|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500 > General
This book challenges the popular use of 'Valentinian' to describe a
Christian school of thought in the second century CE by analysing
documents ascribed to 'Valentinians' by early Christian Apologists,
and more recently by modern scholars after the discovery of codices
near Nag Hammadi in Egypt. To this end, Ashwin-Siejkowski
highlights the great diversity of views among Christian theologians
associated with the label 'Valentinian', demonstrating their
attachment to the Scriptures and Apostolic traditions as well as
their dialogue with Graeco-Roman philosophies of their time. Among
the various themes explored are 'myth' and its role in early
Christian theology, the familiarity of the Gospel of Truth with
Alexandrian exegetical tradition, Ptolemy's didactic in his letter
to Flora, the image of the Saviour in the Interpretation of
Knowledge, reception of the Johannine motifs in Heracleon's
commentary and the Tripartite Tractate, salvation in the Excerpts
from Theodotus, Christian identity in the Gospel of Philip, and
reception of selected Johannine motifs in 'Valentinian' documents.
Valentinus' Legacy and Polyphony of Voices will be an invaluable
and accessible resource to students, researchers, and scholars of
Early Christian theologies, as well as trajectories of exegesis in
New Testament sources and the emerging of different Christian
identities based on various Christologies.
This monograph revisits one of the most debated aspects of
Dionysian scholarship: the enigma of its authorship. To establish
the identity of the author remains impossible. However, the
legitimacy of the attribution of the corpus to Dionysius the
Areopagite should not be seen as an intended forgery but rather as
a masterfully managed literary device, which better indicates the
initial intention of the actual author. The affiliation with
Dionysius the Areopagite has metaphorical and literary
significance. Dionysius is the only character in the New Testament
who is unique in his conjunction between the apostle Paul and the
Platonic Athenian Academy. In this regard this attribution, to the
mind of the actual author of the corpus, could be a symbolic
gesture to demonstrate the essential truth of both traditions as
derived essentially from the same divine source. The importance of
this assumption taken in its historical context highlights the
culmination of the formation of the civilized Roman-Byzantine
Christian identity.
The late Mario Mignucci was one of the most authoritative,
original, and influential scholars in the area of ancient
philosophy, especially ancient logic. Collected here for the first
time are sixteen of his most important essays on Ancient Logic,
Language, and Metaphysics. These essays show a perceptive historian
and a skillful logician philosophically engaged with issues that
are still at the very heart of history and philosophy of logic,
such as the nature of predication, identity, and modality. As well
as essays found in disparate publications, often not easily
available online, the volume includes an article on Plato and the
relatives translated into English for the first time and an
unpublished paper on De interpretatione 7. Mignucci thinks
rigorously and writes clearly. He brings the deep knowledge of a
scholar and the precision of a logician to bear on some of the
trickiest topics in ancient philosophy. This collection deserves
the close attention of anyone concerned with logic, language, and
metaphysics, whether in ancient or contemporary philosophy.
Originally compiled and published in 1922, this volume contains
three studies on Early Greek Thought: E. Hofmann's Qua Ratione; J.
W. Beardslee's Fifth-Century Greek Literature; and O. JOhrens's Die
Fragmente des Anaxagoras.
What is a human being according to Augustine of Hippo? This
question has occupied a group of researchers from Brazil and Europe
and has been explored at two workshops during which the
contributors to this volume have discussed anthropological themes
in Augustine's vast corpus. In this volume, the reader will find
articles on a wide spectrum of Augustine's anthropological ideas.
Some contributions focus on specific texts, while others focus on
specific theological or philosophical aspects of Augustine's
anthropology. The authors of the articles in this volume are
convinced that Augustine's anthropology is of major importance for
how human beings have been understood in Western civilization for
better or for worse. The topic is therefore highly relevant to
present times in which humanity is under pressure from various
sides.
Plato and his Predecessors considers how Plato represents his philosophical predecessors in a late quartet of dialogues: the Theaetetus, the Sophist, the Politicus and the Philebus. These predecessors appear in imaginary conversations; and they are refuted when they fail to defend their philosophical positions in debate. Professor McCabe argues that Plato's reflections on these conversations allow him to develop a new account of the principles of reason, and forge a fresh view of the best life--the life of the philosopher.
The question The Republic sets out to define is "What is justice?"
Given the difficulty of this task, Socrates and his interlocutors
are led into a discussion of justice in the city, which Socrates
suggests may help them see justice in the person, but on a grander
(and therefore easier to discuss) scale ("suppose that a
short-sighted person had been asked by some one to read small
letters from a distance; and it occurred to some one else that they
might be found in another place which was larger and in which the
letters were larger," 368, trans. Jowett). Some critics (such as
Julia Annas) have adhered to this premise that the dialogue's
entire political construct exists to serve as an analogy for the
individual soul, in which there are also various potentially
competing or conflicting "members" that might be integrated and
orchestrated under a just and productive "government."
