|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Western philosophy, c 500 to c 1600 > General
The conventional opposition of scholastic Aristotelianism and
humanistic science has been increasingly questioned in recent
years, and in these articles William Wallace aims to demonstrate
that a progressive Aristotelianism in fact provided the foundation
for Galileo's scientific discoveries. The first series of articles
supply much of the documentary evidence that has led the author to
the sources for Galileo's early notebooks: they show how Galileo,
while teaching or preparing to teach at Pisa, actually appropriated
much of his material from Jesuit lectures given at the Collegio
Romano in 1598-90. The next articles then trace a number of key
elements in Galileo's later work, mainly relating to logical
methodology and natural philosophy, back to sources in medieval
Aristotelian thought, notably in the writings of Albert the Great
and Thomas Aquinas. La mise en opposition conventionnelle entre
l'aristotelisme scolastique et la science humaniste a ete de plus
en plus remise en question durant les dernieres annees. Tout au
long de ces articles, William Wallace tente de demontrer que
l'aristotelisme progressif a en fait pourvu le fondement des
decouvertes scientifiques de Galilee. Le premier groupe d'articles
fournit la plupart des preuves documentees qui ont mene l'auteur
aux sources des premiers cahiers de notes de Galilee; on y voit
comment celui-ci, alors qu'il enseignait, ou s'apprAtait A
enseigner A Pise, s'etait en fait approprie quantite de donnees
issues de cours magistraux jesuites qui avaient ete donnes au
Collegio Romano entre 1588 et 90. Les etudes suivantes retracent A
leur tour un certain nombre d'elements-clef des travaux ulterieurs
de Galilee, se rapportant plus particulierement A la methodologie
logique et a la philosophie naturelle, jusqu'A leurs sources dans
la pensee aristotelicienne du Moyen Age, notamment dans les ecrits
d'Albert le Grand et de Thomas d'Aquin.
Drawing on the work of Georg Misch, this work seeks to give back to
the Word its original fullness of meaning. Misch's notion of a
logic of life considers the Word in the plenitude of its great
powers. The question of life leads the inquiries undertaken in this
study via Misch's anthropological conception on to the
phenomenological ontology of Martin Heidegger and Josef Koenig's
investigation of 'Being and Thought'. Heidegger's quest for the
meaning of Being calls for a close inspection of its linguistic
foundation. 'Being' reveals itself as the original truth. It is the
verbum demonstrativum in its verbal form. Solely to Indo-European
languages is this form immanent. Thus, the established basis may be
the starting point from which to reconsider the question of
tradition as well as constructs of higher levels.
'This sentence is false' - is that true? The 'Liar paradox'
embodied in those words exerted a particular fascination on the
logicians of the Western later Middle Ages, and, along with similar
'insoluble' problems, forms the subject of the first group of
articles in this volume. In the following parts Professor Spade
turns to medieval semantic theory, views on the relationship
between language and thought, and to a study of one particular
genre of disputation, that known as 'obligationes'. The focus is on
the Oxford scholastics of the first half of the 14th century, and
it is the name of William of Ockham which dominates these pages - a
thinker with whom Professor Spade finds himself in considerable
philosophical sympathy, and whose work on logic and semantic theory
has a depth and richness that have not always been sufficiently
appreciated.
In this classic work the author undertakes to show how Spinoza's
philosophical ideas, particularly his political ideas, were
influenced by his underlying emotional responses to the conflicts
of his time. It thus differs form most professional philosophical
analyses of the philosophy of Spinoza. The author identifies and
discusses three periods in the development of Spinoza's thought and
shows how they were reactions to the religious, political and
economic developments in the Netherlands at the time. In his first
period, Spinoza reacted very strongly to the competitive capitalism
of the Amsterdam Jews whose values were "so thoroughly pervaded by
an economic ethics that decrees the stock exchange approached in
dignity the decrees of God," and of the ruling classes of
Amsterdam, and was led out only to give up his business activities
but also to throw in his lot with the Utopian groups of the day. In
his second period, Spinoza developed serious doubts about the
practicality of such idealistic movements and became a "mature
political partisan" of Dutch liberal republicanism. The collapse of
republicanism and the victory of the royalist party brought further
disillusionment. Having become more reserved concerning democratic
processes, and having decided that "every form of government could
be made consistent with the life of free men," Spinoza devoted his
time and efforts to deciding what was essential to any form of
government which would make such a life possible. In his carefully
crafted introduction to this new edition, Lewis Feuer responds to
his critics, and reviews Spinoza's worldview in the light of the
work of later scientists sympathetic to this own basic standpoint.
