more complex life that characterizes today's world. And The
Impossibility of Perfection argues in particular that we need some
new notions, new distinctions, and even new philosophical methods
in order to distill some of the ethical insights of recent feminist
thought and arrive at a fuller and more realistic picture of
ethical phenomena.
|
De Anima
(Hardcover)
Aristotle; Volume editing by William D. Ross
|
R3,857
R2,729
Discovery Miles 27 290
Save R1,128 (29%)
|
Ships in 12 - 17 working days
|
|
In this pathbreaking interpretation of Plato's foundational text of
political philosophy, Carolina Araujo reveals how the Republic
remains ripe for an interpretation grounded in notions of
cooperation, flourishing and justice relevant to the diversity of
contemporary life. Plato's Republic has the Greek name of Politeia
that Araujo translates as "the way of life of the citizens," not
"the State" or "the form of government" as it more traditionally
rendered. Plato's treatise, Politeia, depicts the rich array of
patterns emerging from human interaction and enquires into the best
amongst them. Cooperative Flourishing in Plato's Republic returns
to these important questions about society - how to live with a
vast diversity of personalities, with different interests and
abilities, all of them trying to flourish - and asks how best can
we share our environment? With rigorous philosophical analysis of
the Greek text, accompanied by original translations of the most
important passages, Araujo upends mainstream scholarship to
progress Socrates' "bottom-up" view of politics and rejects
previous readings of the Republic as a proto-totalitarian text,
psychological study or lengthy analogy. By defending a theory of
Platonic justice that is rooted in cooperative flourishing, the
public education of all citizens and the contribution of
philosophers to political life, "the beautiful city", which Plato
called Kallipolis, emerges as a hopeful possibility.
This book examines how ancient authors explored ideas of kingship
as a political role fundamental to the construction of civic unity,
the use of kingship stories to explain the past and present unity
of the polis and the distinctive function or status attributed to
kings in such accounts. It explores the notion of kingship offered
by historians such as Herodotus, as well as dramatists writing for
the Athenian stage, paying particular attention to dramatic
depictions of the unique capabilities of Theseus in uniting the
city in the figure of the 'democratic king'. It also discusses
kingship in Greek philosophy: the Socratics' identification of an
'art of kingship', and Xenophon and Isocrates' model of 'virtue
monarchy'. In turn, these allow a rereading of explorations of
kingship and excellence in Plato's later political thought, seen as
a critique of these models, and also in Aristotle's account of
total kingship or pambasileia, treated here as a counterfactual
device developed to explore the epistemic benefits of democracy.
This book offers a fascinating insight into the institution of
monarchy in classical Greek thought and society, both for those
working on Greek philosophy and politics, and also for students of
the history of political thought.
Jewish Messianism and the History of Philosophy contests the
ancient opposition between Athens and Jerusalem by retrieving the
concept of meontology - the doctrine of nonbeing - from the Jewish
philosophical and theological tradition. For Emmanuel Levinas, as
well as for Franz Rosenzweig, Hermann Cohen and Moses Maimonides,
the Greek concept of nonbeing (understood as both lack and
possibility) clarifies the meaning of Jewish life. These thinkers
of 'Jerusalem' use 'Athens' for Jewish ends, justifying Jewish
anticipation of a future messianic era as well as portraying the
subjects intellectual and ethical acts as central in accomplishing
redemption. This book envisions Jewish thought as an expression of
the intimate relationship between Athens and Jerusalem. It also
offers new readings of important figures in contemporary
Continental philosophy, critiquing previous arguments about the
role of lived religion in the thought of Jacques Derrida, the role
of Plato in the thought of Emmanuel Levinas and the centrality of
ethics in the thought of Franz Rosenzweig.
Reframing Aristotle’s natural philosophy, this wide-ranging
collection of essays reveals the centrality of magic to his
thinking. From late medieval and Renaissance discussions on the
attribution of magical works to Aristotle to the philosophical and
social justifications of magic, international contributors chart
magic as the mother science of natural philosophy. Tracing the
nascent presence of Aristotelianism in early modern Europe, this
volume shows the adaptability and openness of Aristotelianism to
magic. Weaving the paranormal and the scientific together, it pairs
the supposed superstition of the pre-modern era with modern
scientific sensibilities. Essays focus on the work of early modern
scholars and magicians such as Giambattista Della Porta, Wolferd
Senguerd, and Johann Nikolaus Martius. The attribution of the
Secretum secretorum to Aristotle, the role of illusionism, and the
relationship between the technical and magical all provide further
insight into the complex picture of magic, Aristotle and early
modern Europe. Aristotelianism and Magic in Early Modern Europe
proposes an innovative way of approaching the development of
pre-modern science whilst also acknowledging the crucial role that
concepts like magic and illusion played in Aristotle’s time.
This book investigates some of the central topics of metaphysics in
the philosophical thought of the Maya people of Mesoamerica,
particularly from the Preclassic through Postclassic periods. This
book covers the topics of time, change, identity, and truth,
through comparative investigation integrating Maya texts and
practices-such as Classic Period stelae, Postclassic Codices, and
Colonial-era texts such as the Popol Vuh and the books of Chilam
Balam-and early Chinese philosophy.
In this book, Mary Townsend proposes that, contrary to the current
scholarship on Plato's Republic, Socrates does not in fact set out
to prove the weakness of women. Rather, she argues that close
attention to the drama of the Republic reveals that Plato
dramatizes the reluctance of men to allow women into the public
sphere and offers a deeply aporetic vision of women's nature and
political position-a vision full of concern not only for the human
community, but for the desires of women themselves.
|
You may like...
Republic
Plato
Paperback
R95
R76
Discovery Miles 760
|