Political theory offers a great variety of interpretive traditions
and models. Today, pluralism is the paradigm. But are all
approaches equally useful? What are their limits and possibilities?
Can we practice them in isolation, or can we combine them? Modeling
Interpretation and the Practice of Political Theory addresses these
questions in a refreshing and hands- on manner. It not only models
in the abstract, but also tests in practice eight basic schemes of
interpretation with which any ambitious reader of political texts
should already be familiar. Comprehensive and engaging, the book
includes: A straightforward typology of interpretation in political
theory. Chapters on the analytical Oxford model, biographical and
oeuvre- based interpretation, Skinner's Cambridge School, the
esoteric model, reflexive hermeneutics, reception analysis and
conceptual history. Original readings of Federalist Paper No. 10 ,
Plato's Statesman, de Gouges's The Three Urns, Rivera's wall
painting The History of Mexico and Strauss's Persecution and the
Art of Writing; with further chapters on Machiavelli, Huang Zongxi
and a Hittite loyalty oath. An Epilogue proposing pragmatist
eclecticism as the way forward in interpretation. An inspiring,
hands- on textbook suitable for undergraduate and graduate
students, as well as experienced scholars of political theory,
intellectual history and philosophy interested in learning more
about types and models of interpretation, and the challenge of
combining them in interpretive practice.
The Stoic Doctrine of Providence attempts to reconstruct the Stoic
doctrine of providence (as argued for in ancient texts now lost)
and explain its many fascinating philosophical issues. Examining
issues such as the compatibility between good and evil, and how a
provident god can serve as model of political leadership, this is
the first monograph of its kind to focus on the question of Stoic
providence. It offers an in-depth study of the meaning and
importance of this topic in eight distinct generations of Stoics,
from Zeno of Citium (fourth century B.C.) to Panaetius of Rhodes
(second century B.C.) to Marcus Aurelius (second century A.D.). The
Stoic Doctrine of Providence is key reading for anyone interested
in Ancient Stoicism or the study of divine providence in a
philosophical setting.
Whereas the history of demography as a social science has been
amply explored, that of the construction of the concept of
population has been neglected. Specialists systematically ignore a
noteworthy paradox: strictly speaking, the great intellectual
figures of the past dealt with in this book have not produced
demographic theories or doctrines as such, but they have certainly
given some thought to population at both levels. First, the central
epistemological and methodological orientation of the book is
presented. Ideas on population, far from being part of the
harmonious advancement of knowledge are the product of their
context, that is evidently demographic, but also economic,
political and above all intellectual. Then the ideas on population
of Plato, Bodin, the French mercantilists, Quesnay and the
physiocrats are examined under this light. The last chapter
addresses the implicit philosophical, economic and political issues
of population thought.
|
Meditations
(Hardcover)
Marcus Aurelius; Introduction by John Sellars; Translated by A.S.L. Farquharson
1
|
R280
R219
Discovery Miles 2 190
Save R61 (22%)
|
Ships in 5 - 10 working days
|
|
A timely book for today's world, Marcus Aurelius's Meditations
explores how to endure hardship, how to cope with change and how to
find something positive out of adversity. Part of the Macmillan
Collector's Library; a series of stunning, clothbound, pocket-sized
classics with gold foiled edges and ribbon markers. These beautiful
books make perfect gifts or a treat for any book lover. This
edition is translated by A. S. L. Farquharson and features an
introduction by John Sellars. The Meditations are a set of personal
reflections by Marcus Aurelius. He writes about the vicissitudes of
his own life and explores how to live wisely and virtuously in an
unpredictable world. He was a follower of the Stoic tradition of
philosophy, and one of its finest advocates, both in the clarity of
his writing and in the uprightness of his life. The aphorisms show
how for him, as perhaps for us all, the answer to life lies in
keeping a calm and rational mind, and in refusing to be cast down
or alarmed by things over which we have no control.
Platonism and Christian Thought in Late Antiquity examines the
various ways in which Christian intellectuals engaged with
Platonism both as a pagan competitor and as a source of
philosophical material useful to the Christian faith. The chapters
are united in their goal to explore transformations that took place
in the reception and interaction process between Platonism and
Christianity in this period. The contributions in this volume
explore the reception of Platonic material in Christian thought,
showing that the transmission of cultural content is always
mediated, and ought to be studied as a transformative process by
way of selection and interpretation. Some chapters also deal with
various aspects of the wider discussion on how Platonic, and
Hellenic, philosophy and early Christian thought related to each
other, examining the differences and common ground between these
traditions. Platonism and Christian Thought in Late Antiquity
offers an insightful and broad ranging study on the subject, which
will be of interest to students of both philosophy and theology in
the Late Antique period, as well as anyone working on the reception
and history of Platonic thought, and the development of Christian
thought.