He reviews Spinoza's arguments for the ethical and political
contributions of the principle of determinism, and examines how
these have guided, and at times frustrated, students and scholars
of the social and physical sciences who have sought to understand
and advance these disciplines.
Marsilio Ficino (1433-1499), the Florentine
scholar-philosopher-magus, was largely responsible for the
Renaissance revival of Plato. The publication of his Latin
translations of the dialogues in 1484 was an intellectual event of
the first magnitude, making the Platonic canon accessible to
western Europe after the passing of a millennium and establishing
Plato as an authority for Renaissance thought. This volume contains
Ficino's extended analysis and commentary on the "Phaedrus," which
he explicates as a meditation on "beauty in all its forms" and a
sublime work of theology. In the commentary on the "Ion," Ficino
explores a poetics of divine inspiration that leads to the
Neoplatonist portrayal of the soul as a rhapsode whose song is an
ascent into the mind of God. Both works bear witness to Ficino's
attempt to revive a Christian Platonism and what might be called an
Orphic Christianity.
This second edition concentrates on various philosophers and
theologians from the medieval Arabian, Jewish, and Christian
worlds. It principally centers on authors such as Abumashar,
Saadiah Gaon and Alcuin from the eighth century and follows the
intellectual developments of the three traditions up to the
fifteenth-century Ibn Khaldun, Hasdai Crescas and Marsilio Ficino.
The spiritual journeys presuppose earlier human sources, such as
the philosophy of Plato, Aristotle, Plotinus, and Porphyry and
various Stoic authors, the revealed teachings of the Jewish Law,
the Koran and the Christian Bible. The Fathers of the Church, such
as St. Augustine and Gregory the Great, provided examples of
theology in their attempts to reconcile revealed truth and man's
philosophical knowledge and deserve attention as pre-medieval
contributors to medieval intellectual life. Avicenna and Averroes,
Maimonides and Gersonides, St. Thomas Aquinas and St. Bonaventure,
stand out in the three traditions as special medieval contributors
who deserve more attention. This second edition of Historical
Dictionary of Medieval Philosophy and Theology contains a
chronology, an introduction, appendixes, and an extensive
bibliography. The dictionary section has over 300 cross-referenced
entries on important persons, events, and concepts that shaped
medieval philosophy and theology. This book is an excellent
resource for students, researchers, and anyone wanting to know more
about medieval philosophy and theology.
This new introduction replaces Marenbon's best-selling editions
Early Medieval Philosophy (1983) and Later Medieval Philosophy
(1987) to present a single authoritative and comprehensive study of
the period. It gives a lucid and engaging account of the history of
philosophy in the Middle Ages, discussing the main writers and
ideas, the social and intellectual contexts, and the important
concepts used in medieval philosophy. Medieval Philosophy gives a
chronological account which: treats all four main traditions of
philosophy that stem from the Greek heritage of late antiquity:
Greek Christian philosophy, Latin philosophy, Arabic philosophy and
Jewish philosophy provides a series of 'study' sections for close
attention to arguments and shorter 'interludes' that point to the
wider questions of the intellectual context combines philosophical
analysis with historical background includes a helpful detailed
guide to further reading and an extensive bibliography All students
of medieval philosophy, medieval history, theology or religion will
find this necessary reading.
This book maps the entire development of Comenius's considerations
on man, from his earliest writings to his philosophical masterwork.
Although this book primarily offers an analysis and description of
the conception of man in Comenius's work, it may also serve the
reader as a more general introduction to his philosophical
conception. The author shows that, in spite of the fact that
Comenius has received no small amount of academic attention, funded
studies or monographs in English language remain in single figures.