This book offers a novel defence of a highly contested
philosophical position: biological natural kind essentialism. This
theory is routinely and explicitly rejected for its purported
inability to be explicated in the context of contemporary
biological science, and its supposed incompatibility with the
process and progress of evolution by natural selection. Christopher
J. Austin challenges these objections, and in conjunction with
contemporary scientific advancements within the field of
evolutionary-developmental biology, the book utilises a
contemporary neo-Aristotelian metaphysics of "dispositional
properties", or causal powers, to provide a theory of essentialism
centred on the developmental architecture of organisms and its role
in the evolutionary process. By defending a novel theory of
Aristotelian biological natural kind essentialism, Essence in the
Age of Evolution represents the fresh and exciting union of
cutting-edge philosophical insight and scientific knowledge.
This book explores the origins of western biopolitics in ancient
Greek political thought. Ojakangas's argues that the conception of
politics as the regulation of the quantity and quality of
population in the name of the security and happiness of the state
and its inhabitants is as old as the western political thought
itself: the politico-philosophical categories of classical thought,
particularly those of Plato and Aristotle, were already
biopolitical categories. In their books on politics, Plato and
Aristotle do not only deal with all the central topics of
biopolitics from the political point of view, but for them these
topics are the very keystone of politics and the art of government.
Yet although the Western understanding of politics was already
biopolitical in classical Greece, the book does not argue that the
history of biopolitics would constitute a continuum from antiquity
to the twentieth century. Instead Ojakangas argues that the birth
of Christianity entailed a crisis of the classical biopolitical
rationality, as the majority of classical biopolitical themes
concerning the government of men and populations faded away or were
outright rejected. It was not until the renaissance of the
classical culture and literature - including the translation of
Plato's and Aristotles political works into Latin - that
biopolitics became topical again in the West. The book will be of
great interest to scholars and students in the field of social and
political studies, social and political theory, moral and political
philosophy, IR theory, intellectual history, classical studies.
In studies of early Christian thought, 'philosophy' is often a
synonym for 'Platonism', or at most for 'Platonism and Stoicism'.
Nevertheless, it was Aristotle who, from the sixth century AD to
the Italian Renaissance, was the dominant Greek voice in Christian,
Muslim and Jewish philosophy. Aristotle and Early Christian Thought
is the first book in English to give a synoptic account of the slow
appropriation of Aristotelian thought in the Christian world from
the second to the sixth century. Concentrating on the great
theological topics - creation, the soul, the Trinity, and
Christology - it makes full use of modern scholarship on the
Peripatetic tradition after Aristotle, explaining the significance
of Neoplatonism as a mediator of Aristotelian logic. While
stressing the fidelity of Christian thinkers to biblical
presuppositions which were not shared by the Greek schools, it also
describes their attempts to overcome the pagan objections to
biblical teachings by a consistent use of Aristotelian principles,
and it follows their application of these principles to matters
which lay outside the purview of Aristotle himself. This volume
offers a valuable study not only for students of Christian theology
in its formative years, but also for anyone seeking an introduction
to the thought of Aristotle and its developments in Late Antiquity.
This book offers a new account of Aristotle's practical philosophy.
Pavlos Kontos argues that Aristotle does not restrict practical
reason to its action-guiding and motivational role; rather,
practical reason remains practical in the full sense of the term
even when its exercise does not immediately concern the guidance of
our present actions. To elucidate why this wider scope of practical
reason is important, Kontos brings into the foreground five
protagonists that have long been overlooked: (a) spectators or
judges who make non-motivational judgments about practical matters
that do not interact with their present deliberations and actions;
(b) legislators who exercise practical reason to establish
constitutions and laws; (c) hopes as an active engagement with
moral luck and its impact on our individual lives; (d) prayers as
legislators' way to deal with the moral luck hovering around the
birth of constitutions and the prospect of a utopia; and (e) people
who are outsiders or marginal cases of the responsibility community
because they are totally deprived of practical reason. Building on
a wide range of interpretations of Aristotle's practical philosophy
(from the ancient commentators to contemporary analytic and
continental philosophers), Kontos offers new insights about
Aristotle's philosophical contribution to the current debates about
radical evil, moral luck, hope, utopia, internalism and
externalism, and the philosophy of law. Aristotle on the Scope of
Practical Reason will appeal to researchers and advanced students
interested in Aristotle's ethics, ancient philosophy, and the
history of practical philosophy.
This new edition introduces the reader to the philosophy of early
Christianity in the second to fourth centuries AD, and
contextualizes the philosophical contributions of early Christians
in the framework of the ancient philosophical debates. It examines
the first attempts of Christian thinkers to engage with issues such
as questions of cosmogony and first principles, freedom of choice,
concept formation, and the body-soul relation, as well as later
questions like the status of the divine persons of the Trinity. It
also aims to show that the philosophy of early Christianity is part
of ancient philosophy as a distinct school of thought, being in
constant dialogue with the ancient philosophical schools, such as
Platonism, Aristotelianism, Stoicism, and even Epicureanism and
Scepticism. This book examines in detail the philosophical views of
Christian thinkers such as Justin Martyr, Clement of Alexandria,
Irenaeus, Tertullian, Origen, Basil, and Gregory of Nyssa, and
sheds light in the distinct ways they conceptualized traditional
philosophical issues and made some intriguing contributions. The
book's core chapters survey the central philosophical concerns of
the early Christian thinkers and examines their contributions.
These range across natural philosophy, metaphysics, logic and
epistemology, psychology, and ethics, and include such questions as
how the world came into being, how God relates to the world, the
status of matter, how we can gain knowledge, in what sense humans
have freedom of choice, what the nature of soul is and how it
relates to the body, and how we can attain happiness and salvation.
This revised edition takes into account the recent developments in
the area of later ancient philosophy, especially in the philosophy
of Early Christianity, and integrates them in the relevant
chapters, some of which are now heavily expanded. The Philosophy of
Early Christianity remains a crucial introduction to the subject
for undergraduate and postgraduate students of ancient philosophy
and early Christianity, across the disciplines of classics,
history, and theology.
Accompanied by a new translation of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics
X, this volume presents a hybrid between a traditional commentary
and a scholarly monograph. Aristotle's text is divided into one
hundred lemmata which not only explore comprehensively the content
and strength of each of these units of thought, but also emphasise
their continuity, showing how the smaller units feed into the
larger structure. The Commentary illuminates what Aristotle thinks
in each lemma (and why), and also shows how he thinks. In order to
bring Aristotle alive as a thinker, it often explores several
possible ways of reading the text to enable the reader to make up
their own mind about the best interpretation of a given passage.
The relevant background in Plato's dialogues is discussed, and a
substantial Introduction sets out the philosophical framework
necessary for understanding Book X, the final and most arresting
section of the Ethics.
Aristotle is a rarity in the history of philosophy and science - he
is a towering figure in the history of both disciplines. Moreover,
he devoted a great deal of philosophical attention to the nature of
scientific knowledge. How then do his philosophical reflections on
scientific knowledge impact his actual scientific inquiries? In
this book James Lennox sets out to answer this question. He argues
that Aristotle has a richly normative view of scientific inquiry,
and that those norms are of two kinds: a general, question-guided
framework applicable to all scientific inquiries, and
domain-specific norms reflecting differences in the target of
inquiry and in the means of observation available to researchers.
To see these norms of inquiry in action, the second half of this
book examines Aristotle's investigations of animals, the soul,
material compounds, the motions of heavenly bodies, and
respiration.
The present work has three principal objectives: (1) to fix the
chronology of the development of the pre-Euclidean theory of
incommensurable magnitudes beginning from the first discoveries by
fifth-century Pythago reans, advancing through the achievements of
Theodorus of Cyrene, Theaetetus, Archytas and Eudoxus, and
culminating in the formal theory of Elements X; (2) to correlate
the stages of this developing theory with the evolution of the
Elements as a whole; and (3) to establish that the high standards
of rigor characteristic of this evolution were intrinsic to the
mathematicians' work. In this third point, we wish to
counterbalance a prevalent thesis that the impulse toward
mathematical rigor was purely a response to the dialecticians'
critique of foundations; on the contrary, we shall see that not
until Eudoxus does there appear work which may be described as
purely foundational in its intent. Through the examination of these
problems, the present work will either alter or set in a new light
virtually every standard thesis about the fourth-century Greek
geometry. I. THE PRE-EUCLIDEAN THEORY OF INCOMMENSURABLE MAGNITUDES
The Euclidean theory of incommensurable magnitudes, as preserved in
Book X of the Elements, is a synthetic masterwork. Yet there are
detect able seams in its structure, seams revealed both through
terminology and through the historical clues provided by the
neo-Platonist commentator Proclus."
All disciplines can count on a noble founder, and the
representation of this founder as an authority is key in order to
construe a discipline's identity. This book sheds light on how
Plato and other authorities were represented in one of the most
long-lasting traditions of all time. It leads the reader through
exegesis and polemics, recovery of the past and construction of a
philosophical identity. From Xenocrates to Proclus, from the
sceptical shift to the re-establishment of dogmatism, from the
Mosaic of the Philosophers to the Neoplatonist Commentaries, the
construction of authority emerges as a way of access to the core of
the Platonist tradition.
|
You may like...
Republic
Plato
Paperback
R95
R76
Discovery Miles 760
|