Thus, a range of Comenius's remarkable ideas are still unknown to
the wider public.
A timely examination of the ways in which sixteenth-century
understandings of the world were framed by classical theory. The
long sixteenth century saw a major shift in European geographical
understanding: in the space of little more than a hundred years
Western Europeans moved to see the world as a place in which all
parts of the sphere were made by God for human exploitation and to
interact with one another. Taking such a scenario as its historical
backdrop, Framing the Early Modern World examines the influence of
Greek and Roman ideas on the formulation of new geographical
theories in sixteenth-century western Europe. While discussions of
inhabitability dominate the geographical literature throughout the
sixteenth century, humanist geographers of the sixteenth century,
trained in Greek and Roman writings, found in them the key
intellectual tools which allowed the oikoumene (the habitable
world) to be redefined as a globally-connected world. In this
world, all parts of the sphere were designed to be in communication
with one another. The coincidence of the Renaissance and the period
of European exploration enabled a new geographical understanding
fashioned as much by classical theory as by early modern empirical
knowledge. Newly discovered lands could then be defined, exploited
and colonized. In this way, the author argues, the seeds of the
modern era of colonization, expansionism and ultimately
globalization were sown. Framing the Early Modern World is a timely
work, contributing to a growing discourse on the origins of
globalization and the roots of modernity.
This book analyses the process of development of Byzantine thought,
which carries original solutions to fundamental philosophical
questions and an original understanding of the world and humanity.
The author defines the contents and characteristics of Byzantine
philosophy, discusses the most important factors of its development
as well as the role of Greco-Roman world and the place of Christian
thinkers in this process. He also takes into consideration the
Alexandrian school and the School of Antioch, the relationship
between Byzantine philosophy and Greek Patristics and the attempts
to restore the Byzantine neptic thought after the fall of
Constantinople. The study is based on Byzantine sources, written in
Greek.
Tackling the question of why medieval philosophy matters in the
current age, Stephen Boulter issues a passionate and robust defence
of this school in the history of ideas. He examines both familiar
territory and neglected texts and thinkers whilst also asking the
question of why, exactly, this matters or should matter to how we
think now. Why Medieval Philosophy is also provides a introduction
to medieval philosophy more generally exploring how this area of
philosophy has been received, debated and, sometimes, dismissed in
the history of philosophy.
In the late 1960s, a whole pantheon of thinkers regarding
themselves as radicals stole a part of the anarchic praxis of late
capitalism, turned it into philosophy, and with the resulting set
of views turned against the foundations of the system in a
purportedly radical gesture. Postmodernism was the name for the
superficially revolutionary culture which then came into existence.
The thought of the late left appears as the subsequent response to
the cunning of the system. The main figures of Farewell to
Postmodernism are Perry Anderson, David Harvey, Fredric Jameson,
Terry Eagleton and Slavoj Zizek. The book provides an encyclopaedic
introduction to their work, while at the same time seeking to grasp
the current trajectory of radical thought.
It is commonly supposed that certain elements of medieval
philosophy are uncharacteristically preserved in modern
philosophical thought through the idea that mental phenomena are
distinguished from physical phenomena by their intentionality,
their intrinsic directedness toward some object. The many
exceptions to this presumption, however, threaten its viability.
This volume explores the intricacies and varieties of the
conceptual relationships medieval thinkers developed among
intentionality, cognition, and mental representation. Ranging from
Aquinas, Scotus, Ockham, and Buridan through less-familiar writers,
the collection sheds new light on the various strands that run
between medieval and modern thought and bring us to a number of
fundamental questions in the philosophy of mind as it is conceived
today.
Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy showcases the best scholarly
research in this flourishing field. The series covers all aspects
of medieval philosophy, including the Latin, Arabic, and Hebrew
traditions, and runs from the end of antiquity into the
Renaissance. It publishes new work by leading scholars in the
field, and combines historical scholarship with philosophical
acuteness. The papers will address a wide range of topics, from
political philosophy to ethics, and logic to metaphysics. OSMP is
an essential resource for anyone working in the area.
|
You may like...
Quantum City
Ayssar Arida
Paperback
R1,441
Discovery Miles 14 410
|